Skip to main content
Log in

A Philosophical Path from Königsberg to Kyoto

The Science of the Infinite and the Philosophy of Nothingness

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Mathematics is the science of the infinite, its goal the symbolic comprehension of the infinite with human, that is finite, means.’ Along this line, in The Open World, Hermann Weyl contrasted the desire to make the infinite accessible through finite processes, which underlies any theoretical investigation of reality, with the intuitive feeling for the infinite ‘peculiar to the Orient,’ which remains ‘indifferent to the concrete manifold of reality.’ But a critical analysis may acknowledge a valuable dialectical opposition. Struggling to spell out the infinity of real numbers mathematicians come to see the active role of emptiness. Pondering over the essence of self-awareness, the Japanese philosopher Nishida Kitarō comes to see the ‘place’ where it abides as absolute nothingness. Thus, the two ways of seeing coalesce into a perspective in which infinity and nothingness mirror each other.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For more, see in particular Kemp (1990).

  2. For a thorough analysis, see Friedman (2012).

  3. In his Geometrie der Lage (Nürnberg 1847).

  4. For more, see Stillwell (2018), pp. 14–16.

  5. See My Philosophical Path (1939), in Yusa (2002), p. 301.

  6. For an insightful discussion, see Ghilardi (2009).

  7. For a deeper analysis, see Maraldo (2006).

  8. For more, see Yusa (2002), p. 203.

  9. Aristotle De anima 429A 27–29; quoted in Nishida (2012), p. 6.

  10. For an insightful discussion, see Tremblay (2000).

  11. For more details, see Dalissier (2008).

  12. ‘Here I made the point of departure of my philosophy’ (Nishida 1987b, p. 67).

  13. For more details, see Stillwell (2013), p. 82.

  14. On the origin of zero and the logic of the Prajnaparamitra Sutra, see Matsuo (1987).

  15. In contrast with the measure argument for the uncountability of real numbers (mentioned above), Cantor constructed a real number x unequal to each member of a given countable set S = {x1, x2, x3, x4, ...} of real numbers (and therefore, not in S). For more details, see Stillwell (2013), pp. 70–72.

  16. For a thoughtful analysis, see Weyl (2009).

  17. See, in particular, Nishida (1995). For more, see Jacinto Zavala (2018).

  18. Cf. Yukawa (1973), pp. 78–84. For more on Epicurus’ concepts of void and spatiality, see Martini (2018).

  19. On the issues of quantum vacuum, gravity, and space-time, see, among others: Barrow (2000), Isham (1994), Yukawa (1973).

References

  • Alberti, L. B. (2004). On painting [1435]. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrow, J. D. (2000). The book of nothing. Vacuum, voids, and the latest ideas about the origins of the universe. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernays, P. (1998). Hilbert's significance for the philosophy of mathematics. In P. Mancosu (Ed.), From Brouwer to Hilbert (pp. 189–198). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cantor, G. (1874). On a property of the set of real algebraic numbers. In W. Ewald (Ed.), From Kant to Hilbert (Vol. 2, pp. 839–843). Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Cassirer, E. (1957). The philosophy of symbolic forms (Vol. 3). New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer, E. (1963). The individual and the Cosmos in renaissance philosophy. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cusanus, N. (1985). On learned ignorance. Minneapolis, MN: The Arthur J. Banning Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dalissier, M. (2008). La topologie philosophique. Un essai d’introduction à Nishida Kitarō. Archives de Philosophie, 4, 631–668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dedekind, R. (1872). Continuity and irrational numbers. In W. Ewald (Ed.), From Kant to Hilbert (Vol. 2, pp. 766–779). Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Dedekind, R. (1888). Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? In W. Ewald (Ed.), From Kant to Hilbert (Vol. 2, pp. 790–833). Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Frege, G. (1980). Philosophical and mathematical correspondence. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2012). Kant on geometry and spatial intuition. Synthese, 186, 231–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghilardi, M. (2009). Una logica del vedere. Estetica ed etica nel pensiero di Nishida Kitarō. Milano: Mimesis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heisig, J. W. (2001). Philosophers of nothingness. Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. (1918). Axiomatic thought. In W. Ewald (Ed.), From Kant to Hilbert (Vol. 2, pp. 1105–1115). Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Hilbert, D. (1930). Logic and the knowledge of nature. In W. Ewald (Ed.), From Kant to Hilbert (Vol. 2, pp. 1157–1165). Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Hilbert, D. (1967). On the infinite. In J. van Heijenoort (Ed.), From Frege to Gödel (pp. 367–392). Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D., & Cohn-Vossen, S. (1952). Geometry and the imagination. New York: Chelsea Pub. Co..

