Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

On the anthropological foundation of bioethics: a critique of the work of J.-F. Malherbe

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this article, I critically analyze the anthropological foundation of the bioethics of philosopher Jean-François Malherbe, particularly as presented in his book, Pour une Éthique de la Médecine. Malherbe argues that such practices as organ donation and transplants, assisted reproduction, resuscitation, and other uses of biotechnologies in contemporary medicine are unethical because they go against essential human nature. Furthermore, he uses this position as a basis to prescribe public policy and institutional practice. In contrast, I argue not only that ‘human nature’ is much more malleable and adaptive to changes in technology and society than Malherbe allows, but also that his criticisms of medicine and technoscientific development overstep the bounds of the social function of philosophical ethics, which is to inform and clarify public debate. Public policy and institutional practice is thus best left to the democratic political process under the parameters of the just rule of law.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Despite his numerous interventions on the international scene, including, notably, his service on the Executive Board of the European Directory of Bioethics [18], it is difficult to identify one policy, national or international, that directly cites his theory of medical ethics. But this absence of significant references seems to indicate the difference in bioethics approaches between North America and Europe, as opposed to a lack of his influence. About this, there is much to say. However, I cannot discuss it here as it would digress from the subject of this article. On a separate note, all quotations of Malherbe in this article are my translations from the original French.

  2. Jonas asserts: “All this holds on the assumption made here that we live in an apocalyptic situation, that is, under the threat of universal catastrophe if we let things take their present course” [24, p. 10].

  3. Habermas points out: “The provocation inherent in the advances of genetic engineering that have already been realized or are realistically to be expected does as yet not go that far” [31, p. 42].

  4. Malherbe’s criticism is similar to the scepticism raised by Animal Alliance of Canada about interspecies transplant (xenograft): “The pig receives human genes. The human receives pig organs. Where does the pig end and the human begin? How much DNA does it take before one becomes the other? The answer to these questions, once ridiculous and offensive, may now just be a matter of degree” [32].

  5. On the controversies relative to genetic manipulations, read also [3341].

  6. See [4244] for other recent and opposing viewpoints.

  7. See also [5870].

  8. “Physical necessity is a heteronomy of the efficient causes, for every effect is possible only according to this law, that something else determines the efficient cause to exert its causality. What else then can freedom of the will be but autonomy, that is, the property of the will to be a law to itself?” [25]. See also, “Heteronomy of the Will as the Source of All Spurious Principles of Morality” in Ibid.

  9. Which, Rousseau states in Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right, must consist of all people who represent the general will.

  10. See an opposite position in [71, 72].

  11. According to Aristotle “the end of the medical art is health” [73, bk. 1].

  12. Malherbe himself italicizes this phrase. Everything takes place as if we have to replace, henceforth, our supreme and constitutional courts with teams of doctors.

  13. For a useful brief introduction to this tradition, see any of the editions (1968, 1973, 1978, 1981, 1987, 1996, and 2002) of Rubington and Weinberg [82].

  14. This concept comes up a number of times in Malherbe arguments without being specified.

  15. I get the impression that the doctor has to choose between his or her own knowledge and clinical experience on the one hand, and, on the other hand, the principles abstracted from metaphysics.

  16. This is my example.

  17. In the following statement, Malherbe seems to view his work as having direct implications for medical practice and public policy: “To propose to doctors conceptual tools developed by common accord and adapted to the exercise of their ethical responsibilities, such is the contribution which the philosopher hopes to bring to medicine” [1, p. 157].

  18. It is as if the individual is dispossessed of his autonomous consciousness in favor of the judgments of the expert in bioethics.

  19. Habermas has clearly seen this function: “Thanks to its multilingual character, if philosophy simply keeps the basic concepts clear it can uncover a surprising degree of coherence at a metalevel” [90, p. XXXIX].

  20. In this regard, Luc Ferry notes: “Wise men's committees and authorities which we shall want, so pluralistic as well require the most scrupulous democracy, their decisions to authorize (or to forbid) the abortive pill, the experiment on the embryo, where the increase of Zygote Intrafallopian Transfer (ZIFT) will be inevitably more just” [38, p. 47].

