Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

A Theory of Standards for Intermediary Powers

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Jus Cogens Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is a widespread sense that intermediary institutions which made representative democracy function ever since the nineteenth century—political parties and free media—are presently undergoing profound structural transformations. We partly have trouble judging those transformations—will they destroy or strengthen democracy?—because we lack a set of clear normative standards for intermediary powers. The article suggests such standards: institutions should be accessible, accurate, autonomous, assessable, and accountable. A precondition for these attributes to be realized is financial transparency and the empowerment of citizens other than the owners of concentrated wealth to influence intermediary powers. Accordingly, the article also endorses a scheme to put financing into the hands of citizens themselves via a voucher scheme for both political parties and media.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Urbinati (2015); Pickard (2020)

  2. One of the curious developments of our time is that self-declared antiliberals—who seek to fake democracy—are careful to construct intermediary powers, including carefully controlled opposition parties and media (alongside simulacra of civil society more broadly). Russia under Putin is the most glaring example. For an illuminating comparative account, see Dobson (2013).

  3. Landemore (2020) and Guerrero (2014)

  4. On basic, quite possibly irreplaceable, functions of parties, see Aldrich (2011).

  5. The idea of a party system will be familiar to political theorists, the concept of media system possibly less so. The best—both analytically and historically—account remains Hallin and Mancini (2004).

  6. Disch (2015)

  7. Arendt (1977)

  8. White and Ypi (2016)

  9. AS Thomas Rid points out in his masterful history of disinformation, “some of the most vicious and effective measures in the history of covert action were designed to deliver entirely accurate information.” Rid (2020), 10

  10. Callison and Slobodian (2021)

  11. Rehfeld (2017)

  12. The classic account of the constructive turn in theories of representation is Saward (2010).

  13. Przeworksi and Sprague (1986)

  14. “The people lose patience,” The Economist, 29 August 2020.

  15. “A new world: Real opposition politics beckons for the first time,” The Economist, 4 July 2020.

  16. See also Garsten (2009) and the chapter on political equality in Scanlon (2018).

  17. “No joke as Brazil clown tops votes for Congress”, at: https://www.bbc.com/news/world-latin-america-11465127.

  18. Perney (1993)

  19. Such a line of reasoning can also be deployed against an antitrust approach to political competition: a duopoly is acceptable, as long as it beneficial to voters as “consumers of politics” (in parallel to Robert Bork’s argument that monopolies are acceptable as long as they benefit consumers) (see Bork 1978).

  20. Issacharoff and Pildes (1998)

  21. Zuboff (2019)

  22. See https://www.cs.cmu.edu/news/nearly-half-twitter-accounts-discussing-%E2%80%98reopening-america%E2%80%99-may-be-bots

  23. Cagé (2020), 239

  24. Garton Ash (2016), 204

  25. To be sure, the self-presentation of Fox News oscillates between objectivity (“we report, you decide”) and supposedly transparent partiality, as when Bill O’Reilly claimed to offer news and analysis from a distinct working class point of view (Peck 2019).

  26. Peck (2019), 69–70

  27. Van Biezen (2004) and Epstein (1986)

  28. I am indebted to Paul Starr for this point. The supervision of party and media systems should ideally be delegated to politically balanced or outright depoliticized boards. The task of such non-partisan bodies is not to reduce partisanship but to regulate political and professional rivalry. In practice, this will mean regulatory bodies staffed by figures associated with different political directions. Authoritarian populists like Poland’s PiS immediately moved to make the staffing of regulatory bodies a matter of simple parliamentary majorities.

  29. Katz and Mair (2018)

  30. Hansen (1999), 316

  31. In France and the UK, 10% of “megadonors” account for more than two thirds of the total of donations, according to Cagé’s study.

  32. Public funding is, not surprisingly, under attack from populists. M5S brought about a situation in which public funding of parties effectively stopped.

  33. Cagé (2020)

  34. Cagé (2020), 248

  35. Lessig (2011) as well as Ackerman and Ayres (2004)

  36. And, parties could still charge membership fees. These have never really sustained most parties, which is not to say that they don’t matter: laws about public funding can be tailored in such a way that they reward the ability to attract a large membership (Germany being an example).

  37. In New York City, 6 to 1 matching grants for small contributions encourage a similar attitude—except that contributions still tend to come from the top earners. In a better system, citizens wouldn’t feel their contribution has a real opportunity cost when money’s tight.

  38. Markovits (2019), 53. Zephyr Teachout claims that representatives spend between 30 and 70% of their time every week raising money, in Teachout (2014), 252.

