Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Performance, self-explanation, and agency

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Social constructionist explanations of human thought and behavior hold that our representations (e.g. of race, or gender, or mental illness, or emotion) produce and regulate the categories, thoughts, and behaviors of those they represent. Performative versions of constructionist accounts explain these thoughts and behaviors as part of an intentional, strategic performance that is elicited and regulated by our representations of ourselves. This paper has four aims. First, I sketch a causal model of performative social constructionist claims. Second, I articulate a puzzling feature of performative claims that makes them seem especially implausible: the puzzle of intention and ignorance. Like other constructionists, performative constructionists are especially interested in explaining thoughts and behaviors that are widely but mistakenly believed to be the unintentional consequences of membership in a natural kind. But why doesn’t the intentional performance of a category undermine this ignorance? My third aim is to resolve this puzzle. I suggest that a plausible understanding can be found in the failure to locate one’s mental states in a causal explanation of one’s thoughts and actions. Finally, I argue that this model implies that the sorts of theories we (as a community or as a culture) offer of particular behaviors can create or destroy agency and responsibility with regard to those behaviors.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Hacking has also discussed child abuse (1991, 1992), autism (1995b), fugue (1998), and race (2005).

  2. Hacking later discusses the role of a medical diagnosis that secured release for nineteenth fugueurs (1998, Chp. 4).

  3. Despite the centrality of intentional action under a description to his understanding of “making up people” (Hacking 1986, 1995a), Hacking expresses doubts about the sufficiency of conscious, intentional action to account for the phenomena of MPD or other “interactive kinds” (e.g. Hacking 1995b, 368; 1999, 115). The discussion here assumes only that performative accounts treat it as necessary. Relatedly, understanding multiple personality disorder as a performance should be distinguished from the claim that multiple personality disorder is a sort of malingering. Multiples may perform symptoms while at the same time belonging to some (perhaps natural kind of) human category that explains their propensity to perform.

  4. Lewis (1969) introduced of common knowledge. “Common knowledge” is a technical term; propositions that are common knowledge need not be true.

  5. Such social roles can also exist even where there are real natural kinds raising the possibility of partial or mixed constructions. I ignore these complications here.

  6. The intentional domain may be much broader than this, encompassing behaviors that are not “normal” or “rational.” Certainly, we attribute intention in some such cases (e.g. cases of akrasia). For present purposes, I will not be concerned with this broader domain.

  7. Because conscious intentional processes are resource intensive, drawing on finite resources like attention and willpower, this sort of shift from conscious and proximally intentional to unconscious and automatic is plausibly interpreted as a mechanism by which humans ontogenetically adapt to recurring environmental problems.

  8. E.g. Hacking (1999), Haslanger (2003), Mallon (2007) and Kukla (2000).

  9. “Natural” here should be treated simply as stipulatively picking out the complement of what is socially constructed rather than picking out some metaphysically fundamental feature of things.

  10. This terminology is adapted from Griffiths (1997, p. 145).

  11. E.g. Weiner et al. (1988), Monterosso et al. (2005), Woolfolk et al. (2006) and Vohs and Schooler (2008) all suggest certain sorts of causal constraint exculpate.

  12. Griffiths calls it the “problem of sincerity” that confronts what he calls “disclaimed actions.”

  13. Conversely, see Robbins’s (2006) discussion of successful introspective knowledge as involving detection and identification of one’s psychological states.

  14. See Griffiths (1997, pp. 151ff). Cf. Nichols and Stich (2003), Doris (2009). Because theorists often do not distinguish between detection, identification and what I call location, it is not always clear what is intended. An admirable exception is Doris (2009) though he is clear that his primary concern is with detection (2009, p. 80, endnote 16). Though he doesn’t draw this distinction Nahmias (2007) is, like me, clearly concerned about failures of location.

  15. This aspect of Nisbett and Wilson’s account is substantively distinct from those implied by the contemporary dual process accounts that are its most obvious descendents, even though Nisbett and Wilson’s work is typically presented as a seemless predecessor to contemporary dual process accounts (E.g. Haidt 2001), including by Wilson himself (Wilson 2002).

  16. According to the General SS at the University of Chicago, marital infidelity rates over several decades suggest that the rate is about 12 % for men, 7 % for women every year (Castleman 2009).

  17. In order: from, Woody Allen, explaining his relationship with Soon-Yi Previn in Isaacson (2001); from the character Mike McConnell in the movie Adventureland by Mottola (2009); Nora Ephron on men and her ex-husbands, in Levy (2009, 68).

  18. MacKinnon’s account suggests something more: that the selection of this explanation is motivated by the subject’s preference that the explanation be true. While MacKinnon offers no evidence for her account, there is extensive literature on motivated cognition (Kunda 1999), and she may well be right. Our model is compatible with such motivated cognition, but silent as to its extent.

  19. We must be careful. If MacKinnon is right, it is likely that the success of this failure of location can itself be helpful in enacting “receptivity” that enables someone to avoid violence. In the actual world, successful location may not be a good thing for an actor, all things considered.

  20. Fischer and Ravizza’s account of “taking responsibility” has been criticized for implying subjectivism about the conditions of responsibility (Ginet 2006; Eshleman 2001; McKenna 2000). In contrast to the cases that concern these critics, the agents in constructionist examples have appropriately internalized the norms for what counts as a fair target of the reactive attitudes in their communities. One could worry that this is still insufficiently objective, but requiring more seems to require abandoning a Strawsonian approach to responsibility.

References

  • American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5. Washington, DC: American Psychatric Publishing.

  • American Psychiatric Association Ed. (1994). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-IV. Washington, DC: American Psychatric Publishing.

  • Appiah, K. A. (1996). Race, culture, identity: Misunderstood connections. In K. A. Appiah & A. Guttmann (Eds.), Color conscious: The political morality of race. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Appiah, A. (2005). The ethics of identity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Averill, J. (1980a). A constructivist view of emotion. In R. Plutchik & H. Kellerman (Eds.), Emotion: Theory, research and experience: Theories of emotion (Vol. 1). New York City: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Averill, J. (1980b). Emotion and anxiety: Sociocultural, biological, and psychological determinants. In A. Rorty (Ed.), Explaining emotions. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. N. (1990). Adaptation and environment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. (1990). Gender trouble. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castleman, M. (2009). Marital infidelity: How common is it?” All about sex blog. Retrieved March 6, 2014, from http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/all-about-sex/200910/marital-infidelity-how-common-is-it

  • Doris, J. M. (2009). Skepticism about persons. Philosophical Issues, 19(1), 57–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. (2015). Talking to our selves: Reflection, skepticism, and agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Eshleman, A. S. (2001). Being is not believing: Fischer and Ravizza on taking responsibility. The Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 79(4), 479–490.

  • Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. (2008). Alief and belief. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 634–663.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, C. (2006). Working with Fischer and Ravizza's account of moral responsibility. The Journal of Ethics, 10, 229–253.

  • Goffman, E. (1970). Asylums: Essays on the social situation of mental patients and other inmates. Chicago: Aldine Pub. Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (1997). What emotions really are: The problem of psychological categories. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1986). Making up people. In T. C. Heller, M. Sosna, & D. E. Wellbery (Eds.), Reconstructing individualism: Autonomy, individuality, and the self in western thought (pp. 222–236). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1991). The making and molding of child abuse. Critical Inquiry, 17, 253–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1992). World making by kind making: Child-abuse for example. In M. Douglas & D. Hull (Eds.), How classification works: Nelson Goodman among the social sciences (pp. 180–238). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1995a). Rewriting the soul: Multiple personality and the sciences of memory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1995b). The looping effects of human kinds. In D. Sperber, D. Premack, & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal cognition: A multidisciplinary debate (pp. 351–394). New York: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1998). Mad travelers: Reflections on the reality of transient mental illnesses. Charlottesville, VA: University Press of Virginia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1999). The social construction of what?. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (2005). Why race still matters. Daedelus, 134, 102–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, 814–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2003). Social construction: The “debunking” project. In F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing metaphysics: The nature of social reality (pp. 301–325). Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. A. (2012). Resisting reality: Social construction and social critique. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Isaacson. (2001). The heart wants what it wants. Time. http://content.time.com/time/magazine/article/0,9171,160439,00.html. Accessed 6 March 2014.

  • Kukla, A. (2000). Social constructivism and the philosophy of science. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kunda, Z. (1999). Social cognition: Making sense of people. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2009). Nora Ephron knows what to do. New Yorker. 60–69. New York: Conde Nast.

  • Lewis, D. (1969). Convention: A philosophical study. New Castle: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKinnon, C. A. (1987). Feminism unmodified: Discourses on life and law. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKinnon, C. A. (1989). Toward a feminist theory of the state. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mallon, R. (2003). Social construction, social roles and stability. In F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing metaphysics (pp. 327–353). Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

  • Mallon, R. (2007). A field guide to social construction. Philosophy Compass, 2(1), 93–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2000). Assessing reasons-responsive compatibilism. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 8(1), 89–114.

  • Monterosso, J., Royzman, E. B., et al. (2005). Explaining away responsibility: Effects of scientific explanation on perceived culpability. Ethics and Behavior, 15(2), 139–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mottola, G. (2009). Adventureland, Miramax.

  • Nahmias, E. (2007). Autonomous agency and the threat of social psychology. In M. Marraffa, M. Caro, & F. Ferretti (Eds.), Cartographies of the mind: Philosophy and psychology in intersection. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. P. (2003). Mindreading: An integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R. E., & Bellows, N. (1977). Verbal reports about causal influences on social judgments: Private access vs. public theories. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 35, 613–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84(3), 231–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nolan, J. M., Schultz, P. W., et al. (2008). Normative social influence is underdetected. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34(7), 913–923.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2002). The blank slate: The modern denial of human nature. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, P. (2006). The ins and outs of introspection. Philosophy Compass, 1(6), 617–630.

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1956). Being and nothingness: An essay on phenomenological ontology. New York: Philosophical Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheff, T. J. (1974). The labelling theory of mental illness. American Sociological Review, 39, 444–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shackelford, T. K., & Buss, D. M. (1996). Betrayal in mateships, friendships, and coalitions. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 22(11), 1151–1164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1976). Responsibility for self. In A. Rorty (Ed.), The identities of persons (pp. 281–299). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1992). The psychological foundations of culture. In J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted mind (pp. 19–136). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trivers, R. (1976). Foreword. In R. Dawkins (Ed.), The selfish gene (pp. v–vii). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. D. (2000). The possibility of practical reason. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vohs, K., & Schooler, J. W. (2008). The value of believing in free will: Encouraging a belief in determinism increases cheating. Psychological Science, 19(1), 49–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Hippel, W., & Trivers, R. (2011). The evolution and psychology of self deception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34, 1–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiner, B., Perry, R. P., et al. (1988). An attributional analysis of reactions to stigma. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 55, 738–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, T. D. (2002). Strangers to ourselves: Discovering the adaptive unconscious. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollstonecraft, M. (1995). A vindication of the rights of woman. In S. Tomaselli (Ed.), A vindication of the rights of man with a vindication of the rights of woman and hints (pp. 65–294). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Woolfolk, R. L., Doris, J. M., & Darley, J. M. (2006). Identification, situational constraint, and social cognition: Studies in the attribution of moral responsibility. Cognition, 100(2), 283–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Research and writing of this paper was supported by the Princeton University Center for Human Values and the American Council of Learned Societies. I am grateful to Chrisoula Andreou, John Doris, Anne Eaton, Aaron Meskin, Shaun Nichols, Philip Pettit, Anya Plutynksi, and Stephen Stich, and audiences at Arizona, Arizona State, Duke, Houston, Princeton, Tulane, Washington University in St. Louis and Western Michigan for helpful discussion or comments on earlier drafts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ron Mallon.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mallon, R. Performance, self-explanation, and agency. Philos Stud 172, 2777–2798 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0444-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0444-y

Keywords

Navigation