Skip to main content
Log in

Evidence based methodology: a naturalistic analysis of epistemic policies in regulatory science

  • Paper in Philosophy of Science in Practice
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we argue for a naturalistic solution to some of the methodological controversies in regulatory science, on the basis of two case studies: toxicology (risk assessment) and health claim regulation (benefit assessment). We analyze the debates related to the scientific evidence that is considered necessary for regulatory decision making in each of those two fields, with a particular attention to the interactions between scientific and regulatory aspects. This analysis allows us to identify two general stances in the debate: a) one that argues for more permissive standards of evidence and for methodological pluralism, and b) an opposing one that not only defends strict evidence requirements but also stipulates the use of one particular (or at most a few) scientific methodologies for data generation. We argue that the real-world outcomes produced by alternative regulatory options are a vital piece of information that allows for the empirical assessment of these two stances. In particular, this information on outcomes makes it possible to analyze which standards of evidence and scientific methods generate the most useful knowledge as input for regulatory decision making. Our conclusion is that instead of an a priori selection of methodologies and standards, such decisions ought to be based on empirical evidence related to real-world outcomes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, cognitive psychology, history of science, biology, etc. Different naturalisms use different scientific disciplines as a basis.

  2. Some of those methods for causal analysis are: quasi-experimental design, causal network models, conditional independence tests, and marginal structural models.

  3. Causality is understood here as INUS (insufficient but necessary part of an unnecessary but sufficient) conditions.

  4. The hierarchies of evidence established on the basis of standards of proof may refer to the scientific evidence itself (data), but also to the methods used for obtaining this evidence (Illari and Russo 2014). Often they are hierarchies of methodologies, and only indirectly of the generated evidence.

  5. Mechanistic studies allow for the identification of the mechanisms and biological pathways by which a food ingredient produces the desired positive health effects.

  6. In general, a weight-of-evidence analysis is based on the assessment of evidence from different sources, meaning different lines of research, methodologies for data generation, and so on. The basic idea is that while the evidence from one single line of research will not be sufficient to be able to accept or reject a particular hypothesis, taking all the evidence together would be sufficient because the different lines of research support each other (Haack 2008, 2014). The concept of weight-of-evidence is used in environmental studies, toxicology, nutrition and other scientific fields to designate the combination of multiple lines of evidence during an analysis in order to reach a conclusion (Weed 2005). The complexity inherent in joining up evidence from very different sources, as well as varying types and qualities has led to multiple ways of interpreting WOE analyses from a philosophical standpoint (evidence amalgamation: Landes, Osimani and Poellinger 2018; Fletcher, Landes, and Poellinger 2019).

References

  • Andreoletti, M., & Teira, D. (2019). Rules versus standards: What are the costs of epistemic norms in drug regulation? Science, Technology and Human Values, 44(6), 1093–1115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bast, A., Briggs, W., Calabrese, E., Fenech, M., Hanecamp, J., Heaney, R., Rijkers, G., Schwitters, B., & Verhoeven, P. (2013). Scientism, legalism and precaution—Contending with regulation nutrition and health claims in Europe. EFFL, 6, 401–409.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biesalski, H. K., et al. (2011). 26th Hohenheim consensus conference, September 11, 2010 scientific substantiation of health claims: Evidence-based nutrition. Nutrition, 27, S1–S20.

  • Canali, S. (2019). Evaluating evidential pluralism in epidemiology: Mechanistic evidence in exposome research. HPLS., 41, 4. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-019-0241-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N., & Hardie, J. (2013). Evidence-based policy: A practical guide to doing it better. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N., & Stegenga, J. (2011). A theory of evidence for evidence-based policy. In W. Twining, P. Dawid, & D. Vasilaki (Eds.), Evidence, inference and enquiry (pp. 291–322). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clewell, H. (2005). Use of mode of action in risk assessment: Past, present, and future. Regulatory Toxicology and Pharmacology, 42, 3–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cox, L. A. (2013). Improving causal inferences in risk analysis. Risk Analysis, 33(10), 1762–1771.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cox, L. A. (2015). Breakthroughs in decision science and risk analysis. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons, Inc..

    Google Scholar 

  • Cranor, C. (1993). Regulating toxic substances. A philosophy of science and the law. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cranor, C. (1995). The social benefits of expedited risk assessment. Risk Analysis, 15(4), 353–358.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cranor, C. (2011). Legally poisoned. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cranor, C. (2017). Tragic failures: How and why we are harmed by toxic chemicals. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2000). Inductive risk and values in science. Philosophy of Science, 67, 559–579.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2009). Science, policy, and the value-free ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • EFSA. (2009). Technical report: Briefing document for member states and European Commission on the evaluation of article 13.1 health claims. EFSA Journal, 7(1386), 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • EFSA. (2010). Guidance on human health risk benefit assessment of foods. Tabiano: EFSA.

