Skip to main content
Log in

Relative Interpretation Between Logics

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Interpretation is commonly used in mathematical logic to compare different theories and identify cases where two theories are for almost all intents and purposes the same. Similar techniques are used in the comparison between alternative logics although the links between these approaches are not transparent. This paper generalizes theoretical comparison techniques to the case of logical comparison using an extremely general approach to semantics that provides a very generous playing field upon which to make our comparisons. In particular, we aim to develop the useful idea that interpretations should determine inner models.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For an excellent and thorough discussion of these techniques, see Visser (2004).

  2. See French (2019) for a great overview of this.

  3. Problems for evaluating such questions have been raised in Meadows (2015) and Meadows and Weber (2016). It is noted there that in the absence of an acceptable tool to compare classical and non-classical logics it is almost impossible to assess claims that classical mathematics has been recaptured.

  4. That said formulae will always be represented by \(\varphi ,\psi\) and \(\chi\); never ABC. Given my goal is to bridge this work with that done in set theory and other areas of mathematical logic, more uniformity of notation seems desirable.

  5. Note that on the left side of this identity we have an operator from the algebra, while on the right side we have the syntactic connective.

  6. This makes our presentation simpler, however, we’ll show how to avoid this in Sect. 6.

  7. Note that I am writing \(h``\Gamma\) to mean the pointwise image of \(\Gamma\) under h; i.e., \(h``\Gamma =\{h(\gamma )\ |\ \gamma \in \Gamma \}\).

  8. This is called weak extensionality by Humberstone and is discussed on p. 455 of Humberstone (2011).

  9. This is essentially Exercise 3.23.4 from Humberstone (2011). I should also note that we usually do not have a \(\top\) in strong Kleene. It makes no difference to the result above if we extend the language and its interpretation to accommodate \(\top\).

  10. In some sense, providing a definition of logic could be construed as a challenge to find something that fails to satisfy it. Nonetheless, the definitions used in the paper provide a very broad umbrella.

  11. Within the context of the proposed framework, I think it would be natural to regard Kripke’s semantics for S4 as being partially interpreted. By this we mean that there is structure in the Kripke semantics which is not determined by the consequence relation. For many applications, this structure is—of course—invaluable. Nonetheless, the underlying framework of this paper could be adapted to logics fitting the Kripke semantics provided there is a uniform means of defining the required semantics from the consequence relations of those logics.

  12. We note that the converse does become available in stronger logics. For example, suppose that \({\mathcal {L}}\) contains a binary context (see Sect. 3.16 of Humberstone (2011) for a definition) \(\Sigma\) such that for all \(\Gamma \cup \{\varphi ,\psi \}\subseteq {\mathcal {L}}\), \(\Gamma \vdash \Sigma (\varphi ,\psi )\) iff \(\Gamma \cup \{\varphi \}\vdash \psi\) and \(\Gamma \cup \{\psi \}\vdash \varphi\). Then let \(\sim\) be an arbitrary consequence relation on \(\varvec{{\mathcal {L}}}\). We show there is some \(\Gamma\) such that \(\sim =\sim _{\Gamma }\). Let \(\Gamma =\{\Sigma (\varphi ,\psi )\ |\ \varphi \sim \psi \}\). Then we see that for all \(\varphi ,\psi \in \varvec{{\mathcal {L}}}\)

    $$\begin{aligned} \varphi \sim \psi&\Leftrightarrow \Gamma \vdash \Sigma (\varphi ,\psi )\\&\Leftrightarrow \Gamma \cup \{\varphi \}\vdash \psi \ \& \ \Gamma \cup \{\psi \}\vdash \varphi \ \Leftrightarrow \ \varphi \sim _{\Gamma }\psi . \end{aligned}$$

    We remark more on this phenomenon in Sect. 6.1.

  13. Section 2.12–13 of Humberstone (2011) and Sect. 6 of Jansana (2016) describe matrix semantics in more detail.

  14. For a definition of context see Sect. 3.16 in Humberstone (2011). From the algebraic perspective, this is a term with a free variable.

  15. The other operations are then defined by recursion.

  16. This should be compared to condition (4) of Definition 17.

  17. The intention here is that \(\#_{i}^{{\mathbb {A}}_{0}^{\dagger }}\) is the interpretation of the operator \(\#_{i}\) from \(\varvec{{\mathcal {L}}_{0}}\) in the model \({\mathbb {A}}_{0}^{\dagger }\).