  39. Sarah Kliff, “Seattle’s radical plan to fight big money in politics”, Vox, 5 November 2018, at: https://www.vox.com/2018/11/5/17058970/seattle-democracy-vouchers.

  40. To be sure, making perceptions of integrity a criterion is dangerous in contexts where integrity has been used as a weapon of exclusion of voters (Karlan 2016, 141–51).

  41. This proposal of a survey as a quasi-constitutional tool can be found in Ringen (2013), 202–3.

  42. As Bush put it at a fundraiser, surrounded entirely by elderly white men in tuxedos: “Some people call you the elite. I call you my base.” To be fair, the annual Al Smith dinner is supposed to feature self-deprecating jokes; yet, Bush’s supposed self-irony here (as so many of his other remarks delivered with a smirk) plainly revealed the truth. See https://www.c-span.org/video/?c4506459/user-clip-haves-mores [last accessed 24 May 2020].

  43. Critics of the private financing of politics often conflate different issues: one concern is corruption—which even a conservative Supreme Court recognizes as grounds for restrictions (albeit understood by Roberts and colleagues in the narrowest possible sense of a quid pro quo, not the more general dependency on a donor class which can set—and limit—the political agenda); another is equality of opportunity to influence politics, which is distinct from corruption: a self-financed billionaire—as Trump kept emphasizing during his first campaign—probably cannot be corrupted, but if only oligarchs can have a shot at running for office, political equality is obviously violated. Voucher schemes are likely to reduce dependence on the donor class, and they can certainly be justified as a step in the direction of equality of political opportunity, but they will not assure such equality as such (see Pevnik 2016).

  44. For such well-financed right-wing campaigns against the BBC, see Barwise and York (2020).

  45. The initiative still prompted the public service to undertake a number of what were presented as important reforms: more investment in information-gathering on the one hand, fewer texts freely available online on the other, so as not to engage in what private publishers had criticized as unfair competition.

  46. Cagé (2016)

  47. Mudge (2018), 74–5. Arguably Mirabeau was the first modern campaigning journalist. Gramsci would be another example. And maybe Boris Johnson (who, after all, combined a seat in parliament with the seat of the editor of The Spectator).

  48. There’s also the problem that supposedly non-partisan non-profit journalism in fact relies on partisan sources; see Konieczna (2018), 59–61.

  49. Rosen (2000)

  50. See his remarks at https://pressthink.org/2019/06/key-steps-in-the-citizens-agenda-style-of-campaign-coverage/

  51. See O’Neill (n.d.)

  52. Issacharoff (2017), Schlozman and Rosenfeld (2019), Meyer (2017)

  53. It also must be possible to come to some reasoned judgement about its internal pluralism (even if we saw that pluralism is a tricky criterion: it’s possible to see whether there’s a real possibility for debate, but we can’t mandate that partisans or journalists, for that matter, disagree).

  54. Gerbaudo (2019)

  55. Article 21 of the German Basic Law states: “The political parties participate in the formation of the political will of the people. They may be freely established. Their internal organization must conform to democratic principles. They must publicly account for their assets and for the sources and use of their funds as well as assets.” The Party Law in turn regulates the specifics of internal democracy to a degree of detail that one might well consider as an infringement of the right of free association. In general, constitutionalizing parties has become the norm in Europe, see the excellent overview by van Biezen (2012).

  56. On the wider significance of intra-party democracy, see also Scheppele (2018).

  57. Of course, something like the Fairness Doctrine can also be weaponized by those who wish to use “both-sides”-journalism to obfuscate particular matters. The demand to present ‘both sides’ on tobacco and global warming are the well-known examples (see Oreskes and Conway 2010).

  58. Matsusaka (2020)

  59. Winters (2011)

References

  • Ackerman B, Ayres I (2004) Voting with dollars: a new paradigm for campaign finance. Yale University Press, New Haven

  • Aldrich JH (2011) Why parties? A second look. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt H (1977) Between past and future. Penguin, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise P, York P (2020) The war against the BBC. Penguin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bork RH (1978) The antitrust paradox. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cagé J (2016) Saving the media: capitalism, crowdfunding, and democracy, trans. Arthur Goldhammer. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cagé J (2020) The price of democracy: how money shapes politics and what to do about it, trans. Patrick Camiller. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Callison W, Slobodian Q (2021) Coronapolitics from the Reichstag to the Capitol Boston Review, at: http://bostonreview.net/politics/william-callison-quinn-slobodian-coronapolitics-reichstag-capitol

  • Disch L (2015) The ‘constructivist turn’ in democratic representation: a normative dead end? Constellations 22:487–495