    Google Scholar 

  • EFSA. (2011). Scientific and technical guidance for the preparation and presentation of an application for authorisation of a health claim (revision 1). EFSA Journal, 9(2170), 1–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. (2011). Is a little pollution good for you? Incorporating societal values in environmental research. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, S. C., Landes, J., & Poellinger, R. (2019). Evidence amalgamation in the sciences: An introduction. Synthese, 196, 3163–3188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, S. (2000). The governance of science. Buckingham: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1985). Philosophy of science naturalized. Philosophy of Science, 52(3), 331–356.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1998). Naturalized philosophy of science. In Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D. (2011). The Russo–Williamson thesis and the question of whether smoking causes heart disease. In P. Illari, F. Russo, & J. Williamson (Eds.), Causality in the sciences (pp. 110–125). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. (2008). Proving causation: The holism of warrant and the atomism of Daubert. Journal of Health & Biomedical Law, 4, 253–289.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. (2014). Evidence matters. Science, proof, and truth in the law. New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Hansson, S. O. (2020). Values in pharmacology. In A. LaCaze & B. Osimani (Eds.), Uncertainty in pharmacology. Epistemology, methods, and decisions (pp. 375–396). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harremoës, P., et al. (Eds.). (2002). The precautionary principle in the twentieth century: Late lessons from early warnings. London: Earthscan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heaney, R. (2008). Nutrients, endpoints, and the problem of proof. Journal of Nutrition, 8(138), 1591–1595.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heesen, R., Bright, L. K., & Zucker, A. (2019). Vindicating methodological triangulation. Synthese, 196, 3067–3081.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendrickx, K. (2013). Rivaling evidence-bases and politics in regulatory science. Food, Science & Law, vol. 4, Http://hdl.handle.net/2268/162196

  • Hill, A. B. (1965). The environment and disease: Association or causation? Proceedings of the Royal Society of Medicine, 58(5), 295–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Illari, P., & Russo, F. (2014). Causality: Philosophical theory meets scientific practice. Oxford University Press.

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krewski, D., Andersen, M. E., Mantus, E., & Zeise, L. (2009). Toxicity testing in the 21st century: Implications for human health risk assessment. Risk Analysis, 29, 474–479.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landes, J., Osimani, B., & Poellinger, R. (2018). Epistemology of causal inference in pharmacology. Euro Jnl Phil Sci, 8, 3–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1987). Progress or rationality? The prospects for normative naturalism. American Philosophical Quarterly, 24, 19–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1990). Normative naturalism. Philosophy of Science, 57, 44–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lave, L. B., & Omenn, G. S. (1986). Cost-effectiveness of short-term test for carcinogenicity. Nature, 324(6092), 29–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leuridan, B., & Weber, E. (2011). The IARC and mechanistic evidence. In P. M. Illari, F. Russo, & J. Williamson (Eds.), Causality in the sciences (pp. 91–109). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1990). Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luján, J. L., & Todt, O. (2015). The role of values in methodological controversies: The case of risk assessment. Philosophia Scientiae, 19(1), 45–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luján, J. L., & Todt, O. (2018). The dilemmas of science for policy. EMBO Reports, 19(2), 194–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luján, J. L., & Todt, O. (2020). Standards of evidence and causality in regulatory science: Risk and benefit assessment. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 80(April), 82–89. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2019.05.005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayo, D., & Miller, J. (2008). The error statistical philosopher as normative naturalist. Synthese, 163, 305–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Osimani, B. (2014). Safety vs. efficacy assessment of pharmaceuticals: Epistemological rationales and methods. Preventive Medicine Reports, 1, 9–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Osimani, B. (2020). Epistemic gains and epistemic games: Reliability and higher order evidence in medicine and pharmacology. In A. LaCaze & B. Osimani (Eds.), Uncertainty in pharmacology. Epistemology, methods, and decisions (pp. 345–372). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, J. (2015). A pragmatist theory of evidence. Philosophy of Science, 82(3), 341–362.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, K. (1989). Scientific progress and models of justification. In Goldman (Ed.), Science, technology, and social progress (pp. 196–226). Bethlehem: Lehigh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, K. (1991). Risk and rationality: Philosophical foundations for populist reforms. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, K. (1994). Ethics of scientific research. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2001). Social empiricism. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steel, D. (2015). Philosophy and the precautionary principle: Science, evidence, and environmental policy, Cambridge University Press.

  • Stegenga, J. (2014). Down with the hierarquies. Topoi, 33, 313–322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. (2002). Risk and reason: Safety, law, and the environment, Cambridge university press.

  • Teira, D. (2020). On the normative foundations of pharmaceutical regulation. In A. LaCaze & B. Osimani (Eds.), Uncertainty in pharmacology. Epistemology, methods, and decisions (pp. 417–437). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Todt, O., & Luján, J. L. (2017). Health claims and methodological controversy in nutrition science. Risk Analysis, 37(5), 958–968.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vandenbroucke, J. P., Broadbent, A., & Pearce, N. (2016). Causality and causal inference in epidemiology: The need for a pluralistic approach. International Journal of Epidemiology, 2016, 1776–1786.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verhagen, H., Robinson, T., Gallani, B., Hugas, M., Kleiner., J., Hardy, A., & Devos, Y. (2019). EFSA’s third scientific conference ‘science, food, Society’: concluding remarks. EFSA Journal, 17. https://doi.org/10.2903/j.efsa.2019.e170723.

  • Weed, D. (2005). Weight of evidence. Risk Analysis, 25, 1545–1155.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank for their financial support: European Commission European Regional Development Fund (FEDER)/ Spanish Ministry for Science, Innovation and Universities – State Research Agency (AEI)/ Research Project “Estándares de prueba y elecciones metodólogicas en la fundamentación científica de las declaraciones de salud”, FFI2017-83543-P.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to José Luis Luján.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Luján, J.L., Todt, O. Evidence based methodology: a naturalistic analysis of epistemic policies in regulatory science. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 11, 26 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-020-00340-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-020-00340-7

Keywords

Navigation