  18. Specifically, in the case of theories in classical first order logic, suppose we have a relative interpretation \(t:{\mathcal {L}}_{\in }\rightarrow {\mathcal {L}}_{\in }\) such that if \(S\vdash \varphi\), then \(T\vdash t(\varphi )\) for all \(\varphi \in {\mathcal {L}}_{\in }\). Then if \(t^{*}\) is the associated mod-functor, we know that for all models M satisfying T, we have

    $$\begin{aligned} t^{*}(M)\models \varphi \ \Leftrightarrow \ M\models t(\varphi ). \end{aligned}$$
  19. See Remark 2.13.4 in Humberstone (2011) for references to a proof.

  20. One might wonder if the algebraic semantics offered for algebraizable logics could be used to provide a further notion of interpretation. As far as I know, these semantics are less suitable for this purpose. This is because establishing that some logic is algebraizable in the sense of Blok and Pigozzi (1989) is often a non-trivial matter, while the semantics for a proto-algebraic logic just fall directly out of its consequence relation. I suspect this indicates that the algebraic semantics delivered for algebraizable logics is more informative that the semantics we have used above.

  21. This is discussed in both Blok and Pigozzi (1986, 1989). Theorem 2.11 of Blok and Pigozzi (1986) is useful to establish these claims. See also Sect. 5.2 of Blok and Pigozzi (1989).

  22. This approach is also adopted in Dewar (2018).

  23. These are sometimes known as equivalential logics. See p. 267 of Pelletier and Urquhart (2003) for the axioms that must be satisfied. In particular, Kleene’s strong logic does not satisfy \(\vdash A\leftrightarrow A\).

  24. This fits well with Woods’ goals since he is aiming to give a syntactic account. The account of this paper sits somewhere in between the syntactic and semantic realms.

  25. This problem is easily surmountable. Moreover, Woods addresses it in an intriguing manner, which warrants further consideration. In particular, given logics \(\langle \varvec{{\mathcal {L}}},\vdash \rangle\) and \(\langle \varvec{{\mathcal {L}}}^{*},\vdash ^{*}\rangle\), Woods suggests that what we have called a relative interpretation should have two components \(t_{0},t_{1}:\varvec{{\mathcal {L}}}\rightarrow \varvec{{\mathcal {L}}}^{*}\) such that for all \(\Gamma \cup \{\varphi \}\in {\mathcal {L}}\), if \(\Gamma \vdash \varphi\), then \(t_{0}``\Gamma \vdash ^{*}t_{1}(\varphi ).\) Thus, we translate premises and conclusions of consequences differently. Woods argues that this extra dimension provides a better tool for respecting the intended meanings of the logics involved (Woods, 2018, p. 61).

  26. I say surprising here to avoid obvious cases like the fact that intuitionistic logic is equivalent to classical logic if we include the law of excluded middle as an axiom schema.

  27. In the case of theoretical comparison, sentential equivalence and bi-interpretability lie in between mutual interpretability and synonymy (Visser, 2004). An excellent starting point for this question which starts from the logic side of things is French (2011).

References

  • Blok, W. J., & Pigozzi, D. (1986). Protoalgebraic logics. Studia Logica, 45(4), 337–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blok, W. J., & Pigozzi, D. (1989). Algebraizable logics. American Mathematical Society.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1946). Modalities and quantification. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 11(2), 33–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewar, N. (2018). On translating between logics. Analysis, 78(4), 622–630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, R. (2019). Notational variance and its variants. Topoi, 40(38), 321–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, R. (2011). Translational embeddings in modal logic. Ph.D. thesis, Monash University.

  • Humberstone, L. (2011). The connectives. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jansana, R. (2016). Algebraic propositional logic. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1963). Semantical considerations on modal logic. Acta Philosophica Fennica - Modal and Many-valued Logics, 16, 83–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKinsey, J. C. C., & Tarski, Alfred. (1948). Some theorems about the sentential calculi of Lewis and Heyting. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 13(1), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meadows, T. (2015). Unpicking Priest’s bootstraps. Thought, 4(3), 181–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meadows, T., & Weber, Z. (2016). Computation in non-classical foundations. Philosophers’ Imprint, 16(13), 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pelletier, F. J., & Urquhart, A. (2003). Synonymous logics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 32, 259–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Visser, A. (2004). Categories of theories and interpretations. Utrecht Logic Group Preprint Series, 26, 284–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigglesworth, J. (2017). Logical anti-exceptionalism and theoretical equivalence. Analysis, 77(4), 759–767.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wigglesworth, J. (2019). Individuating logics: A category-theoretic approach. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 8(3), 200–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. (2018). Intertranslatability, theoretical equivalence, and perversion. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 7(1), 58–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Toby Meadows.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

I would like to thank Rohan French, Tobi Koch and Kai Wehmeier for a number of stimulating conversations that inspired this paper and made it so much better. I would also like to thank the anonymous referees for their extremely helpful comments.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Meadows, T. Relative Interpretation Between Logics. Erkenn 88, 3203–3220 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-021-00498-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-021-00498-3

Navigation