Skip to main content
Log in

Acting for a Reason and Following a Principle

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to an influential view of practical reason and rational agency, a person acts for a reason only if she recognizes some consideration to be a reason, where this recognition motivates her to act. I call this requirement the guidance condition on acting for a reason. Despite its intuitive appeal, the guidance condition appears to generate a vicious regress. At least one proponent of the guidance condition, Christine M. Korsgaard, is sensitive to this regress worry, and her appeal in recent work to the constitutive principles of action can be seen, in part, as a response to it. I argue, however, that if we are to appeal to the constitutive principles of action to resolve the regress, then we must determine whether acting on such principles is also subject to the guidance condition. This raises a dilemma. If following these principles is subject to the guidance condition, then the regress remains unresolved. But if not, then the rationale for applying it to acting for a reason vanishes as well. I conclude that we should embrace an account of acting for a reason that rejects the guidance condition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The main aim of Korsgaard’s constitutivism is to ground the normativity of practical reason in the constitutive principles of willing or action. But, for Korsgaard, this aim can be satisfied only by showing how agents actively constitute themselves by acting for reasons. Thus, establishing how agents can act for reasons without generating a regress plays an important role in Korsgaard’s constitutivist account.

  2. See Davidson (1963) for the canonical contemporary development of this model.

  3. J. David Velleman makes a similar point and proposes a requirement similar to the guidance condition (2000, 9, 194). For reasons on which I cannot elaborate here, however, I do not think his view is vulnerable to the regress problem I describe later.

  4. The example comes from Nagel (1970), 33–4.

  5. The last sentence of the quoted passage—“Such an agent is guided by reason”—suggests that, for Korsgaard, being motivated by one’s recognition of some consideration as a reason is not only necessary but also sufficient for acting for a reason. It is the necessity claim that primarily concerns me, however. If a proposed necessary condition for acting for a reason cannot be satisfied without generating a vicious regress, then we must either conclude that acting for a reason is impossible or conclude that the proposed condition is not necessary after all.

  6. See, also, related arguments by Arpaly and Schroeder (2012) for why an act of past, present, or possible deliberation cannot, on pain of regress, be required to act for a reason.

  7. On Korsgaard’s view, these principles include the principle of instrumental reason and, ultimately, the categorical imperative (2009).

  8. I do not mean to suggest that the regress problem Carroll illustrates is generated by a requirement to preclude “blind conditioning” but only that such a requirement—as represented by the guidance condition—generates a structurally similar regress when applied to guidance by principles. For some further discussion of the Tortoise and Achilles regress problem in practical reason, see Railton (1997) and Dreier (2001).

  9. See Katsafanas (2013, 49), who makes a similar point.

  10. Thanks to Adam Leite and Aleksy Tarasenko-Struc for sharing a version of this objection with me.

  11. Notice the conditional character of this claim. I am not claiming here that we should be gripped by the worry about accidental conformity in either case.

  12. For an enlightening discussion about how some of these concerns about guidance figure in the literature about rule-following—specifically in Wittgenstein (1973) and Kripke (1982)—see Bridges (2014).

  13. See Railton (2004) for an outline of such an account and Arpaly (2006) for a more elaborate development of such an account.

  14. Whether the conditions for answerability are identical to the conditions for attributability is a deeper question on which I cannot elaborate in this paper. See Shoemaker (2011) for critique of this identity thesis, a thesis he attributes to Scanlon (1998) and Smith (2005).

  15. I argue for and elaborate on this thesis in McAninch Andrew (forthcoming) “Activity, Passivity, and Normative Avowal.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. See also Moran’s (2001) treatment of the connection between avowal and rational agency.

  16. Of course, the regress problem implies that no agent can meet the guidance condition on acting for a reason all the way down.

References

  • Arpaly N (2006) Merit, meaning, and human bondage. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Arpaly N, Schroeder T (2012) Deliberation and acting for reasons. Philos Rev 1212(2):209–239

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bridges J (2014) Rule-Following Skepticism, Properly So Called. In: James C, Andrea K (eds) Varieties of Skepticism: Essays after Kant, Wittgenstein, and Cavell. De Gruyter, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll L (1895) What the tortoise said to Achilles. Mind 4:278–280

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (1963) Actions, reasons, and causes. J Philos 60(23):685–700

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreier J (2001) Humean doubts about categorical imperatives. In varieties of practical reasoning. Edited by Elijah Millgram. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Katsafanas P (2013) Agency and the foundations of ethics: Nietzschean constitutivism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard Christine M (1997) The Normativity of Instrumental Reason. In: Garret C, Berys G (eds) In Ethics and Practical Reason. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard CM (2008) The constitution of agency: essays on practical reason and moral psychology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard Christine M (2009) Self-constitution: agency, identity, and integrity. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke SA (1982) Wittgenstein on rules and private language: an elementary exposition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • McAninch Andrew (forthcoming) Activity, Passivity, and Normative Avowal. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. Moran R (2001) Authority and estrangement: an essay on self-knowledge. Princeton University Press, Princeton

  • Nagel T (1970) The possibility of altruism. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Railton P (1997) On the hypothetical and Non-hypothetical in reasoning about belief and action. In: Garret C, Berys G (eds) In ethics and practical reason. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Railton P (2004) How to engage reason: the problem of regress. In: Jay Wallace R, Philip P, Samuel S, Michael S (eds) In reason and value: themes from the moral philosophy of Joseph Raz. Clarendon; Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon TM (1998) What We Owe to each other. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker D (2011) Attributability, answerability, and accountability: toward a wider theory of moral responsibility. Ethics 121:602–632

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith A (2005) Responsibility for attitudes: activity and passivity in mental life. Ethics 115:236–271

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman J David (2000) The possibility of practical reason. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Westlund AC (2003) Selflessness and responsibility for self: is deference compatible with autonomy?. The Philos Rev 112(4):483–523

  • Wittgenstein L (1973) Philosophical investigations, 3rd edn. Prentice Hall, Upper Saddle

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For helpful comments and suggestions, I would like to thank audiences at the University of Pennsylvania, the 2013 APA Central Division meeting in San Francisco, and the 2012 Illinois Philosophical Association meeting in Champaign, IL. I would also like to thank the following individuals: Gary Ebbs, Adam Leite, Kate Abramson, Colin Allen, Matt Carlson, Michael Koss, Susan Blake, Blakely Phillips, Marija Jankovic, Aleksy Tarasenko-Struc, Daniel J. Singer, and Justin Bernstein.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrew James McAninch.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

McAninch, A.J. Acting for a Reason and Following a Principle. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 18, 649–661 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-014-9551-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-014-9551-7

Keywords

Navigation