  21. See also [31, p. 73; 52].

References

  1. Malherbe, J.-F. 1987. Pour une éthique de la médecine. Paris: Larousse.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Malherbe, J.-F. 2004. La démocratie au risque de l’usure: L’éthique face à la violence du crédit abusive. Montréal: Liber.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Malherbe, J.-F. 2007. Sujet de vie ou objet de soin? Introduction à la pratique clinique. Montréal: Fides.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Malherbe, J.-F. 2000. Les équivoques de l’autonomie. Sherbrooke: GGC Éditions.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Malherbe, J.-F. 1997. L’éthique clinique en situation de pénurie: un questionnement. Saint-Laurent, Québec: Fides.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Quintin, J. 2008. Cheminer vers soi: Hommage à Jean-François Malherbe pour son soixantième anniversaire. Montréal: Liber.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Durand, G., and J.-F. Malherbe. 1992. Vivre avec la souffrance: repères théologiques. Montréal: Fides.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Malherbe, J.-F. 2006. Les crises de l’incertitude: essais d’éthique critique III. Montréal: Liber.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Malherbe, J.-F. 2003. Les ruses de la violence dans les arts du soin: essais d’éthique critique II. Montréal: Liber.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Malherbe, J.-F. 2001. Éthique et leadership dans les services de police [Ethics and leadership in police departments]. Sherbrooke: GGC Éditions.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Malherbe, J.-F. 1999. Compromis, dilemmes et paradoxes en éthique clinique. Saint-Laurent, Québec: Fides.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Malherbe, J.-F. 1996. Homicide et compassion: l’euthanasie en éthique clinique. Montréal: Médiaspaul.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Bellefeuille, M. 1994. Jean-François Malherbe, Pour une éthique de la médecine. Horizons philosophiques 4(2): 154–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Malherbe, J.-F. 2002. The contribution of ethics in defining guiding principles for a public drug policy: export report to the Special Committee on Illegal Drugs of the Senate of Canada. http://www.parl.gc.ca/content/SEN/Committee/371. Accessed June 10, 2013.

  15. Malherbe, J.-F. 2005. Long-term care for older persons. Presented at a conference organized by the Luxembourg Presidency with the Social Protection Committee of the European Union, Luxembourg. http://www.mss.public.lu/public.lu/publications/blq019/bl. Accessed June 10, 2013.

  16. Hottois, G., and J.-N. Missa. 2001. Nouvelle encyclopédie de bioéthique. Bruxelles: De Boeck.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Malherbe, J.-F. 2010. La democrazia a rischio d’usura. L’etica di fronte alla violenza del credito abusivo. Trans. T. Lynch. Trento: Il Margine.

  18. Hube, G. 1993. European directory of bioethics. London: John Liber & Company Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Malherbe, J.-F. 1990. Medizinische ethik. Trans. P. Sana-Kerres. Neuenhagen, Germany: Medimops.

  20. Malherbe, J.-F. 1998. Hacia una etica de la medicina, 2nd ed. Trans. J.C. Gόmez. Santafe De Bogota, Colombia: Sociedad de San Pablo.

  21. Malherbe, J.-F. 1989. Per un’etica della medicina. Trans. P. Quattrocchi. Milano: San Paolo Edizioni.

  22. Vendemiati, A. 2002. La specificità bio-etica. Soveria Mannelli, Italy: Rubbettino Editore.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Sgreccia, E. 2007. Manuale di bioethica: fondamenti ed ethica biomedical [Bioethics: Foundations and Applications], 4th ed. Milano: Vita e Pensiera.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Jonas, H. 1984. The imperative of responsibility: in search of ethics for the technological age. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Kant, I. 2001. Fundamental principles of the metaphysics of morals. In Basic writings of Kant, ed. A. Wood. New York: The Modern Library.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Kant, I. 1997. Critique of pure reason. Trans. P. Guyer and A. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  27. Engelhardt, H.T. 1996. The foundation of bioethics. Oxford: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Beauchamp, T.L., and J.F. Childress. 2009. Principles of biomedical ethics, 6th ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Sartre, J.-P. 1973. Existentialism and humanism. Trans. P. Mairet. London: Methuen.

  30. Somerville, M. 2004. The ethical canary: science, society, and the human spirit. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Habermas, J. 2003. The future of human nature. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Harvard College v. Canada (Commissioner of Patents) [2002] 4 S.C.R. 45. http://c.s.c.lexum.org/decisia-scc-csc. Accessed April 17, 2013.

  33. Sosoe, L. 2005. Wie natürlich ist die menschliche natur? Überlegungen zur zukunft der menschlichen natur von Jürgen Habermas. In Gattungsethik-Schutz für das Menschengeschlecht? ed. M. Kaufmann, and L. Sosoe, 105–130. Frankfurt am Main: Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Buchanan, A., D.W. Brock, N. Daniels, and D. Wikler. 2001. From chance to choice: genetics and justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Lappé, M. 1999. Ethical issues in manipulating the human germ line. In Bioethics, ed. H. Kuhse, and P. Singer. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Kuhmann, A. 2001. Politik des lebens, politik des sterbens. Berlin: Alexander Fest Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Edelman, B. 1988. L’homme, la nature et le droit. Paris: Christian Bourgeois.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Goyard-Fabre, S. 1991. L’Europe et le droit. Droits: Revue française de théorie juridique 14: 33–53.

