Skip to main content
Log in

“What Counts as an Insult?”

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In virtue of what does a linguistic act count as an insult? I discuss five main approaches to this question, according to which an insult is determined by (i) the semantic properties of the expression used; (ii) the insulter, her intention, or attitudes; (iii) the addressee and her personal standard; (iv) the features of the speech act performed; and (v) the standard of the relevant social group. I endorse the last, objectivist account, according to which an act x counts as an insult if and only if x is assessed as demeaning when addressed at A by the standard of the relevant social group at t.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some theorists use “insult” to refer to a property of terms. Thus, Hom (2010), DiFranco (2014), and Bolinger (2015), among others, consider insults to be a subset of pejoratives, reserving “offense” to describe a property of acts. Such a distinction is not always used consistently. As I will focus entirely on the property of act, I will use “insult” and “offense” interchangeably, as well as the related verb phrases and adjectives.

  2. See Neu 2008: pp. 6–10. In Bolinger’s terminology (2015: p. 3), the relevant distinction is between the actual and the warranted offense, respectively.

  3. Commonly, the subject expresses when being in such a state, although nothing here hinges on it.

  4. See Ryle 1949: pp. 130, 149–153.

  5. The name he is generally referred to by the literary critics.

  6. There is a remaining possibility that Zverkov took an insult but did not express it due to his higher social standing. In order to draw the relevant distinction, I leave this possibility aside.

  7. For Hom, “chink” expresses a complex property, such as “ought to be subject to higher college admissions standards, and ought to be subject to exclusion from advancement to managerial positions, and…, because of being slanty-eyed, and devious, and good-at-laundering, and…, all because of being Chinese” (Hom 2010: p. 180).

  8. Again, I do not assume that Hom or other semantic theorists had this intention. Instead, I discuss Hom’s proposal as a starting point in building an otherwise plausible candidate for a theory of insult.

  9. Arguably, not every ignorance is excusable: one may insist that there are contexts in which the speaker should know that certain act would be deemed insulting (cf. Bolinger 2015: p. 11).

  10. Jeshion (2013: p. 331 n. 15) remarks that not even all slurs have neutral counterparts, citing “Gook,” used to refer to Korean and Vietnamese people, as one such example.

  11. This notion of standard does a double duty: it tells us both whether an act x satisfies the sufficient degree to be called insulting in the first place, as well as whether x is more insulting than another act y.

  12. On this analysis, [[insulting]]j,w = (λx. [λx. x appears insulting for the agent j in w). Note, however, that the subjectivist is not committed to the relativist twist concerning changes within intra-personal assessment. For example, if one finds x tasty at t1 but changes her mind at t2, the relativist insist that the relevant assessment is the latter one, obliging the subject to retract her original assertion (MacFarlane 2014: pp. 108–111, 306). In my opinion, the subjectivist about insults has sufficient argumentative maneuvers to avoid the relativist dictum here.

  13. Thanks to the anonymous referee who suggested this maneuver to me.

  14. For further sources on linking insults to natural selection, see Progovac and Locke (2009).

  15. I leave the possibility that some insulting acts may be considered as speech acts of their own, such as slurring (Anderson and Lepore 2013: pp. 351–352).

  16. Searle (1979, ix) only mentions this in passing, without actually advocating this view. In fact, he speaks of insinuation and hinting, rather than insults. I am here only taking his reference to construct a possible approach. I opted for this name in analogy with a view concerning perceptual content.

  17. I read Anderson and Lepore’s (2013) prohibitionism as advancing an objectivist proposal: since slurs and other pejoratives are prohibited words in a given society, by using them one violates the prohibition and thus generates offense.

  18. For the purposes of the paper, I do not wish to commit myself to any view concerning group beliefs, although the proposal resembles the inflationist view advocated by Schmitt (1994).

  19. Although it is possible to use slurs in a non-demeaning way, I here presuppose a typical case of slurring.

  20. Austin (1970:133) held that “to say that you are a cuckold may be to insult you, but it is also and at the same time to make a statement which is true or false” (see also Neu (2008: pp. 17–18)).

  21. Although this might be suggested by the phrase “demeaning to the addressee,” we are not interested in whether the addressee finds herself demeaned by the act. Instead, the stress is on “socially considered.”

  22. The example is adapted from Scorsese’s Goodfellas.

  23. See: https://web.archive.org/web/20110221124434/http://current.com/news-and-politics/88877763_dutch-man-jailed-for-insulting-the-queen.htm. Accessed on April 5, 2018.

References

  • Anderson, L., & Lepore, E. (2013). What did you call me? Slurs as prohibited words. Analytic Philosophy, 54(3), 350–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. Philosophical papers (p. 1970). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Berkovski, Y. S. (2016). A naturalist view of humiliation. Phenomenology and Mind, (11):78–86.

  • Berkovski, Y.S. (2017). A contextualist analysis of insults. In Dey, A. Kokinov, Leake, D. And turner, R. (Eds), Modeling and using context. Springer International Publishing, pp 661–674.

  • Bolinger, R. (2015). The pragmatics of slurs. Noûs, 51(3), 439–462. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12090.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Croom, A. (2011). Slurs. Language Sciences, 33(3), 343–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Culpeper, J. (2010). ‘Conventionalized Impoliteness Formulae’, in Journal of Pragmatics 42, 3232–3245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DiFranco, R. (2014). Pejorative language. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

  • Dostoyevsky, F. (1996). Notes from the underground. Translated by Constance Garnett. Project Gutenberg.

  • Hom, C. (2008). The semantics of racial epithets. Journal of Philosophy, 105, 416–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hom, C. (2010). Pejoratives. Philosophy Compass, 5(2), 164–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hom, C., & May, R. (2013). Moral and semantic innocence. Analytic Philosophy, 54(3), 293–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (2001). Meaning and Uselessness: How to Think about Derogatory Words. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 25, 128–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeshion, R. (2013). Expressivism and the offensiveness of slurs. Philosophical Perspectives, 27, 307–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeshion, R. (2016). Slur creation, bigotry formation: the power of expressivism. Phenomenology and Mind, 11, 130–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasersohn, P. (2005). Context dependence, disagreement, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 28(6), 643–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (2000). Philosophy of language. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2014). Assessment sensitivity: relative truth and its applications. Oxford University Press.

  • Meibauer, J. (2014). Bald-faced lies as acts of verbal aggression. Journal of Language Aggression and Conflict, 2(1), 127–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neu, J. (2008). Sticks and stones: the philosophy of insults. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popa-Wyatt, M. (2016). Not all slurs are equal. Phenomenology and Mind, 11, 150–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popa-Wyatt, M & Wyatt, J. L. (2017). Slurs, roles and power. Philosophical Studies. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0986-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Progovac, L. J., & Locke, J. (2009). The urge to merge: ritual insult and the evolution of syntax. Biolinguistics, 3(2–3), 337–354.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richard, M. (2008). When Truth Gives Out. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, F. (1994). The justification of group beliefs. In F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing epistemology: the social dimensions of knowledge (pp. 257–287). Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1979). Expression and meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sennet, A. (2016). Ambiguity. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy.

  • Sennet, A., & Copp, D. (2015). What kind of a mistake is it to use a slur? Philosophical Studies, 172(4), 1079–1104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephenson, T. (2007). Judge dependence, epistemic modals, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistic Philosophy, 30(4), 487–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I wish to thank Manuel García-Carpintero, Javier González de Prado Salas, Anton Markoč, Neri Marsili, Mihaela Popa, and David Rey for their comments on earlier versions of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ivan Milić.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author declares that there is no conflict of interest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Milić, I. “What Counts as an Insult?”. Acta Anal 33, 539–552 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-018-0353-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-018-0353-8

Keywords

Navigation