Skip to main content

Becoming a Good Human Being: Aristotle on Virtue and Its Cultivation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Handbuch Tugend und Tugendethik

Abstract

In deliberate contrast to the ethical intellectualism of Socrates, Aristotle develops a complex conception of virtues as character traits which are closely tied to the different elements and stages of their cultivation: in the gradual process of becoming good, ‘learning by doing’ is the central cornerstone for establishing a close connectivity between emotion and reason as well as between desire, decision and right action. Virtue as a perfection of human nature engenders the best possible integration of irrational striving with reason in the soul and is thus the constitutive component of human flourishing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    I will not take into account the Magna Moralia, another ethical treatise which is attributed to Aristotle but was probably not written by himself.

  2. 2.

    All quotations from Aristotle are taken from Barnes 1984, with the notable difference that aretē is translated as “virtue” and not as “excellence”.

  3. 3.

    Accordingly, Aristotle shows the tendency to use aretē without further specification as a shorthand expression for ethical or character virtue. I will follow this usage.

  4. 4.

    There are also other ‘losers’ in Aristotle’s ethics, i.e. character types who cannot make moral progress (Curzer 2012, Chap. 17).

  5. 5.

    This is one of the reasons why Aristotle deliberately turns his back on the Socratic notion of a virtue-technē (Angier 2010, Chap. 2): He does not subscribe to the idea that knowledge of the good is sufficient for moral motivation.

  6. 6.

    Another interesting approach to solve the problem of acquiring moral motivation is provided by Fossheim (2006), who points to mimēsis as habituation of the fine in musical performances. This idea ties in nicely with the basic Aristotelian structure of learning by doing (and not by simply being affected).

  7. 7.

    For this translation see Lorenz 2009, pp. 196–197.

  8. 8.

    This seems to tie the mean closely to a single scale, but it is also possible to define courage and the two extremes surrounding it in terms of the emotion of confidence and not only with regard to fear, as Aristotle himself recognises (NE 1107a33). Yet then there are more than two opposites involved.

  9. 9.

    This reading is to a certain extent indebted to the conception of metriopatheia, which in Aristotle’s school, the Peripatos, was later pitted against the Stoic ideal of apatheia, i.e. the extirpation of passions in the wise person.

  10. 10.

    If this were the case Aristotle would probably have used pros tina instead of pros hēmas (Brown 1997, p. 89).

  11. 11.

    For further passages in NE and EE see Moss (2011) with a thorough discussion.

  12. 12.

    It is an open discussion of whether this more substantial understanding of the role of phronēsis commits Aristotle to a ‘grand-end view’ according to which practical wisdom operates with a comprehensive blueprint of the overall human good in determining human conduct (Kraut 1993) or if phronēsis only deliberates about more limited local ends (Broadie 1991, pp. 198–202).

  13. 13.

    This conjunction does not pertain to the other intellectual virtues: one can be wise in theoretical matters (sophos) without possessing practical wisdom (NE 1141b3–8).

  14. 14.

    It is better to avoid the often used expression ‘unity thesis’ for the relationship between the virtues in Aristotle: this formula fits only for the Socratic point of view, according to which all virtues are ultimately identical. Aristotle, instead, argues for a ‘reciprocity thesis’.

  15. 15.

    The reciprocity thesis might also be conceived of as a kind of regulative ideal (Russell 2014, pp. 215–216).

  16. 16.

    As does Korsgaard (1996, esp. p. 205); contra: Whiting (2002). There are some ‘Kantian’ readings of Aristotle’s notion of virtue, apart from Korsgaard also by Sherman (1997) and Hursthouse (1999, Chaper 4). However, Aristotle does not share Kant’s overriding concern for morality (in the modern sense) and would probably regard Kantian virtues as mere forms of strength of will.

  17. 17.

    For kalon as the object of virtuous choice see, e.g., NE 1115b12–13. See also Cooper (1999, pp. 264–279) for the three kinds of desires which correspond to the fine, the advantageous and the pleasurable.

  18. 18.

    The attempt by Gardiner (2004) to distinguish between basic and non-basic virtues in Aristotle lacks sufficient textual backing.