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobson WJ (2013) The dictator’s learning curve. Anchor, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein LD (1986) Political parties in the American Mold. The University of Wisconsin Press, Madison

    Google Scholar 

  • Garsten B (2009) Representative government and popular sovereignty. In: Shapiro I, Stokes SC, Wood EJ, Kirshner AS (eds) Political representation. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 90–110

    Google Scholar 

  • Garton Ash T (2016) Free speech. Atlantic, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerbaudo P (2019) The digital party: political organisation and online democracy. Pluto, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Guerrero AA (2014) Against elections: The lottocratic alternative. Philos Public Aff 42:135–178

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hallin DC, Mancini P (2004) Comparing media systems: three models of media and politics. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen M (1999) The Athenian democracy in the age of Demosthenes, trans. J. A. Crook. University of Oklahoma Press, Norman

    Google Scholar 

  • Issacharoff S (2017) Outsourcing politics: the hostile takeover of our hollowed-out political parties. Houston Law Review 54:845–880

    Google Scholar 

  • Issacharoff S, Pildes RH (1998) Politics as markets: partisan lockups of the democratic process. Stanford Law Rev 50:643–717

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karlan P (2016) Citizens deflected: electoral integrity and political reform. In: Post Robert C (ed) Citizens divided. Harvard UP, Cambridge, pp 141–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz R, Mair P (2018) Democracy and the cartelization of political parties. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Konieczna M (2018) Journalism without profit: making news when the market fails. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Landemore H (2020) Open democracy: reinventing popular rule for the twenty-first century. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lessig L (2011) Republic, lost: how money corrupts congress—and a plan to stop it. Twelve, New York

  • Markovits D (2019) The meritocracy trap: how America’s foundational myth feeds inequality, dismantles the middle class, and devours the elite. Penguin Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Matsusaka JG (2020) Let the people rule: how direct democracy can meet the populist challenge. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer J (2017) Dark money. Anchor, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mudge SL (2018) Leftism reinvented: Western parties from socialism to neoliberalism. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Müller JW (2021) Democracy rules. Penguin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Peck R (2019) Fox populism: branding conservatism as working class. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Perney D (1993) Dimensions of the right to vote: the write-in vote, Donald Duck, and voting booth speech written-off. Missouri Law Review 58:945–968

    Google Scholar 

  • Pevnik R (2016) The anatomy of debate about campaign finance. J Polit 78:1184–1195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickard V (2020) Democracy without Journalism? Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Przeworksi A, Sprague J (1986) Paper stones: a history of electoral socialism. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill O (n.d.) The rights of journalism and the needs of audiences at: http://kingsreview.co.uk/articles/the-rights-of-journalism-and-the-needs-of-audiences/. Accessed 1 Mar 2019

  • Oreskes N, Conway EM (2010) Merchants of doubt: how a handful of scientists obscured the truth on issues from tobacco smoke to global warming. Bloomsbury, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rehfeld A (2017) On representing. J Polit Philos 26:216–239

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rid T (2020) Active measures: the secret history of disinformation and political warfare. FSG, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ringen S (2013) Nation of devils: democratic leadership and the problem of obedience. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen J (2000) Questions and answers about public journalism. Journal Stud 1:679–694

    Google Scholar 

  • Saward M (2010) The representative claim. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon T (2018) Why does inequality matter? Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheppele KL (2018) The party’s over. In: Levinson S, Graber M, Tushnet M (eds) Constitutional democracy in crisis? Oxford University Press, New York, pp 495–513

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlozman D, Rosenfeld S (2019) The hollow parties. In: Lee FE, McCarty N (eds) Can America govern itself? Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 120–50

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Teachout Z (2014) Corruption in America. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Urbinati N (2015) A revolt against intermediary bodies. Constellations 22:477–485

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Biezen I (2004) Political parties as public utilities. Party Polit 10:701–722

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Biezen I (2012) Constitutionalizing party democracy. Br J PolitSci 42:187–212

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White J, Ypi L (2016) The meaning of partisanship. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Winters J (2011) Oligarchy. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zuboff S (2019) The age of surveillance capitalism. Public Affairs, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This essay draws heavily on my forthcoming Democracy Rules (2021). For comments on how to think about standards for intermediary institutions, I owe thanks to a large number of friends and colleagues. Particularly useful feedback on an earlier incarnation of this paper was provided by Carlo Accetti Invernizzi, Peter Giraudo, and John Morijn. I also benefited from the comments of an anonymous reviewer for the journal.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jan-Werner Müller.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Müller, JW. A Theory of Standards for Intermediary Powers. Jus Cogens 3, 141–158 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s42439-021-00040-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s42439-021-00040-7

Keywords

Navigation