    Google Scholar 

  • Isham, C. J. (1994). Prima facie questions in quantum gravity. In J. Ehlers & H. Friedrich (Eds.), Canonical relativity: Classical and quantum (pp. 1–21). Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacinto Zavala, A. (2018). El camino de Nishida Kitarō hacia una fundamentación filosófica de las matemáticas. Modernos & Contemporaneos, 2, 75–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998). Critique of Pure Reason, first (A) and second (B) editions [1781/1787]. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kemp, M. (1990). The science of art. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. W. (1840). Préceptes pour avancer les sciences. In J. E. Erdmann (Ed.), Leibnitii opera omnia. Berlin.

  • Leibniz, G. W. (1989). Philosophical essays. Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maraldo, J. C. (2006). Self-mirroring and self-awareness: Dedekind, Royce, and Nishida. In J. W. Heisig (Ed.), Frontiers of Japanese philosophy 1. Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture: Nagoya.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martini, C. (2018). Void and spatiality in Epicurus’ letter to Herodotus. BPhil Thesis, Oxford University.

  • Matsuo, H. (1987). The logic of Unity. The discovery of zero and emptiness in Prajnaparamita thought. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (1973). Art and morality. Honolulu: East-West Center Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (1987a). Intuition and reflection in self-consciousness. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (1987b). Nothingness and the religious worldview. Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (1995). Fundamentación filosófica de las matemática. In A. Jacinto Zavala (Ed.), Textos de la filosofía japonesa moderna. El Colegio de Michoacán: Mich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (2001). Nishida Kitarō Zenshū [collected works of Nishida Kitarō] (Vol. 13). Tokyo: Iwanami.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (2003). Compréhension logique et compréhension mathématique. Ebisu, 31, 115–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (2012). Basho. In J. W. M. Krummel & S. Nagatomo (Eds.), Place and dialectic: Two essays by Nishida Kitarō (pp. 1–129). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida, K. (2015). De ce qui agit à ce qui voit. Montréal: Les Presses de l’Université de Montréal.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sieg, W. (2014). The ways of Hilbert’s Axiomatics: Structural and formal. Perspectives on Science, 22(1), 133–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stillwell, J. (2005). The four pillars of geometry. Springer.

  • Stillwell, J. (2010). Roads to infinity. Natick MA: AK Peters Ltd..

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stillwell, J. (2013). The real numbers. Springer.

  • Stillwell, J. (2018). Reverse mathematics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Suzuki, D. (1964). An introduction to Zen Buddhism. New York: Grove Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tremblay, J. (2000). Nishida Kitarō: le jeu de l’individuel et de l’universel. Paris: CNRS Ed.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. (2009). The open world. In P. Persic (Ed.), Mind and nature (pp. 34–82). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Yukawa, H. (1973). Creativity and intuition. A physicist looks at east and west. Tokyo, New York & San Francisco: Kodansha International Ltd..

    Google Scholar 

  • Yukawa, H. (1982). Tabibito (the traveler). Singapore: World Scientific.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Yusa, M. (2002). Zen & Philosophy. An intellectual biography of Nishida Kitarō. Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Agustín Jacinto Zavala, Masato Mitsuda, and Jacynthe Tremblay for reading an earlier draft of this article, and John Stillwell for corrections and helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rossella Lupacchini.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lupacchini, R. A Philosophical Path from Königsberg to Kyoto. SOPHIA 60, 851–868 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-020-00776-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-020-00776-7

Keywords

Navigation