  19. 19.

    For lists of the Aristotelian virtues and their spheres see Gottlieb (2009, p. 112) and Curzer (2018, p. 115).

References

  • Angier, Tom. 2010. Technē in Aristotle’s ethics: Crafting the moral life. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, Jonathan (ed.). 1984. The Complete Works of Aristotle. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broadie, Sarah. 1991. Ethics with Aristotle. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Lesley. 1997. What is “the mean relative to us” in Aristotle’s ethics? Phronesis 42: 77–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Lesley. 2014. Why is Aristotle’s virtue of character a mean? Taking Aristotle at his word (NE ii 6). In The Cambridge companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Ronald Polansky, 64–80. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnyeat, Miles. 1980. Aristotle on learning to be good. In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty, 69–92. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charpenel, Eduardo. 2017: Ethos und Praxis: Der Charakterbegriff bei Aristoteles. Freiburg i. Br., München: Karl Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coope, Ursula. 2012. Why does Aristotle think that ethical virtue is required for practical wisdom? Phronesis 57: 142–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, John. 1999. Reason and emotion. Essays on moral psychology and ethical theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curzer, Howard. 2005. How good people do bad things: Aristotle on the misdeeds of the virtuous. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 28: 233–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curzer, Howard. 2012. Aristotle and the virtues. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Curzer, Howard. 2018. Aristotle and moral virtue. In The Oxford handbook of virtue, ed. Nancy E. Snow, 104–129. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fossheim, Hallvard. 2006. Habituation as mimesis. In Values and virtues. Aristotelianism in contemporary ethics, ed. Timothy D. J. Chappell, 105–117. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardiner, Stephen. 2004. Aristotle’s basic and non-basic virtues. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 20: 261–295.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gill, Mary Louise. 2015. Virtue and reason in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. In Bridging the gap between Aristotle’s science and ethics, eds. Devin Henry and Karen Margrethe Nielsen, 94–110. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb, Paula. 2009. The virtue of Aristotle’s ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Halbig, Christoph. 2013. Der Begriff der Tugend und die Grenzen der Tugendethik. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halper, Edward. 1999. The unity of the virtues in Aristotle. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 17: 115–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann, Magdalena. 2010. Der Standard des Guten bei Aristoteles: Regularität im Unbestimmten. Freiburg i. Br: Karl Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, Rosalind. 1999. On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, Rosalind. 2006. The central doctrine of the mean. In The Blackwell guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Richard Kraut, 96–115. Chichester/Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson, D. S. 1986. The virtues of Aristotle. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irwin, Terence. 1988. Disunity in the Aristotelian virtues. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 7: 61–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irwin, Terence. 2010. The sense and reference of Kalon in Aristotle. Classical Philology 105: 381–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, Christine. 1996. From duty and for the sake of the noble. In Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics. Rethinking happiness and duty, eds. Stephen P. Engstrom and Jennifer Whiting, 203–236. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, Richard. 1993. In defense of the grand end. Ethics 103: 361–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, Richard. 2012. Aristotle on becoming good: Habituation, reflection, and perception. In The Oxford handbook of Aristotle, ed. Christopher Shields, 529–557. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson, Kristján. 2007. Aristotle, emotions, and education. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawrence, Gavin. 2013. Human excellence in character and intellect. In A companion to Aristotle, ed. Georgios Anagnostopoulos, 419–441. Chichester/Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lear, Gabriel Richardson. 2006. Aristotle on moral virtue and the fine. In The Blackwell guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Richard Kraut, 116–136. Chichester/Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leighton, Stephen. 1992. Relativizing moral excellence in Aristotle. Apeiron 25: 49–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, James. 1999. Aristotle on the biological roots of human virtue: The natural history of natural virtue. In Biology and the foundation of ethics, eds. Jane Maienschein and Michael Ruse, 10–31. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leunissen, Mariska. 2012. Aristotle on natural character and its implications for moral development. Journal of the History of Philosophy 50: 507–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leunissen, Mariska. 