  39. Rabinow, P. 1999. French DNA: trouble in purgatory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Featherstone, K., P. Atkinson, A. Bharadwaj, and A. Clarke. 2006. Risky relations: family, kinship and the new genetics. Oxford: Berg.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Hedgecoe, A. 2002. Reinventing diabetes: classification, division, and the geneticization of disease. New Genetics and Society 21(1): 7–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Boyd, K. 2006. Medical ethics: hippocratic and democratic ideals. In First do no harm: law, ethics and healthcare, ed. S.A.M. McLean, 29–39. Hampshire: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Lock, M., and V.K. Nguyen. 2010. An anthropology of biomedicine. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Good, B.J. 2010. Medical anthropology and the problem of belief. In A reader in medical anthropology: theoretical trajectories, emergent realities, ed. B.J. Good, et al., 64–76. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Lindemann, G. 2010. Medicine as practice and culture: the analysis of border regimes and the necessity of a hermeneutics of physical bodies. In Biomedicine as culture: Instrumental practices, technoscientific knowledge, and new modes of life, ed. V.B. Regula, and J. Dumit, 47–58. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Buchanan, A. 1995. Genetic manipulation and the morality of inclusion. Social Philosophy and Policy 13(2): 18–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Murphy, T.F., and M. Lappé. 1994. Justice and the human genome project. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Heyd, D. 1992. Genetics: moral issues in the creation of people. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Adams, M.B. 1990. Eugenics in the history of science. In The well-born science: eugenics in Germany, France, Brazil and Russia, ed. M.B. Adams, 3–10. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Anderson, W.F., and J.C. Fletcher. 1980. Gene therapy in human beings: when is it ethical to begin? New England Journal of Medicine 303(22): 1293–1297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Nelkin, D., and S. Lindee. 1995. The DNA mystique: the gene as a cultural icon. New York: W.H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Mbulu, H. 2005. Die Habermassche Gattungsethik und das Prinzip der Vorsicht. In Gattungsethik-Schutz für das Menschengeschlecht?, ed. M. Kaufmann, and L. Sosoe, 83-103. Frankfurt am Main: Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Nietzsche, F. 1966. Beyond good and evil. Trans. W. Kaufmann. New York: Random House.

  54. Heidegger, M. 1997. Kant and the problem of metaphysics. Trans. R. Taft. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  55. Wittgenstein, L. 1969. On certainty. Ed. G.E.M. Anscombe and G.H. von Wright. New York: Harper Torchbooks.

  56. MacIntyre, A. 1979. Why is the search for the foundations of ethics so frustrating? Hastings Center Report 9: 16–22.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Sartre, J.-P. 1943. Being and nothingness. Trans. H.E. Barnes. New York: Philosophical Library.

  58. Gaudemet, J. 1987. Le mariage en Occident: les moeurs et le droit. Paris: Cerf.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Bologne, J.-C. 1997. Histoire du mariage en Occident. Paris: Calmann-Lévy (Pluriel).

    Google Scholar 

  60. Westermarck, E. 1891. The history of human marriage. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Westermarck, E. 1934. Three essays on sex and marriage. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Kertzer, D., and B. Marzio. 2001. The history of European family. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Jones, R.E., and L.H. Kristin. 2006. Human reproductive biology, 3rd ed. Burlington, MA: Elsevier Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Fox, R. 1983. Kinship and marriage: an anthropological perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Wilkinson, S. 2003. Bodies for sale: ethics and exploitation in the human body trade. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Ber, R. 2000. Ethical issues in gestational surrogacy. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 21: 153–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  67. Freeman, M. 1989. Is surrogacy exploitative? In Legal issues in human reproduction, ed. S. McLean, 165–175. Aldershot, UK: Dartmouth.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Robertson, J. 1994. Children of choice. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Robertson, J. 1986. Embryos, families, and procreative liberty: the legal structure of the new reproduction. Southern California Law Review 59: 955.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Atkinson, P., and P. Glasner. 2007. Introduction: new genetic identities? In New genetics, new identities, ed. P. Atkinson, et al., 1–10. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Gadamer, J. 1996. The enigma of health: the art of healing in a scientific age. Trans. J. Gaiger and R. Walker. Oxford: Polity Press.

  72. Gadamer, H.-G. 2003. Schmerz. Einschätzungen aus medizinischer, philosophischer und therapeutischer Sicht. Heidelberg: Universitätsverlag Winter.

  73. Aristotle. 1908. Nicomachean ethics. Trans. W.D. Ross. Oxford: Clarendo Press.

  74. Foucault, M. 1989. The birth of the clinic: an archaeology of medical perception. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Lindesmith, A.R. 1968. Addiction and opiates. Chicago: Aldine.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Lemert, E. 1951. Social pathology: a systematic approach to the theory of sociopathic behavior. Toronto: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Lemert, E. 1972. Human deviance, social problems, and social control. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Becker, H.S. 1967. Outsider: studies in the sociology of deviance. London: Free Press of Glencoe, Collier-Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Matza, D. 1969. Becoming deviant. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Conrad, P., and J. Schneider. 1980. Deviance and medicalization: from badness to sickness. St Louis: Mosby.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Lofland, J. 1969. Deviance and identity. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Rubington, E., and M. Weinberg. 2002. Deviance: the interactionist perspective. Boston: Allyn and Bacon.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Kant, I. 2002. The philosophy of law. Trans. W.B.D. Hastie. New Jersey: The Lawbook Exchange.

  84. Luhmann, N. 1982. The differentiation of society. Trans. S. Holmes and C. Larmore. NY: Columbia University Press.

  85. Quebec. 2013. Code of ethics of physicians. RRQ, ch. M-9, r. 3. http://www.canlii.org/eliisa. Accessed July 18, 2013.

  86. Quebec. 2012. Medical act. RSQ, ch. M-9, s. 3. http://www.canlii.org/en/qc/laws. Accessed July 18, 2013.

  87. Quebec. 2012. Professional code. RSQ, ch. C-26, s. 87. http://www.canlii.org/eliisa. Accessed July 18, 2013.

  88. Quebec. 2013. An act respecting health services and social services. RSQ, ch. S-4.2. http://www.canlii.org/eliisa. Accessed July 18, 2013.

  89. Quebec. 2013. Civil code of Quebec. LRQ, ch. C-1991, art. 10-31. http://www.canlii.org/eliisa. Accessed July 18, 2013.

  90. Habermas, J. 1996. Between facts and norms: contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. Trans. W. Rehg. Massachusetts: The MIT Press.

  91. Romains, J. 1924. Knock ou le triomphe de la médecine. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Freidson, E. 1988. Profession of medicine: a study of the sociology of applied knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Canguilhem, G. 2007. The normal and the pathological. Trans. C.R. Fawcett. NY: Zone Books.

  94. Rawls, J. 1971. Theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Kitcher, P. 2001. Science, truth, and democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  96. Jasonoff, S. 2005. Designs on nature: science and democracy in Europe and the United States. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Kleinman, D.L. 2000. Democratizations of science and technology. In Science, technology, and democracy, ed. D.L. Kleinman, 139–166. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Warren, M.E. 1999. Introduction. In Democracy and trust, ed. M.E. Warren, 1–19. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  99. Ricci, D.M. 1984. The tragedy of political science: politics, scholarship, and democracy. New York: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Trotter, G. 2006. Bioethics and deliberative democracy: five warnings from Hobbes. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 31(3): 235–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  101. Bishop, J.P., and F. Jotterand. 2006. Bioethics as Biopolitics. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 31(3): 205–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  102. Myser, C. 2004. Community-based participatory research in United States bioethics: steps toward more democratic theory and policy. American Journal of Bioethics 4(2): 67–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  103. Rosoff, P.M. 2012. The myth of genetic enhancement. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 33: 163–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  104. Lajeunesse, I., and L. Sosoe. 1996. Bioéthique et culture démocratique. Paris: L’Harmattan.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Rose, N. 2006. The politics of life itself: biomedicine, power, and subjectivity in the twenty-first century. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Kitcher, P. 1997. The lives to come: the genetic revolution and human possibilities. New York: Touchstone.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Lukas Sosoe for his helpful suggestions with regard to the content of this paper. I would also like to thank Michael Petrunik and Lizanne Avon for assisting this author, whose first language is French, in the editing of several drafts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Henri Mbulu.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mbulu, H. On the anthropological foundation of bioethics: a critique of the work of J.-F. Malherbe. Theor Med Bioeth 34, 409–431 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-013-9267-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-013-9267-z

Keywords

Navigation