Skip to main content

Criminal Justice and the Liberal State

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Palgrave Handbook on the Philosophy of Punishment

Part of the book series: Palgrave Handbooks in the Philosophy of Law ((PHPL))

  • 497 Accesses

Abstract

The chapter concerns the relationship between the justification of criminal law and punishment and the justification of the state. It briefly surveys the debate between retributivists and consequentialists and argues that both are inappropriate when it comes to state punishment. It next turns to arguments by Vincent Chiao, Malcolm Thorburn, and Antony Duff that locate criminal law and punishment in public law. The final parts of the chapter develop an account of criminal law and punishment as best understood as constitutive elements of a liberal political community necessary to ensure stability, to reinforce the commitment of the members to the rules as regulative of their plans of life, and to communicate and censure the offender for the wrong that has been done.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I am not sure where the phrase “political turn” first emerged. It was used for a conference in 2019 and has since appeared in the literature, including in papers that emerged from that conference (Burchard and Duff 2021) and in Brown Coverdale and Wringe (2022) and Thorburn (2022).

  2. 2.

    For details, see Moore (1997); for criticisms, see Dolinko (1991, 555–59), Matravers (2000, 81–87), and Hoskins and Duff (2021, §4).

  3. 3.

    A similar criticism is made by Malcolm Thorburn: “Moore has no tools available to explain why it must be the state and only the state that delivers criminal justice” (2012, 86–87). One of the more remarkable features of the very long first chapter of Moore’s book is that, despite its length and its focus on being “a theory of criminal law theories,” it does not mention the state once in its seventy-eight pages.

  4. 4.

    In Punishment and the Moral Emotions, Jeffrie Murphy writes of Moore that, “if he believed in God he probably would not favor this [retributive] account of secular, state punishment” (2012, 29).

  5. 5.

    It also misrepresents the origins and development of the criminal law. On the ways in which the criminal law was, and is, centrally concerned with order, see Farmer (2016).

  6. 6.

    It is important to distinguish this claim from the claim that all punishment is state punishment or that theorists of state punishment have nothing to learn from other instances of punishment. Legal punishment—which follows criminal lawbreaking, which in turn presupposes criminalization—is distinct in that very sense. However, that is not to say that non-legal punishments have nothing to teach us or that we should always focus on “paradigmatic punishments” such as imprisonment. For a useful survey, see Brown Coverdale and Wringe (2022); for a recent monograph, Radzik (2020).

  7. 7.

    For an interesting account of how utilitarianism is particularly suited to public policy—often for precisely the same reasons as it is not suited to ordinary interpersonal morality—see Goodin (1995).

  8. 8.

    For critical discussions of utilitarianism (both act and rule), see Mabbott (1955), Lyons (1965), and Williams (1973). For a more detailed account of the argument above with respect to punishment, see Matravers (2000, ch. 1).

  9. 9.

    In addition to the authors discussed below, others who have criticized the suitability of “interpersonal morality” as a basis for discussing state punishment, and who have offered alternative accounts of the latter, include Lindsay Farmer (2016) and Nicola Lacey (2004, 2016a, 2016b).

  10. 10.

    For an interesting discussion of these costs in relation to whether the achieving of retributive justice is “worth” the price, see Husak (2008, 203–6). As Husak puts it, “the expense of our system of criminal justice is astronomical. … Persons might reasonably prefer to use their tax dollars for any number of other worthy purposes” (203–4).

  11. 11.

    Thus, Thorburn joins with Chiao and Farmer in arguing that “criminal wrongs and justifications in the common law world do not even approximately follow the contours of moral wrongdoing and justification” (Thorburn 2011, 23).

  12. 12.

    For a clear statement of his differences with Moore, see Duff (2014).

  13. 13.

    For a detailed discussion of Duff’s account public wrongs, see Dempsey (2011).

  14. 14.

    In addition to Farmer (2016), the relationship of civil society, liberalism, and punishment is examined in Jonathan Jacobs’s important recent book, The Liberal State and Criminal Sanction (2020).

  15. 15.

    For discussion of the place of punishment in Duff’s theory, see Matravers (2011). For Duff’s response, see Duff (2011, 374–75).

  16. 16.

    I am indebted in what follows to Hanafy (2021, 54–64).

  17. 17.

    This criticism has been made by several people. For example, Michael Moore alleges that the account of public wrongs is “in danger of returning us to the conventionalist and relativist ethics that made Devlin’s brand of legal moralism so distasteful” (2014, 199). Victor Tadros claims that “any wrongdoing could become the state’s business by the public binding itself together by the values that underpin the wrong” (2016, 126). And Patrick Tomlin says, “‘public wrongs’ seems so permissive as to provide hardly any brakes on the criminalization process at all—if we think something is ‘our’ business, we can criminalize it” (2020, 320).

  18. 18.

    In developing this account, I have drawn on Charvet (1995, 2013, 2019) and Matravers (2000).

  19. 19.

    What follows draws on Matravers (2000, chs. 8–9).

  20. 20.

    This raises the issue of what to do with those offenders who do not endorse, but reject, the entirety of the rules and thus their membership of the political community. It may be that a political community has no other option at that point other than what Andrew von Hirsch calls “tiger control” (1993, 6)—that is preventative control—while, if possible, engaging with the offender to convince them of the value of the civil order.

  21. 21.

    Cf. Simester and von Hirsch: “Rational coercion operates via, and appeals to, the subject’s responsible agency; it offers her reasons for action, reasons she may choose to ignore. It does not make the decision for her” (2011, 6–7).

  22. 22.

    I am grateful to the Leverhulme Trust for a Major Research Fellowship (award MRF-2020-090) that enabled me to work on this chapter.

References

  • Brown Coverdale, Helen, and Bill Wringe. 2022. “Non-Paradigmatic Punishments.” Philosophy Compass 17, no. 5 (May): e12824.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burchard, Christopher, and Antony Duff. 2021. “Criminal Law Exceptionalism: Introduction.” Criminal Law and Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-021-09612-6.

  • Charvet, John. 1995. The Idea of an Ethical Community. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. The Nature and Limits of Human Equality. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2019. Liberalism: The Basics. Abingdon, UK: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiao, Vincent. 2019. Criminal Law in the Age of the Administrative State. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dempsey, Michelle Madden. 2011. “Public Wrongs and the ‘Criminal Law’s Business’: When Victims Won’t Share.” In Crime, Punishment, and Responsibility: The Jurisprudence of Antony Duff, edited by Rowan Cruft, Matthew H. Kramer, and Mark R. Reiff, 254–72. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dolinko, David. 1991. “Some Thoughts about Retributivism.” Ethics 101, no. 3 (April): 537–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R. A. 2001. Punishment, Communication, and Community. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Answering for Crime: Responsibility and Liability in the Criminal Law. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. “In Response.” In Crime, Punishment, and Responsibility: The Jurisprudence of Antony Duff, edited by Rowan Cruft, Matthew H. Kramer, and Mark R. Reiff, 351–79. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. “Towards a Modest Legal Moralism.” Criminal Law and Philosophy 8, no. 1 (January): 217–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018. The Realm of Criminal Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. “Criminal Law and the Constitution of Civil Order.” University of Toronto Law Journal 70, no. suppl. 1: 4–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R. A., and S. E. Marshall. 2019. “Crimes, Public Wrongs, and Civil Order.” Criminal Law and Philosophy 13, no. 1 (March): 27–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farmer, Lindsay. 2016. Making the Modern Criminal Law: Criminalization and Civil Order. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, David. 1988. “Moral Artifice.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18, no. 2: 385–418.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, Robert E. 1995. Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hanafy, Hend. 2021. The Justification of Punishment in Authoritarian States. Ph.D. thesis, University of Cambridge. https://doi.org/10.17863/CAM.81813.

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1994. Leviathan. Edited by Edwin Curley. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoskins, Zachary, and Antony Duff. 2021. “Legal Punishment.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2021 edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-punishment/.

  • Husak, Douglas. 2008. Overcriminalization: The Limits of the Criminal Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, Jonathan A. 2020. The Liberal State and Criminal Sanction: Seeking Justice and Civility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, Nicola. 2004. “Criminalization as Regulation: The Role of Criminal Law.” In Regulating Law, edited by Christine Parker, Colin Scott, Nicola Lacey, and John Braithwaite, 144–68. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016a. In Search of Criminal Responsibility: Ideas, Interests, and Institutions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016b. “Socializing the Subject of Criminal Law? Criminal Responsibility and the Purposes of Criminalization.” Marquette Law Review 99, no. 3 (Spring): 541–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, David. 1965. Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mabbott, J. D. 1955. “Professor Flew on Punishment.” Philosophy 30, no. 114 (July): 256–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matravers, Matt. 2000. Justice and Punishment: The Rationale of Coercion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. “Duff on Hard Treatment.” In Crime, Punishment, and Responsibility: The Jurisprudence of Antony Duff, edited by Rowan Cruft, Matthew H. Kramer, and Mark R. Reiff, 68–84. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey, H. J. 1968. “A Non-Utilitarian Approach to Punishment.” In Contemporary Utilitarianism, edited by Michael D. Bayles, 239–59. Garden City, NY: Anchor.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Michael S. 1997. Placing Blame: A General Theory of the Criminal Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. “A Tale of Two Theories.” Criminal Justice Ethics 28, no. 1: 27–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. “Liberty’s Constraints on What Should be Made Criminal.” In Criminalization: The Political Morality of the Criminal Law, edited by R. A. Duff, Lindsay Farmer, S. E. Marshall, Massimo Renzo, and Victor Tadros, 182–212. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Jeffrie G. 2012. Punishment and the Moral Emotions: Essays in Law, Morality, and Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radzik, Linda. 2020. The Ethics of Social Punishment: The Enforcement of Morality in Everyday Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shelby, Tommie. 2016. Dark Ghettos: Injustice, Dissent, and Reform. Cambridge, MA: Belknap.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Simester, A. P., and Andreas von Hirsch. 2011. Crimes, Harms, and Wrongs: On the Principles of Criminalisation. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stark, Findlay. 2019. Review of The Realm of Criminal Law, by R. A. Duff. Cambridge Law Journal 78, no. 2 (July): 453–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tadros, Victor. 2016. Wrongs and Crimes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thorburn, Malcolm. 2011. “Criminal Law as Public Law.” In Philosophical Foundations of Criminal Law, edited by R. A. Duff and Stuart P. Green, 21–43. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. “Constitutionalism and the Limits of the Criminal Law.” In The Structures of the Criminal Law, edited by R. A. Duff, Lindsay Farmer, S. E. Marshall, Massimo Renzo, and Victor Tadros, 85–105. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. “Punishment and Public Authority.” In Criminal Law and the Authority of the State, edited by Antje du Bois-Pedain, Magnus Ulväng, and Petter Asp, 7–32. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. “Criminal Punishment and the Right to Rule.” University of Toronto Law Journal 70, no. suppl. 1: 44–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2022. “In Search of Criminal Law’s Person.” In The Criminal Law’s Person, edited by Claes Lernestedt and Matt Matravers, 99–118. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomlin, Patrick. 2020. “Duffing Up the Criminal Law?” Criminal Law and Philosophy 14, no. 3 (October): 319–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tonry, Michael. 2020. Doing Justice, Preventing Crime. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Hirsch, Andrew. 1993. Censure and Sanctions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walen, Alec. 2020. “Retributive Justice.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2021 edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justice-retributive/.

  • Williams, Bernard. 1973. “A Critique of Utilitarianism.” In Utilitarianism: For and Against, by J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, 75–150. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matt Matravers .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Matravers, M. (2023). Criminal Justice and the Liberal State. In: Altman, M.C. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook on the Philosophy of Punishment. Palgrave Handbooks in the Philosophy of Law. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-11874-6_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics