Skip to main content
Log in

Dialogue games and deductive information: a dialogical account of the concept of virtual information

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Because we are Kantian, because the space of possibilities within which our thinking moves continues to be defined by fundamentally Kantian theses (in ways we will be concerned to explicate), we cannot see that reason has now been realized as a power of knowing, in mathematics in the nineteenth century [...]. And because we do not see this, we cannot understand [...] contemporary mathematical practice, in particular the fact that its proofs can be at once deductive and ampliative, real extensions of our knowledge. (Macbeth, 2014, p. 6).

Abstract

There is a broad debate in contemporary philosophy of logic on the informativeness of proofs. In this context, informative proofs are demonstrations whose premises do not include the content of the conclusion. D’Agostino and Floridi (Synthese 167(2):271–315, 2009) claimed that proofs are informative if they use virtual information. In their terminology, this is the data carried by dischargeable hypotheses, assumptions entertained during proof and eliminated before concluding. Although these authors capture several cases of informative demonstrations, they do not explain the nature of virtual information. Why does the use of dischargeable hypotheses increase the informativeness of a demonstration? Following a Kantian inspiration, D’Agostino and Floridi claim that virtual information adds a synthetic feature to our proofs. However, this appeal to Kantianism is misleading: for Kant, mathematics is synthetic because it requires the construction of concepts in pure intuition. On the other hand, the entertainment of provisional hypotheses does not seem to involve the construction of figures in (transcendental) imagination. Exploring a dialogical characterization of logic, I suggest that virtual information results from the dynamics between a reasoner and her audience. When a reasoner provisionally assumes P, she enacts potential interlocutors who commit to P. Thus, “virtual information” denotes the content of some assumptions of the possible audience of a demonstration. This process of departing from one’s original premises to embrace the suppositions of other people is informative, but it is not synthetic: in this way, the reasoner does not entertain intuitions but only needs to reason through the conceptual content of other people’s premises.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The locus classicus of this problem is (Hintikka, 1970). For an overview of the various attempts to solve it, see Jago (2013).

  2. Although this investigation does not presuppose any particular view on the nature of semantic information, some of the authors mentioned here embrace veridicalism, a thesis introduced by Floridi (2004) according to which semantic information requires truth. For an assessment of veridicalism as an explanation of deductive information, see Mendonça (2021).

  3. The roots of an elucidatory conception of deduction is a theme for historians of logic. Significant moments of this history certainly include Descartes’ claim that logic is nothing more than “a dialectic which teaches ways of expounding to others what one already knows” (Descartes, 1985, p. 186) and Kant’s conception of logic as an example of analytic knowledge. The positivists’ philosophy of logic offers an additional example of this standpoint. For more details on this last issue, see Coffa (1991) and Juhl and Loomis (2009, chap. 1).

  4. These ideas are presented in several other contributions as well. For more details, the reader is also referred to D’Agostino et al. (2013, 2020), D’Agostino (2013, 2014a, b, 2015).

  5. How do D’Agostino and Floridi justify the claim that (4)–(6) are equivalent? Their argumentation has two steps. First, they argue that semantic and informational analyticity are co-extensional notions, since “it seems natural to assume that an inference carries no information if and only if its conclusion can be “seen” as true, whenever its premises are true, by simply looking at the definitions of the logical words occurring in the sentences” (D’Agostino & Floridi, 2009, p. 280). Secondly, they sustain that “if an inference is analytical in the semantic sense, then it should be possible to prove its soundness by means of some formal deduction which is analytical in the syntactic sense as well” (2009, pp. 280–281). This argumentation is, of course, less than convincing. In this sense, one could object that (4) does not seem equivalent to (5) and (6). Many valid deductions do not satisfy the subformula property but still rely exclusively on the meaning of their logical operators. To deal with this criticism, in practice, D’Agostino and Floridi use the refinement (4’): a deduction is analytic if it is justified in terms of the informational meaning of the operators occurring in it (2009, pp. 289–ff.). We do not need to enter in the technical details here. It is sufficient to say that the informational meaning of the logical connectives is the semantic counterpart of the minimum tractable logic \(L_0\). D’Agostino and Floridi’s argument seems circular. In a sense, they must redefine “semantic analyticity” in informational terms to make it equivalent to “informational analyticity.” However, I do not further explore this line of criticism here. Indeed, It is reasonable to say that deductions based on dischargeable hypotheses are not analytic. My main point will be a different one: even though D’Agostino and Floridi are right in saying that such inferences are not analytic, they are not synthetic either.

  6. For this argument step to work, D’Agostino and Floridi need to assume a further thesis implicitly: it is necessary to claim that definitions (4)–(6) exhaust the meaning of analyticity.

  7. Note that the adjective “virtual” as used by D’Agostino and Floridi is not synonymous of “ideal”, “subjective” etc. By this expression they just mean that a piece of information expressed by a dischargeable hypothesis is not included in the information expressed by the premises of an argument.

  8. For two recent presentations of Kant’s concept of mathematical construction as a philosophical account of the Euclidean mathematical practice, see Goodwin (2018) and, especially, Lassalle Casanave (2019).

  9. Note that this is a simplification of Dutilh Novaes’ point of view. She acknowledges that the history of the concept of deduction is more complex and diverse. Over the centuries, this notion has faced multiple processes of erasure and resignification. In particular, Dutilh Novaes (2007) highlights the medieval theory of obligationes as an equally important historical source for a dialogical comprehension of the meaning of deduction.

  10. Habermas (2000) famously criticized the dialogical facet of Brandom’s inferentialism. According to Habermas, the audience’s position in Brandom’s theory of assertion is more of a third-person who interprets the linguistic behavior of an individual than that of a second-person playing the role of an addressee. With some adjustments, Pera’s dialectical model could perhaps do the work of formalizing Habermas’ distinction between the second and third-person perspectives of an interlocutor (Pera, 1994). To my knowledge, the possible connections between Habermas’ theory of discourse and Peras’ model of science are still relatively unexplored. A single entry on this subject is (Rehg, 2009). In the present context, we might ignore Habermas’ criticisms. Perhaps we could say that the Brandomnian theory of assertion is weakly dialogical. Notwithstanding, it’s in a similar weak sense that I sustain that demonstrations display dialogical aspects. The audience of a demonstration is a neutral observer who monitors the prover’s inferential steps and introduces additional hypotheses when necessary.

  11. Dutilh Novaes’ and Marion’s arguments are not the only available attempts to philosophically justify dialogical logics. We also find in Rückert (2001) a more pluralist perspective on the issue. For him, dialogical logics are as theoretically relevant as any monological system, and because of this, the study of those systems should be equally stimulated. However, Rückert does not claim that our argumentative practices are, in any essential way, dialogical. Hence, his proposal is insufficient for our present concerns, namely, to show that deductive information is connected to the dialogical character of demonstrations.

  12. Dutilh Novaes formalizes these ideas in terms of a non-standard dialogical framework introduced originally by Sørensen and Urzyczyn (2006). However, we do not need to follow Dutilh Novaes in the technical details of her position.

  13. The present proposal assumes that the participants’ performance in an argumentative dialogue is, at least in part, governed by a “principle of cooperation”: the audience of a demonstration must cooperate within their powers (for intance, by affording dischargeable hypotheses when necessary). This assumption faces a number of prima facie objections. For instance, political argumentation if often highly confrontational, and it does not seem reasonable to say that, in this argumentative setting, contenders have a disposition to cooperate with each other. So, these examples impose relevant challenges to our proposal. To deal with them, we need to take into account some additional theoretical resources. In particular, Drama Theory shows us that, even in highly confrontational argumentative contexts, participants play a kind of cooperative “meta-game”, namely, players want to establish a set of parameters to achieve a “strict, strong equilibrium” between their positions (Howard, 1994, p. 200). Therefore, perhaps Drama Theory might offer additional conceptual resources to explain the phenomenon of hypothetical reasoning in highly adversarial argumentative contexts—a topic of future research, of course.

  14. D’Agostino and Floridi (2009) consider the two additional symbols t and f as labels for truth and falsehood, respectively. These symbols are unnecessary for the present purposes.

  15. Since the deduction theorem holds in classical logic, we can reduce the dialogical game on the validity of an inference \(\Gamma \Rightarrow P\) to a game on the validity of \(\bigwedge \Gamma \rightarrow P\).

References

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coffa, J. A. (1991). The semantic tradition from Kant to Carnap: To the Vienna station. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • D’Agostino, M. (2013). Semantic information and the trivialization of logic: Floridi on the scandal of deduction. Information, 4(1), 33–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Agostino, M. (2014a). Analytic inference and the informational meaning of the logical operators. Logique et Analyse, 407–437.

  • D’Agostino, M. (2014b). Informational semantics, non-deterministic matrices and feasible deduction. Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science, 305, 35–52.

  • D’Agostino, M. (2015). An informational view of classical logic. Theoretical Computer Science, 606, 79–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Agostino, M., Finger, M., & Gabbay, D. (2013). Semantics and proof-theory of depth bounded boolean logics. Theoretical Computer Science, 480, 43–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Agostino, M., & Floridi, L. (2009). The enduring scandal of deduction. Synthese, 167(2), 271–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Agostino, M., Gabbay, D., & Modgil, S. (2020). Normality, noncontamination and logical depth in classical natural deduction. Studia Logica, 108(2), 291–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1985). Principles of philosophy. In The Philosophical writings of Descartes (Vol. 1, pp. 177–292). Cambridge University Press.

  • Dutilh Novaes, C. (2007). Formalizing medieval logical theories: Suppositio, consequentiae and obligationes (Vol. 7). Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dutilh Novaes, C. (2015). Conceptual genealogy for analytic philosophy. In Beyond the analytic-continental divide (pp. 83–116). Routledge.

  • Dutilh Novaes, C. (2016). Reductio ad absurdum from a dialogical perspective. Philosophical Studies, 173(10), 2605–2628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutilh Novaes, C. (2020). The dialogical roots of deduction: Historical, cognitive, and philosophical perspectives on reasoning. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. (2004). Outline of a theory of strongly semantic information. Minds and Machines, 14(2), 197–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fontaine, M., & Redmond, J. (2008). Logique dialogique: une introduction: Méthode de dialogique: Règles et exercices (Vol. 1). College Publication.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, W. (2018). Conflicting conceptions of construction in Kant’s philosophy of geometry. Perspectives on Science, 26(1), 97–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2000). From Kant to Hegel: On Robert Brandom’s pragmatic philosophy of language. European Journal of Philosophy, 8(3), 322–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1970). Information, deduction, and the a priori. Nous, 135–152.

  • Hodges, W. (2001). Dialogue foundations: A sceptical look. In Aristotelian society supplementary volume (Vol. 75, pp. 17–32).

  • Howard, N. (1994). Drama theory and its relation to game theory. Part 1: Dramatic resolution vs. rational solution. Group Decision and Negotiation, 3, 187–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jago, M. (2013). The content of deduction. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42(2), 317–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Juhl, C., & Loomis, E. (2009). Analyticity. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998). Critique of pure reason. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I., & Allison, H. E. (1973). The Kant-Eberhard controversy; An English translation, together with supplementary materials and a historical-analytic introduction of Immanuel Kant’s on a discovery according to which any new critique of pure reason has been made superfluous by an earlier one. Johns Hopkins University Press.

  • Krabbe, E. C. W. (2006). Dialogue logic. In Handbook of the history of logic (Vol. 7, pp. 665–704). Elsevier.

  • Lassalle Casanave, A. (2019). Por constrção de conceitos: em torno da filosofia kantiana da matemática. Edições Loyola.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, G. E. R. (1996). Adversaries and authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science (Vol. 42). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macbeth, D. (2014). Realizing reason: A narrative of truth and knowing. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Marion, M. (2009). Why play logical games? In Games: Unifying logic, language, and philosophy (pp. 3–26). Springer.

  • Marion, M. (2010). Between saying and doing: From Lorenzen to Brandom and back. In Constructions. Essays in honour of Gerhard Heinzmann (pp. 489–497). College Publications.

  • Mendonça, B. R. (2021). Information and diagrammatic reasoning: An inferentialist reading. Minds and Machines, 31(1), 99–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Netz, R. (2003). The shaping of deduction in Greek mathematics: A study in cognitive history (No. 51). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pera, M. (1994). The discourses of science. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1976). Two dogmas of empiricism. In Can theories be refuted? (pp. 41–64). Springer.

  • Rahman, S., Clerbout, N., & Keiff, L. (2009). On dialogues and natural deduction. Acts of Knowledge, History, Philosophy, Logic, 301–336.

  • Rahman, S., McConaughey, Z., Klev, A., & Clerbout, N. (2018). Immanent reasoning or equality in action: A plaidoyer for the play level (Vol. 18). Springer.

  • Rehg, W. (2009). Cogent science in context: The science wars, argumentation theory, and Habermas. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rückert, H. (2001). Why dialogical logic? Essays on Non-classical Logic, 1, 165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sørensen, M. H., & Urzyczyn, P. (2006). Lectures on the Curry-Howard isomorphism. Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author is supported by a research scholarship from FAPERGS (Brazil: Project ARD/ARC—23/2551-0000775-4).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bruno Ramos Mendonça.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors have no competing interests to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix A: A correspondence between proofs and dialogues

Appendix A: A correspondence between proofs and dialogues

In this appendix, I prove that there is a correspondence between D’Agostino and Floridi’s hierarchy of tractable logics and the hierarchy of dialogical logics presented in Sect. 3.3. To do this, I do not provide a straightforward translation of proofs into dialogues. It’s very hard to obtain such translations: one of the few works exploring this path is (Rahman et al., 2009), but, there, the authors, from the start, diverge significantly from Lorenzen’s standard system. Instead of doing this, in this appendix, I show that D’Agostino and Floridi’s natural deduction system and the dialogical logics introduced here are complete for the same semantics.

In (2015), D’Agostino offered a semantic system for the minimal logic \(L_0\) (hereafter, following D’Agostino, let us call it 3ND-semantics). 3ND-semantics is governed by the following matrices.

