Skip to main content
Log in

Functional Reduction and Mental Causation

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Over the past few decades, Jaegwon Kim has argued that non-reductive physicalism is an inherently unstable position. In his view, the most serious problem is that non-reductive physicalism leads to type epiphenomenalism—the causal inefficacy of mental properties. Kim suggests that we can salvage mental causation by endorsing functional reduction. Given the fact that Kim’s goal in formulating functional reduction is to provide a robust account of mental causation it would be surprising if his position implies eliminativism about mental properties or leads to a view that is similar to one of the versions of non-reductive physicalism that he criticizes. We will show that depending on how certain key claims are interpreted, there are reasons for thinking functional reduction has these implications, in which case either Kim fails to provide a robust account of mental causation or there is reason to suspect that some of his criticisms of non-reductive physicalism are misguided.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Kim defines this principle as follows: “No single event can have more than one sufficient cause occurring at any given time—unless it is a genuine case of causal overdetermination” (Kim 2005, p. 42).

  2. Kim assumes that closure is acceptable to advocates of non-reductive physicalism. We will not challenge this assumption. He defines closure as follows: “If a physical event has a cause that occurs a t, it has a physical cause that occurs at t” (Kim 2005, p. 43).

  3. In his early work on events, Kim leaves open the possibility that properties of events can be re-described (Kim 1993b, p. 43).

  4. This research was supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.

References

  • Antony, L. (1989). Anomalous monism and the problem of explanatory force. Philosophical Review, 98(2), 153–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2003). Do causal powers drain away? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67(1), 133–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • David, M. (1997). Kim’s functionalism. Noûs, 31, 133–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1970). Mental events. In L. Foster & J. Swanson (Eds.), Experience and theory. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press. Reprinted in Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events (pp. 207–224). Oxford, Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1993). Thinking causes. In J. Heil & A. Mele (Eds.), Mental causation (pp. 3–17). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibb, S. (2006). Why Davidson is not a property epiphenomenalist. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 14(3), 407–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gozzano, S. (2003). Second-order properties: Why Kim’s reduction does not work. Logic and Philosophy of Science, 1(1), 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hess, P. (1981). