Skip to main content
Log in

Misattribution of agency in schizophrenia: An exploration of historical first-person accounts

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper provides a concise description and discussion of bottom–up and top–down approaches to misattribution of agency in schizophrenia. It explores if first-person accounts of passivity phenomena can provide support for one of these approaches. The focus is on excerpts in which the writers specifically examine their experiences of external influence. None of the accounts provides arguments that fit easily with only one of the possible approaches, which is in line with current attempts to theoretical integration.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Wittgenstein (1958) already noted that it is nonsensical to ask whether someone can be wrong in identifying the person referred to with “I” in statements like “I try to lift my arm.” Shoemaker (1968) called this immunity to error through misidentification relative to the first-person pronoun and Campbell (1999) argued that reports of passivity phenomena directly challenge this principle. For a discussion of whether these reports really challenge the immunity principle see Gallagher (2000) and Zahavi (1999, p. 153–156).

  2. A phenomenological approach informed by neuroscience, see Gallagher and Varela (2003).

  3. On a closer look, Frith’s theory can be considered a hybrid one since it also involves the failure of sub-personal (neuronal, bottom-up) processes which give rise to the unusual experience of passivity of one’s own actions (Gallagher 2004b, p.13).

  4. In a similar vein, Campbell (2002) has argued that both an empiricist and a rationalist account of the Capgras and Cotard delusions can possibly be rejected in favour of another common cause (depression) of both the delusional belief and the affectless perception.

  5. Carman (2005, p.50) writes: “Merleau-Ponty’s interconnected critiques of empiricism and intellectualism run like a double helix through the pages of Phenomenology of Perception. … As a result, although the current state of play in the philosophy of mind for us today differs widely from what it was for Merleau-Ponty in the middle of the last century, neither would he find it altogether unrecognizable.”

  6. Read (2001) questions whether Sass really succeeds in making schizophrenia understandable. Sass replies in Sass (2003).

  7. Note that what O’Brien describes seems to be the opposite from a hyper-rational attitude that Sass suggests to be important in schizophrenic experience. She actually claims not to be able to perform any intellectual work on her own; and what she does do, she ascribes to Something. Stephens and Graham suggest that a hyper-rational attitude can be a factor that plays a role in making it difficult for a person to keep track of her own intentions. Taking a hyper-rational attitude, they suggest, can make the idea one has of oneself elusive and less transparent.

  8. The selection of accounts is similarly biased as all writers had ‘literary qualities’ and were able to write in a nuanced way about their experience.

  9. Schreber (1903/2000, p.55) talks about compulsive thinking (which he in his text does attribute to the rays), Kandinsky (1881, p.457) writes about the first phase of his illness where there were no hallucinations yet, but “a richness of thoughts, their fast and simultaneously irregular paths, delusions and compulsive ideas.”

  10. Both Schreber (1903/2000, p.83) and Kandinsky (see discussion of his fragment) admit that there probably is something wrong with their nervous system. This does not seem to stop them from developing floridly delusional accounts. Lack of insight in psychosis is a well known and important feature of the disorder (Amador and David, 1998).