\(\wedge \)

1

1/2

0

1

1

1/2

0

1/2

1/2

\(\{1/2,0\}\)

0

0

0

0

0

\(\vee \)

1

1/2

0

1

1

1

1

1/2

1

\(\{1, 1/2\}\)

1/2

0

1

1/2

0

\(\lnot \)

 

1

0

1/2

1/2

0

1

\(\rightarrow \)

1

1/2

0

1

1

1/2

0

1/2

1

\(\{1, 1/2\}\)

1/2

0

1

1

1

3ND-semantics is non-deterministic: in the matrices displayed above, a place filled with \(\{1, 1/2\}\), for example, means that it accepts anyone of these values.

D’Agostino showed that \(ND(L_0)\) is complete for 3ND-semantics. So, in what follows, we only need to demonstrate that the dialogical logic for \(L_0\) is also complete for this system of truth tables.

Theorem 1

P has a winning strategy in a game over \((P_1\wedge \ldots \wedge P_{n})\rightarrow Q\) in the dialogical logic for \(L_0\) if, and only if, \((P_1\wedge \ldots \wedge P_{n})\rightarrow Q\) is logically valid in 3ND-semantics.

Proof

To prove this theorem, we pursue the following strategy. Assume P has no winning strategy in a game over \((P_1\wedge \ldots \wedge P_{n})\rightarrow Q\) in the dialogical logic for \(L_0\). We will extend the set of formulae \(\{P_1,\ldots ,P_n\}\) to a greater collection \(\Delta ^*\) to which we have a model in 3ND-semantics. Subsequently, we will see that this model satisfies all formulae in \(\Delta ^*\) but does not verify Q.

To do this, consider a well-ordering \(\{\phi _m\}_{m\in \mathbb {N}}\) of the set of formulae of our propositional language. We define \(\Delta ^*\) by recursion. First, assume that \(\{P_1,\ldots , P_{n}\}=\Delta _0\). Secondly, for any already defined \(\Delta _m\), let \(\Delta _{m+1}\) be as follows.

  1. 1.

    If \(\phi _{m}\) is a disjunction \(R\vee S\), then \(\Delta _{m+1}\) is

    • \(\Delta _m\cup \{\phi _m\}\), if \(\lnot R, \lnot S \not \in \Delta _m\);

    • \(\Delta _m\cup \{\phi _m\}\), if either \(\lnot R\in \Delta _m\) or \(\lnot S\in \Delta _m\) and P has no winning strategy in a game over \((\bigwedge \Delta _m\wedge \phi _m)\rightarrow Q\);

    • \(\Delta _m\), otherwise.

  2. 2.

    If \(\phi _{m}\) is a conditional \(R\rightarrow S\), then \(\Delta _{m+1}\) is

    • \(\Delta _m\cup \{\phi _m\}\), if \(R, \lnot S \not \in \Delta _m\);

    • \(\Delta _m\cup \{\phi _m\}\), if either \(R\in \Delta _m\) or \(\lnot S\in \Delta _m\) and P has no winning strategy in a game over \((\bigwedge \Delta _m\wedge \phi _m)\rightarrow Q\);

    • \(\Delta _m\), otherwise.

  3. 3.

    If \(\phi _{m}\) is a denied conjunction \(\lnot (R\wedge S)\), then \(\Delta _{m+1}\) is

    • \(\Delta _m\cup \{\phi _m\}\), if \(R, S\not \in \Delta _m\);

    • \(\Delta _m\cup \{\phi _m\}\), if either \(R\in \Delta _m\) or \(S\in \Delta _m\) and P has no winning strategy in a game over \((\bigwedge \Delta _m\wedge \phi _m)\rightarrow Q\);

    • \(\Delta _m\), otherwise.

  4. 4.

    If \(\phi _m\) is neither a disjunction nor an implication nor a denied conjunction, then \(\Delta _{m+1}\) is

    • \(\Delta _{m}\cup \{\phi _m\}\), if P has no winning strategy in a game over \((\bigwedge \Delta _m\wedge \phi _m)\rightarrow Q\);

    • \(\Delta _m\), otherwise.

Finally, let \(\Delta ^*=\underset{m< \omega }{\bigcup }\ \Delta _m\). \(\square \)

Some facts about \(\Delta ^*\) will be important in the rest of this proof.

Proposition 1

The following holds for \(\Delta ^*\):

  1. 5.

    The set \(\Delta ^*\) may not be maximal;

  2. 6.

    \(Q\not \in \Delta ^*\);

  3. 7.

    There is no formula \(P'\) such that \(P', \lnot P'\in \Delta ^*\);

  4. 8.

    \(R\wedge S\in \Delta ^*\) if, and only if, \(R, S\in \Delta ^*\);

  5. 9.

    If \(R\vee S\in \Delta ^*\), then, if \(\lnot R\in \Delta ^*\), then \(S\in \Delta ^*\), and if \(\lnot S\in \Delta ^*\), then \(R\in \Delta ^*\);

  6. 10.