2017. From natural character to moral virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lockwood, Thornton C. 2013. Habituation, habit, and character in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. In A history of habit. From Aristotle to Bourdieu, eds. Tom Sparrow and Adam Hutchinson, 19–36. Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • London, Alex. 2001. Moral knowledge and the acquisition of virtue in Aristotle’s Nicomachean and Eudemian Ethics. Review of Metaphysics 54: 553–583.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz, Hendrik. 2009. Virtue of character in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 37: 177–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1996. Deliberation and moral development in Aristotle’s ethics. In Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics. Rethinking happiness and duty, eds. Stephen P. Engstrom and Jennifer Whiting, 19–35. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moss, Jessica. 2011. “Virtue makes the goal right”: Virtue and Phronesis in Aristotle’s Ethics. Phronesis 56: 204–261.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Anselm. 2004. Aristotle’s conception of ethical and natural virtue: How the unity thesis sheds light on the doctrine of the mean. In Was ist das für den Menschen Gute? Menschliche Natur und Güterlehre, eds. Jan Szaif and Matthias Lutz-Bachmann, 18–53. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Jörn. 2006. Physis und Ethos. Der Naturbegriff bei Aristoteles und seine Relevanz für die Ethik. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Jörn. 2013. Wann kann man ein Leben glücklich nennen? Aristoteles und das Solon-Problem. In Glück, Tugend und Zeit. Aristoteles über die Zeitstruktur des guten Lebens, ed. Walter Mesch, 41–62. Stuttgart: J.B. Metzler.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Jörn. 2014. Was Aristotle an ethical determinist? Reflections on his theory of action and voluntariness. In Fate, providence and moral responsibility in ancient, medieval and early modern thought, eds. Pieter d’Hoine and Gerd van Riel, 75–99. Leuven: Leuven University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Jörn. 2019a. Spot the differences! The hidden philosophical anthropology in Aristotle’s biological writings. In Aristotle’s anthropology, eds. Geert Keil and Nora Kreft, 118–139. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Jörn. 2019b. ‘Learning by doing’? Aristotle on the habituation of moral character. In Aristotle on logic and nature, ed. Jan-Ivar Lindén, 177–209. Leuven: Peeters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 1987. Non-relative virtues: An Aristotelian approach. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 13: 32–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rapp, Christof. 2006. What use is Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean? In The virtuous life in Greek ethics, ed. Burkhard Reis, 99–126. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Daniel. 2014. Phronesis and the virtues (NE vi 12–13). In The Cambridge companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Ronald Polansky, 203–220. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Daniel. 2015. Aristotle on cultivating virtue. In Cultivating virtue, ed. Nancy E. Snow, 17–48. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Santas, Gerasimos. 1996. The structure of Aristotle’s ethical theory: Is it teleological or a virtue ethics? Topoi 15: 59–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sherman, Nancy. 1989. The fabric of character. Aristotle’s theory of virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherman, Nancy. 1997. Making a necessity of virtue. Aristotle and Kant on virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, Peter. 1992. Contemporary virtue ethics and Aristotle. Review of Metaphysics 45: 503–524.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji, Richard. 1980. Aristotle on the role of intellect in virtue. In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty, 201–219. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Telfer, Elizabeth. 1989/1990. The unity of moral virtues in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 90: 35–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tessitore, Aristide. 1996. Reading Aristotle’s ethics. Virtue, rhetoric, and political philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urmson, J. O. 1973. Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean. American Philosophical Quarterly 10: 223–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasiliou, Iakovos. 1996. The role of good upbringing in Aristotle’s ethics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56: 771–797.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whiting, Jennifer. 2002. Eudaimonia, external results, and choosing virtuous actions for themselves. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 270–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jörn Müller .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Fachmedien Wiesbaden GmbH, ein Teil von Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Müller, J. (2021). Becoming a Good Human Being: Aristotle on Virtue and Its Cultivation. In: Halbig, C., Timmermann, F. (eds) Handbuch Tugend und Tugendethik. Springer VS, Wiesbaden. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-658-24466-8_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-658-24466-8_10

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer VS, Wiesbaden

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-658-24465-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-658-24466-8

  • eBook Packages: Social Science and Law (German Language)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics