Skip to main content
Log in

“Personal Knowledge” in Medicine and the Epistemic Shortcomings of Scientism

  • Symposium
  • Published:
Journal of Bioethical Inquiry Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, we outline a framework for understanding the different kinds of knowledge required for medical practice and use this framework to show how scientism undermines aspects of this knowledge. The framework is based on Michael Polanyi’s claim that knowledge is primarily the product of the contemplations and convictions of persons and yet at the same time carries a sense of universality because it grasps at reality. Building on Polanyi’s ideas, we propose that knowledge can be described along two intersecting “dimensions”: the tacit–explicit and the particular–general. These dimensions supersede the familiar “objective−subjective” dichotomy, as they more accurately describe the relationship between medical science and medical practice. Scientism, we argue, excludes tacit and particular knowledge and thereby distorts “clinical reality” and impairs medical practice and medical ethics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In the appraisal of a result using the null hypothesis, a low “p-value” suggests a true relationship and a high value suggests a result caused by chance. The degree of justification (in terms of p-value) required to qualify a result as knowledge is not an “objective” truth but is assigned conventionally (p < 0.05 in most situations).

  2. The inherent uncertainty of science—and resultant need for judgement—is also reinforced by the theory-laden nature of observation. Although intersubjective agreement might rationally strengthen a claim to truth (as happens with peer review), this does not lead to mind independent “objectivity,” as this agreement is still conditional on each individual’s judgement.

  3. Polanyi, who trained as a doctor before becoming a physical chemist and philosopher, also claimed that medicine’s purpose is to attend to suffering (Polanyi 1965).

  4. There have been more recent iterations of evidence-based medicine that claim to equally acknowledge other forms of knowledge (e.g., patient preferences and clinical judgement) (Buetow 2009). However, this rhetoric is at odds with evidence-based medicine’s fundamental tenets, as if other knowledge is equally important it is unclear why medicine must be “evidence-based” and not “preference-based” or “judgement-based,” etc. For a detailed argument, see McHugh (2013).

  5. Others have argued that there is a fundamental incompatibility between evidence-based medicine and Polanyi’s theory of tacit knowledge (Henry 2006; Braude 2012).

  6. Whether such a computer could be said to have “knowledge” at all (i.e., whether it could be artificially intelligent) is a different question that is outside the scope of this paper. Polanyi’s philosophy is certainly relevant to this debate (Blum 2010), and it would seem that as long as computers are unable to grasp the tacit element (and see meaning), true artificial intelligence will be elusive.

References

  • Blum, P.R. 2010. The immortality of the intellect revived: Michael Polanyi and his debate with Alan M. Turing. In Knowing and being: Perspectives on the philosophy of Michael Polanyi, edited by T. Margitay, 173–184. Newcastle Upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braude, H.D. 2012. Intuition in medicine: A philosophical defense of clinical reasoning. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buetow, S. 2009. EBM and the strawman: A commentary on Devisch and Murray (2009). “We hold these truths to be self-evident”: Deconstructing “evidence-based” medical practice. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 15(6): 957–959.

  • Calaprice, A., ed. 2000. The expanded quotable Einstein. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassell, E.J. 2004. The nature of suffering and the goals of medicine, 2nd ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Duan, N., R.L. Kravitz, and C.H. Schmid. 2013. Single-patient (n-of-1) trials: A pragmatic clinical decision methodology for patient-centered comparative effectiveness research. Journal of Clinical Epidemiology 66(8): S21–S28.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Evidence Based Medicine Working Group. 1992. Evidence-based medicine. A new approach to teaching the practice of medicine. The Journal of the American Medical Association 268(17): 2420–2425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, G. 2003. Plato on knowledge and forms: Selected essays. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, Sir R.A. 1935. The design of experiments. Edinburgh: Oliver & Boyd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grene, M. 1977. Tacit knowing: Grounds for a revolution in philosophy. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 8(3): 164–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, M., and G. Gillett. 2012. Suffering and the sleeplessness of physicians. In Perspectives on Human Suffering, edited by J. Malpas and N. Lickiss, 287–305. Heidelberg, London, and New York: Springer Dordrecht.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Henry, S.G. 2006. Recognizing tacit knowledge in medical epistemology. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 27(3): 187–213.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Henry, S.G. 2010. Polanyi’s tacit knowing and the relevance of epistemology to clinical medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 16(2): 292–297.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Henry, S.G., R.M. Zaner, and R.S. Dittus. 2007. Viewpoint: Moving beyond evidence-based medicine. Academic Medicine 82(3): 292–297.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. 1996. The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McHugh, H. 2013. Suffering and the dimensionality of medical knowledge: A critique of evidence based medicine. BMedSc(Hons) thesis, Bioethics Centre, University of Otago.

  • Montgomery, K. 2006. How doctors think: Clinical judgement and the practice of medicine. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrino, E.D., and D.C. Thomasma. 1981. A philosophical basis of medical practice: Towards a philosophy and ethic of the healing professions. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. 1958. Personal knowledge: Towards a post-critical philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. 1965. On the modern mind. Encounter 24(5): 12–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. 1975. Meaning. Edited by H. Prosch. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R. 1972. The logic of scientific discovery. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spielmans, G.I., and P.I. Parry. 2010. From evidence-based medicine to marketing-based medicine: Evidence from internal industry documents. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 7(1): 13–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sturmberg, J.P., and C.M. Martin. 2008. Knowing—in medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 14(5): 767–770.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hugh Marshall McHugh.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

McHugh, H.M., Walker, S.T. “Personal Knowledge” in Medicine and the Epistemic Shortcomings of Scientism. Bioethical Inquiry 12, 577–585 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-015-9661-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-015-9661-5

Keywords

Navigation