    If \(R\rightarrow S\in \Delta ^*\), then, if \(R\in \Delta ^*\), then \(S\in \Delta ^*\), and if \(\lnot S\in \Delta ^*\), then \(\lnot R\in \Delta ^*\).

  7. 11.

    \(\lnot \lnot R\in \Delta ^*\) if, and only if, \(R\in \Delta ^*\);

  8. 12.

    If \(\lnot (R\wedge S)\in \Delta ^*\), then, if \(R\in \Delta ^*\), then \(\lnot S\in \Delta ^*\), and if \(S\in \Delta ^*\), then \(\lnot R\in \Delta ^*\);

  9. 13.

    \(\lnot (R\vee S)\in \Delta ^*\) if, and only if, \(\lnot R, \lnot S\in \Delta ^*\);

  10. 14.

    \(\lnot (R\rightarrow S)\in \Delta ^*\) if, and only if, \(R,\lnot S\in \Delta ^*\)

  11. 15.

    If either \(R\in \Delta ^*\) or \(S\in \Delta ^*\), then \(R\vee S\in \Delta ^*\);

  12. 16.

    If either \(\lnot R\in \Delta ^*\) or \(S\in \Delta ^*\), then \(R\rightarrow S\in \Delta ^*\);

  13. 17.

    If either \(\lnot R\in \Delta ^*\) or \(\lnot S\in \Delta ^*\), then \(\lnot (R\wedge S)\in \Delta ^*\);

  14. 18.

    If \(\lnot (R\wedge S)\not \in \Delta ^*\), then either R or S are in \(\Delta ^*\);

  15. 19.

    If \(R\vee S\not \in \Delta ^*\), then either \(\lnot R\) or \(\lnot S\) are in \(\Delta ^*\);

  16. 20.

    If \(R\rightarrow S\not \in \Delta ^*\), then either R or \(\lnot S\) are in \(\Delta ^*\).

Proof of Proposition 1

  1. 5.

    For instance, if \(\Delta _0\) was \(\{P\rightarrow Q, \lnot P\rightarrow Q\}\), then this set could be increased neither with P nor \(\lnot P\).

  2. 6.

    Suppose Q is in some \(\Delta _m\subseteq \Delta ^*\). Then, P has the following winning strategy in a game over \((\bigwedge \Delta _{m-1}\wedge Q)\rightarrow Q\): she must force O to discharge Q and, subsequently, she must assert the same formula. This strategy induces the following dialogue:

0

D: P - ! - \((\bigwedge \Delta _{m-1}\wedge Q)\rightarrow Q\)

 

1

A: O - ! - \((\bigwedge \Delta _{m-1}\wedge Q)\)

0

2

A: P - ? - \(\wedge _2\)

1

3

D: O - ! - Q

2

4

D: P - ! - Q

1

Therefore, \(Q\not \in \Delta ^*\).

  1. 7.

    Including contradictory pairs in any \(\Delta _m\) creates a winning strategy for P in the dialogical game. We prove this fact by induction on the complexity of formulae. Consider the case of a sentence of the form \(R\vee S\) (the cases of \(R\wedge S\) and \(R\rightarrow S\) work in a similar way). Assume that, for some \(\Delta _m\subseteq \Delta ^*\), \(\Delta _m=\Gamma \cup \{R\vee S,\lnot (R\vee S)\}\). In a game over \(\bigwedge \Delta _m\rightarrow Q\), P can force O to discharge \(\lnot R\), \(\lnot S\), and either R or S. By inductive hypothesis, P has a winning strategy in a match in which O defends this collection of formulae.

  2. 8.

    The use of a conjunction in a dialogue involves discharging its conjunctives. Consequently, the introduction of the conjunctives in \(\Delta ^*\) is redundant. Similar arguments justify items 9 – 14.

  1. 9.

    Without loss of generality, assume that \(R\in \Delta ^*\). Then, \(\lnot R\not \in \Delta ^*\), by item 7. So, the introduction of \(R\vee S\) in \(\Delta ^*\) is, in a sense, redundant. Without \(\lnot R\), one cannot use the disjunction to discharge S. Moreover, the other disjunctive, R, is already in \(\Delta ^*\). Hence, including \(R\vee S\) does not create a winning strategy for P. A similar argument justifies item 17.

  2. 10.

    We need to consider cases here:

    • Case 1: \(\lnot R, S\in \Delta ^*\). So, by item 2, \(R,\lnot S\not \in \Delta ^*\). Hence, by definition of \(\Delta ^*\), \(R\rightarrow S\) is in this set.

    • Case 2: \(\lnot R, \lnot S\in \Delta ^*\). With the inclusion of \(R\rightarrow S\) in \(\Delta ^*\), P may force O to defend \(\lnot R\), which is a redundant move since \(\lnot R\) is already in \(\Delta ^*\). Therefore, including the conditional in \(\Delta ^*\) does not create a winning strategy for P.

