Skip to main content
Log in

Maturationally Natural Cognition, Radically Counter-Intuitive Science, and the Theory-Ladenness of Perception

  • Special Section Article: Theory-Ladenness
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Theory-ladenness of perception and cognition is pervasive and variable. Emerging maturationally natural (MN) perception and cognition, which are on-line, fast, automatic, unconscious, and, by virtue of their selectivity, theoretical in import, if not in form, define normal development. They contrast with off-line, slow, deliberate, conscious perceptual and cognitive judgments that reflective theories, including scientific ones, inform. Although culture tunes MN systems, their emergence and operation do not rely on culturally distinctive inputs. The sciences advance radically counter-intuitive (RCI) representations that depart drastically from MN systems’ deliverances. Extensive experience with RCI scientific theories can result in a practiced naturalness with their perceptual and cognitive consequences; nevertheless, automatic MN verdicts persistently intrude. Fodor suggests that the uniformity of the biases MN systems introduce can serve as a theory-neutral means for adjudicating scientific disputes. Findings about vision challenge Fodor’s proposal for circumventing problems that MN theory-ladenness presents. These considerations indicate that RCI scientific ideas are difficult to learn, master, and deploy; consequently, the corrective import of science’s social and institutional arrangements plays a critical role in its epistemic stature.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. “If perceptual recognition and explanatory understanding are… instances of the same form of cognitive achievement, as I have suggested… then it is proper to regard perceptual recognition itself as being just a case of explanatory understanding at the sensory periphery” (Churchland 1989, 228).

  2. This is not to imply either that all researchers draw the relevant distinction the same way (Evans and Frankish 2009) or that all endorse such a distinction, in the first place (Keren and Schul 2009).

  3. This paper uses senses of “intuitive” and “intuition” employed in the cognitive sciences, as discussed herein. Crucially, these terms can pertain to both perception and cognition (and will be used so here). These senses are, of course, distant on many fronts from the technical senses of these terms in Modern philosophy.

  4. This paper uses the term “knowledge” in the broad sense cognitive scientists do. Since it includes both knowing how (procedural knowledge) as well as knowing that (declarative knowledge), truth is not a necessary condition for knowledge on this view.

  5. Churchland holds that “even the humblest judgment or assertion is always a speculative leap…” (1989, 278).

  6. That skepticism seems particularly justified regarding claims about innateness, in a time when genetics is undergoing fundamental transformations (Jablonka and Lamb 2005) that virtually all of the parties to these debates ignore!

  7. Not only does establishing MN capacities not rely on culturally distinctive inputs, it may, in some cases, not even rely on any distinctively cultural inputs. What appears to be a spontaneous emergence of a collective sign language at a Nicaraguan school for the deaf suggests that such capacities may emerge from basic social interaction (Senghas et al. 2004; Coppola and Newport 2005).

  8. See the discussion in Jordan-Young (2010) of complete androgen insensitive (CAIS) females who are genetic males, i.e., they possess X and Y chromosomes, but who are to all external appearances morphologically female and who respond, if anything, as more feminine than average genetic females on most psychological measures.

  9. If this comment elicits an incredulous response, that, at least in part, is the point.

  10. For an extensive review of this research, see Henrich et al. (2010).

  11. See McCauley (2011) for a general discussion of these matters.

References

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). Mindblindness: An essay on autism and theory of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, J. L. (2012). Born believers: The science of children’s religious belief. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, H. C., & Kurzban, R. (2006). Modularity in cognition: Framing the debate. Psychological Review, 113(3), 628–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D. (Ed.). (2005). The handbook of evolutionary psychology. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C. F., & Hogarth, R. M. (1999). The effects of financial incentives in experiments: A review and capital-labor-production framework. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 19(1–3), 7–42.

  • Caramazza, A., McCloskey, M., & Green, B. (1981). Naive beliefs in “sophisticated” subjects: Misconceptions about trajectories of objects. Cognition, 9(2), 117–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (1986). Cognitive science and science education. American Psychologist, 41(10), 1123–1130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christiansen, M. H., & Chater, N. (1999). Connectionist natural language processing: The state of the art. Cognitive Science, 23(4), 417–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1979). Scientific realism and the plasticity of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (1983). Consciousness: The transmutation of a concept. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64(1), 80–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1989). A neurocomputational perspective: The nature of mind and the structure of science. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (2012). Plato’s camera: How the physical brain captures a landscape of abstract universals. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Contreras, J. M., Schirmer, J., Mahzarin, R. B., & Mitchell, J. P. (2013). Common brain regions with distinct patterns of neural responses during mentalizing about groups and individuals. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 25(9), 1406–1417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coppola, M., & Newport, E. L. (2005). Grammatical subjects in home sign: Abstract linguistic structure in adult primary gesture systems without linguistic input. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 102(52), 19249–19253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Fockert, J., Davidoff, J., Fagot, J., Parron, C., & Goldstein, J. (2007). More accurate size contrast judgments in the Ebbinghaus Illusion by a remote culture. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 33(3), 738–742.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2006). Breaking the spell: Religion as a natural phenomenon. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duchaine, B., & Nakayama, K. (2006). Developmental prosopagnosia: A window to content-specific face processing. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 16(2), 166–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunning, D., & Balcetis, E. (2013). Wishful seeing: How preferences shape visual perception. New Directions in Psychological Science, 22(1), 33–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. S. B. T., & Frankish, K. (Eds.). (2009). In two minds: Dual process and beyond. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1990). A reply to Churchland’s “Perceptual plasticity and theoretical neutrality.” A theory of content and other essays, pp. 253–263. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Gilovich, T. (1991). How we know what isn't so: The fallibility of human reason in everyday life. New York: The Free Press.

  • Gilovich, T., Griffin, D., & Kahneman, D. (Eds.). (2002). Heuristics and biases: The psychology of intuitive judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, T. R. (2009). Understanding natural selection: Essential concepts and common misconceptions. Evolution, Education and Outreach, 2(2), 156–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N. (1958). Patterns of discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1974). On Noam Chomsky: Critical essays. Garden City, NY: Anchor Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. (2010). The weirdest people in the world? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(2–3), 1–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. (2005). Evolution in four dimensions: Genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in the history of life. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan-Young, R. M. (2010). Brain storm: The flaws in the science of sex differences. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). (1982). Judgement under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelemen, D., Rottman, J., & Seston, R. (2012). Professional physical scientists display tenacious teleological tendencies: Purpose-based reasoning as a cognitive default. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 142(4), 1074–1083.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keren, G., & Schul, Y. (2009). Two is not always better than one: A critical evaluation of two-system theories. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 4(6), 533–550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2009). Doing without concepts. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mahoney, M., & DeMonbreun, B. G. (1977). Psychology of the scientist: An analysis of problem solving bias. Cognitive Therapy and Research, 1(3), 229–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCauley, R. N. (2000). The naturalness of religion and the unnaturalness of science. In F. Keil & R. Wilson (Eds.), Explanation and cognition (pp. 61–85). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCauley, R. N. (2011). Why religion is natural and science is not. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCauley, R. N. (2013). Why science is exceptional and religion is not: A response to commentators on Why Religion Is Natural and Science Is Not. Religion, Brain and Behavior, 3(2), 165–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCauley, R. N., & Henrich, J. (2006). Susceptibility to the Muller–Lyer illusion, theory neutral observation, and the diachronic cognitive penetrability of the visual input system. Philosophical Psychology, 19(1), 79–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey, M. (1983). Intuitive physics. Scientific American, 248(4), 122–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey, M., Washburn, A., & Felch, L. (1983). Intuitive physics: The straightdown belief and its origin. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 9(4), 636–649.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mithen, S. (1996). The prehistory of the mind: The cognitive origins of art, religion, and science. London: Thames and Hudson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2000). The evolution of knowledge. In P. Carruthers & A. Chamberlain (Eds.), Evolution and the human mind: Modularity, language, and meta-cognition (pp. 170–206). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Proffitt, D. R., & Gilden, D. L. (1989). Understanding natural dynamics. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 15(2), 384–393.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reber, A. S. (1993). Implicit learning and tacit knowledge: An essay on the cognitive unconscious. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rochat, P. (2009). Others in mind—Social origins of self-consciousness. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rozin, P., Nemeroff, C., Horowitz, M., Gordon, B., & Voet, W. (1995). The borders of the self: Contamination sensitivity and potency of the mouth, other apertures and body parts. Journal of Research in Personality, 29(3), 318–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, W., & Shiffrin, R. M. (1977). Controlled and automatic human information processing I: Detection, search, and attention. Psychological Review, 84(1), 1–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, B. J., & Tremoulet, P. D. (2000). Perceptual causality and animacy. Trends in Cognitive Science, 4(8), 299–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segall, M., Campbell, D., & Herskovits, M. J. (1966). The influence of culture on visual perception. New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Senghas, A., Kita, S., & Özyürek, A. (2004). Children creating core properties of language: Evidence from an emerging sign language in Nicaragua. Science, 305(5691), 1779–1782.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin, R. M., & Schneider, W. (1977). Controlled and automatic human information processing II: Perceptual learning, automatic attending, and a general theory. Psychological Review, 84(2), 127–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spelke, E. S., Breinlinger, K., Macomber, J., & Jacobson, K. (1992). Origins of knowledge. Psychological Review, 99(4), 605–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1992). Conceptual revolutions. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2012). The cognitive science of science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (2002). Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: The conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. In T. Gilovich, D. Griffin, & D. Kahneman (Eds.), Heuristics and biases: The psychology of intuitive judgment (pp. 19–48). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Ioannis Votsis and two anonymous referees for many helpful comments and to Mark Johnson for valuable discussions about theories and concepts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert N. McCauley.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

McCauley, R.N. Maturationally Natural Cognition, Radically Counter-Intuitive Science, and the Theory-Ladenness of Perception. J Gen Philos Sci 46, 183–199 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-015-9292-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-015-9292-x

Keywords

Navigation