  11. The sincerity of these reports of psychotic experience is usually not doubted, see Davies and Coltheart (2000, p.1).

References

  • Amador, X., & David, A. (1998). Insight and psychosis. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (1999). Schizophrenia, the space of reasons, and thinking as a motor process. The Monist, 82(4), 609–626.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2002). Rationality, meaning and the analysis of delusion. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 8, 89–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carman, T. (2005). Sensation, judgement, and the phenomenal field. In T. Carman, & M. B. N. Hansen (Eds.) The Cambridge companion to Merleau-Ponty (pp. 50–73). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M., & Coltheart, M. (2000). Introduction: Pathologies of belief. Mind & Language, 15(1), 1–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. D. (1992). The cognitive neuropsychology of schizophrenia. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. D. (2004). Comments on Shaun Gallagher. Psychopathology, 37, 20–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2000). Self-reference and schizophrenia: A cognitive model of immunity to error through misidentification. In D. Zahavi (Ed.) Exploring the self: Philosophical and psychopathological perspectives on self-experience (pp. 203–239). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2004a). Agency, ownership, and alien control in schizophrenia. In P. Bovet, J. Parnas, & D. Zahavi (Eds.) Interdisciplinary perspectives on self-consciousness (pp. 89–104). Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2004b). Neurocognitive models of schizophrenia: a neurophenomenological critique. Psychopathology, 37, 8–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2007). The natural philosophy of agency. Philosophy Compass, 2(2), 347–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Varela, F. (2003). Redrawing the map and resetting the time: Phenomenology and the cognitive sciences. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 29, 93–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J., & Rosenberg, R. (2005). Unusual experiences, reality testing and delusions of alien control. Mind & Language, 20(2), 141–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers, K. (1962). General psychopathology. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M., Farrer, C., Franck, N., Fourneret, P., Posada, A., Daprati, E., et al. (2003). Action recognition in normal and schizophrenic subjects. In T. Kircher, & A. David (Eds.) The self in neuroscience and psychiatry (pp. 380–406). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kandinsky, V. (1881). Zur Lehre von den Hallucinationen. Archiv fur Psychiatrie und Nervenkrankheiten, 11, 453–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klosterkoetter, J. (1988). Basissymptome und endphaenomene der schizophrenie. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lang, J. (1938). The other side of hallucinations. American Journal of Psychiatry, 94, 1089–1097.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lerner, V., Kapstan, A., & Witzum, E. (2003). Kandinsky–Clerambault’s Syndrome: Concept of use for Western psychiatry. Israelian Journal of Psychiatry and Related Sciences, 40(1), 40–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lerner, V., & Witzum, E. (2003). Victor Kandinsky, MD: Psychiatrist, researcher and patient. History of Psychiatry, 14, 103–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, A. A. (1984). Was the “nervous illness” of Schreber a case of affective disorder? American Journal of Psychiatry, 141, 1236–1239.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maher, B. A. (1974). Delusional thinking and perceptual disorder. Journal of Individual Psychology, 30(1), 98–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mehler, B. (1988). A history of the American Eugenics Society. University of Illinois.

  • Mellor, C. S. (1970). First rank symptoms of schizophrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry, 117, 15–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945/2004). Phenomenology of perception (C. Smith, Trans.). London and New York: Routledge.

  • Minkowski, E. (1933/1995). Le temps vécu. Paris: Quadrige/Presses Universitaires de France.

  • O’Brien, B. (1958). Operators and things. The inner life of a schizophrenic. Cambridge: Arlington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, J. (2000). The self and intentionality in the pre-psychotic stages of schizophrenia: a phenomenological study. In D. Zahavi (Ed.) Exploring the self. Philosophical and psychopathological perspectives on self-experience (pp. 115–148). Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, J. (2003). Self and schizophrenia: a phenomenological perspective. In T. Kircher & A. David (Eds.), The self in neuroscience and psychiatry (pp. 217–241). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Read, R. (2001). On approaching schizophrenia through Wittgenstein. Philosophical Psychology, 14(4), 449–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rulf, S. (2003). Phenomenological contributions on schizophrenia: A critical review and commentary on the literature between 1980–2000. Journal of Phenomenological Psychology, 34(1), 1–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. A. (1994). The paradoxes of delusion. Wittgenstein, Schreber, and the schizophrenic mind. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. A. (2003). Incomprehensibility and understanding: On the interpretation of severe mental illness. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 10(2), 125–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schreber, D. P. (1903/2000). Memoirs of my nervous illness. (I. MacAlpine & R. A. Hunter, Trans.). New York: New York Review Books.

  • Shoemaker, S. (1968). Self-reference and self-awareness. The Journal of Philosophy, 65(19), 555–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sims, A. (2003). Symptoms in the mind. An introduction to descriptive psychopathology. (Third ed.): Saunders.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephens, G. L., & Graham, G. (2000). When self-consciousness breaks: Alien voices and inserted thoughts. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Synofzik, M., Vosgerau, G., & Newen, A. (2007). Beyond the comparator model: A multifactorial two-step account of agency. Consciousness and Cognition (in press). DOI 10.1016/j.concog.2007.03.010.

  • Thornton, T. (2004). Wittgenstein and the limits of empathic understanding in psychopathology. International Review of Psychiatry, 16(3), 216–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). The blue and brown books. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (1999). Self-awareness and alterity. A phenomenological investigation. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2003). Phenomenology of self. In The self in neuroscience and psychiatry (pp. 56–75). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to J. P. M. A. Maes.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Maes, J.P.M.A., Van Gool, A.R. Misattribution of agency in schizophrenia: An exploration of historical first-person accounts. Phenom Cogn Sci 7, 191–202 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-007-9082-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-007-9082-y

Keywords

Navigation