    • Case 3: \(R, S\in \Delta ^*\). With the inclusion of \(R\rightarrow S\) in \(\Delta ^*\), P may force O to defend S, which is a redundant move since S is already in \(\Delta ^*\). Therefore, including the conditional in \(\Delta ^*\) does not create a winning strategy for P.

  1. 11.

    P can attack \(\lnot (R\wedge S)\) only in the presence of either R or S. Similar reasoning justifies items 19 and 20.

Let us come back to the proof of Theorem 1. Now, we need to define a model in 3ND-semantics for \(\Delta ^*\). So, consider the following truth-assignment v (in 3ND-semantics) for the atomic formulae of our propositional language. For any atomic formula p,

  • \(v(p)=1\) if, and only if, \(p\in \Delta ^*\);

  • \(v(p)=0\) if, and only if, \(\lnot p \in \Delta ^*\);

  • \(v(p)=1/2\) if, and only if, \(p,\lnot p \not \in \Delta ^*\).

Due to the non-deterministic feature of 3ND-semantics, we need to add some semantic clauses for v(P) when P is either a conjunction, a disjunction, or an implication.

  • If P is \(R\wedge S\) and \(v(R)=v(S)=1/2\), then \(v(P)=0\);

  • If P is either \(R\vee S\) or \(R\rightarrow S\) and \(v(R)=v(S)=1/2\), then \(v(P)=1\).

Finally, we will show that the following holds: for any formula P of our language,

$$\begin{aligned}{} & {} v(P)=1 \text { if, and only if, } P\in \Delta ^*. \\{} & {} v(P)=0 \text { if, and only if, } \lnot P\in \Delta ^*. \\{} & {} v(P)=1/2 \text { if, and only if, } P, \lnot P\not \in \Delta ^* \end{aligned}$$

We prove this fact by induction on the complexity of formulae.

If P is atomic, the property holds by definition of v.

Assume that P is a conjunction \(R\wedge S\).

(Proof of necessity)

  • Suppose \(R\wedge S\in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.8, \(R, S\in \Delta ^*\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(v(R)=v(S)=1\). So, \(v(R\wedge S)=1\).

  • Suppose \(\lnot (R\wedge S)\in \Delta ^*\). We need to consider cases:

    • Case 1: \(R, S\not \in \Delta ^*\).

      • Subcase 1: either \(\lnot R\) or \(\lnot S\) are in \(\Delta ^*\). So, by the inductive hypothesis, either v(R) or v(S) is 0. Then, \(v(R\wedge S)=0\).

      • Subcase 2: \(\lnot R,\lnot S\not \in \Delta ^*\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(v(R)=v(S)=1/2\). By definition of v, \(v(R\wedge S)=0\).

    • Case 2: either R or S are in \(\Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.12, we have either \(\lnot R\) or \(\lnot S\in \Delta ^*\). By the inductive hypothesis, v(R) or v(S) is 0. So, \(v(R\wedge S)=0\).

  • Suppose \(R\wedge S, \lnot (R\wedge S)\not \in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.17, \(\lnot R,\lnot S\not \in \Delta ^*\). Moreover, by Prop. 1.8, either R or S is not in \(\Delta ^*\). However, due to Prop. 1.18, at least one of them is in \(\Delta ^*\). Without loss of generality, assume \(R\not \in \Delta ^*\) and \(S\in \Delta ^*\). By inductive hypothesis, \(v(R)=1/2\) and \(v(S)=1\). So, \(v(R\wedge S)=1/2\).

(Proof of sufficiency)

  • Suppose \(v(R\wedge S)=1\). Then, \(v(R)=v(S)=1\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(R, S\in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.8, \(R\wedge S\in \Delta ^*\).

  • Suppose \(v(R\wedge S)=0\). We need to consider cases:

    • Case 1: Either \(v(R)=0\) or \(v(S)=0\). Without loss of generality, consider \(v(R)=0\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(\lnot R\in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.17, \(\lnot (R\wedge S)\in \Delta ^*\).

    • Case 2: \(v(R)=v(S)=1/2\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(R, S, \lnot R, \lnot S\not \in \Delta ^*\). So, by the construction of \(\Delta ^*\), \(\lnot (R\wedge S)\in \Delta ^*\).

  • Suppose \(v(R\wedge S)=1/2\). Then, either \(v(R)=1/2\) and \(v(S)=1\) or \(v(R)=1\) and \(v(S)=1/2\). Without loss of generality, assume that \(v(R)=1/2\) and \(v(S)=1\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(R, \lnot R\not \in \Delta ^*\) and \(S\in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.8, \(R\wedge S\not \in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.12, \(\lnot (R\wedge S)\not \in \Delta ^*\).

Assume that P is a disjunction \(R\vee S\).

(Proof of necessity)

  • Suppose \(R\vee S\in \Delta ^*\). We need to consider cases:

    • Case 1: \(\lnot R,\lnot S\not \in \Delta ^*\).

      • Subcase 1: either R or S are in \(\Delta ^*\). By the inductive hypothesis, v(R) or v(S) is 1. So, \(v(R\vee S)=1\).

      • Subcase 2: \(R, S\not \in \Delta ^*\). By inductive hypothesis, \(v(R)=v(S)=1/2\). By definition of v, \(v(R\vee S)=1\).

    • Case 2: either \(\lnot R\) or \(\lnot S\) are in \(\Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.9, we have either S or \(R\in \Delta ^*\). By the inductive hypothesis, v(S) or v(R) is 1. So, \(v(R\vee S)=1\).

  • Suppose \(\lnot (R\vee S)\in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.13, \(\lnot R, \lnot S\in \Delta ^*\). By inductive hypothesis, \(v(R)=v(S)=0\). Consequently, \(v(R\vee S)=0\).

  • Suppose \(R\vee S, \lnot (R\vee S)\not \in \Delta ^*\). Then, by Prop. 1.15, \(R, S\not \in \Delta ^*\). Furthermore, by Prop. 1.13, either \(\lnot R\) or \(\lnot S\) are not in \(\Delta ^*\). On the other hand, due to Prop. 1.19, at least one of these formulae is in \(\Delta ^*\). Without loss of generality, assume \(\lnot R\not \in \Delta ^*\) and \(\lnot S\in \Delta ^*\). By inductive hypothesis, \(v(R)=1/2\) and \(v(S)=0\). So, \(v(R\vee S)=1/2\).

(Proof of sufficiency)

  • Suppose \(v(R\vee S)=1\). We need to consider cases:

    • Case 1: either \(v(R)=1\) or \(v(S)=1\). Without loss of generality, let \(v(R)=1\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(R\in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.15, \(R\vee S\in \Delta ^*\).

    • Case 2: \(v(R)=v(S)=1/2\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(R, S, \lnot R, \lnot S\not \in \Delta ^*\). By the construction of \(\Delta ^*\), \(R\vee S\) is in this set.

  • Suppose \(v(R\vee S)=0\). Then, \(v(R)=v(S)=0\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(\lnot R,\lnot S\in \Delta ^*\). Then, by Prop. 1. 13, \(\lnot (R\vee S)\in \Delta ^*\).

  • Suppose \(v(R\vee S)=1/2\). Then, either \(v(R)=1/2\) and \(v(S)=0\) or \(v(R)=0\) and \(v(S)=1/2\). Without loss of generality, let us assume that \(v(R)=1/2\) and \(v(S)=0\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(R,\lnot R\not \in \Delta ^*\) and \(\lnot S\in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1. 13, \(\lnot (R\vee S)\not \in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1. 9, \(R\vee S\not \in \Delta ^*\).

Assume that P is an implication \(R\rightarrow S\).

(Proof of necessity).

  • Suppose \(R\rightarrow S\in \Delta ^*\). We need to consider cases:

    • Case 1: \(R, \lnot S\not \in \Delta ^*\).

      • Subcase 1: either \(\lnot R\) or S are in \(\Delta ^*\). By the inductive hypothesis, either \(v(R)=0\) or \(v(S)=1\). So, \(v(R\rightarrow S)=1\).

      • Subcase 2: \(\lnot R, S\not \in \Delta ^*\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(v(R)=v(S)=1/2\). So, by the definition of v, \(v(R\rightarrow S)=1\).

    • Case 2: either R or \(\lnot S\) are in \(\Delta ^*\). Then, by Prop. 1.10, either S or \(\lnot R\) is in \(\Delta ^*\). By the inductive hypothesis, either \(v(S)=1\) or \(v(R)=0\). So, \(v(R\rightarrow S)=1\).

  • Suppose \(\lnot (R\rightarrow S)\in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.14, \(R, \lnot S\in \Delta ^*\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(v(R)=1\) and \(v(S)=0\). Consequently, \(v(R\rightarrow S)=0\).

  • Suppose \(R\rightarrow S, \lnot (R\rightarrow S)\not \in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.20, either R or \(\lnot S\) are in \(\Delta ^*\). Moreover, by Prop. 1. 14, either R or \(\lnot S\) is not in \(\Delta ^*\). Without loss of generality, assume \(R\in \Delta ^*\) and \(\lnot S\not \in \Delta ^*\). In this case, the inclusion of \(R\rightarrow S\in \Delta ^*\) creates a winning strategy for P by enabling him to discharge S. Hence, \(S\not \in \Delta ^*\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(v(R)=1\) and \(v(S)=1/2\). Consequently, \(v(R\rightarrow S)=1/2\).

(Proof of sufficiency)

  • Suppose \(v(R\rightarrow S)=1\). We need to consider cases:

    • Case 1: either \(v(R)=0\) or \(v(S)=1\). Then, by the inductive hypothesis, either \(\lnot R\) or S are in \(\Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.16, \(R\rightarrow S\in \Delta ^*\).

    • Case 2: \(v(R)=v(S)=1/2\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(R, S, \lnot R, \lnot S\not \in \Delta ^*\). By the construction of \(\Delta ^*\), \(R\rightarrow S \in \Delta ^*\).

  • Suppose \(v(R\rightarrow S)=0\). Then, \(v(R)=1\) and \(v(S)=0\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(R,\lnot S\in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.14, \(\lnot (R\rightarrow S)\in \Delta ^*\).

  • Suppose \(v(R\rightarrow S)=1/2\). Then, either \(v(R)=1/2\) and \(v(S)=0\) or \(v(R)=1\) and \(v(S)=1/2\). Without loss of generality, assume \(v(R)=1/2\) and \(v(S)=0\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(R,\lnot R\not \in \Delta ^*\) and \(\lnot S\in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1. 14, \(\lnot (R\rightarrow S)\not \in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.10, \(R\rightarrow S\not \in \Delta ^*\).

Assume that P is a negation \(\lnot R\).

(Proof of necessity)

  • Suppose \(\lnot R\in \Delta ^*\). Then, by the inductive hypothesis, \(v(R)=0\). So, \(v(\lnot R)=1\).

  • Suppose \(\lnot \lnot R\in \Delta ^*\). By Prop. 1.11, \(R\in \Delta ^*\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(v(R)=v(\lnot \lnot R)=1\).

  • Suppose \(\lnot R, \lnot \lnot R\not \in \Delta ^*\). Then, \(R\not \in \Delta ^*\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(v(R)=v(\lnot R)=1/2\).

(Proof of sufficiency)

  • Suppose \(v(\lnot R)=1\). Then, \(v(R)=0\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(\lnot R\in \Delta ^*\).

  • Suppose \(v(\lnot R)=0\). Then, \(v(R)=1\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(R\in \Delta ^*\). Then, By Prop. 1. 11, \(\lnot \lnot R\in \Delta ^*\).

  • Suppose \(v(\lnot R)=1/2\). Then, \(v(R)=1/2\). By the inductive hypothesis, \(R,\lnot R\not \in \Delta ^*\).

So, v attributes 1 for every formula in \(\Delta ^*\). Since \(\Delta _0\subseteq \Delta ^*\), then v defines a model in 3ND-semantics that verifies the sentences \(P_1,\ldots , P_n\) but does not satisfy Q. \(\square \)

Corollary 1

For any set of sentences \(\{P_1,\ldots , P_n, Q\}\), the deductive sequence \(P_1,\ldots ,P_n\Rightarrow Q\) holds in \(ND(L_0)\) if, and only if, there is a winning strategy for P in the \(L_0\)-game over \((P_1\wedge \ldots \wedge P_n) \rightarrow Q\).

Finally, let us prove the correspondence between D’Agostino and Floridi’s hierarchy and the dialogical logics presented here.

Theorem 2

For any set of sentences \(\{P_1,\ldots , P_m, Q\}\), for every \(n\ge 0\), the deduction \(P_1,\ldots ,P_m\Rightarrow _n Q\) holds if, and only if, there is a winning strategy for P in the \(L_n\)-game over \((P_1\wedge \ldots \wedge P_m) \rightarrow Q\).

Proof

Assume that \(P_1,\ldots ,P_m\Rightarrow _{n+1} Q\) holds. Then, there is a formula \(R\in \) Sub(\(\{P_1,\ldots , P_m, Q\}\)) such that

  • \(P_1,\ldots ,P_m, R\Rightarrow _{n} Q\);

  • \(P_1,\ldots ,P_m, \lnot R\Rightarrow _{n} Q\).

By the inductive hypothesis, there are winning strategies for P in the games \(G_n((P_1\wedge \ldots \wedge P_m\wedge R)\rightarrow Q)\) and \(G_n((P_1\wedge \ldots \wedge P_m\wedge \lnot R)\rightarrow Q)\). It is easy to verify that, based on these strategies, we can define winning strategies for P in the games \(G_n(R\rightarrow [(P_1\wedge \ldots \wedge P_m)\rightarrow Q])\) and \(G_n(\lnot R \rightarrow [(P_1\wedge \ldots \wedge P_m)\rightarrow Q])\). So, P has a winning strategy in the game \(G_n^+((P_1\wedge \ldots \wedge P_m)\rightarrow Q, R)\). Therefore, P has a winning strategy in \(G_{n+1}((P_1\wedge \ldots \wedge P_m)\rightarrow Q)\). \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mendonça, B.R. Dialogue games and deductive information: a dialogical account of the concept of virtual information. Synthese 202, 73 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04303-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04303-2

Keywords

Navigation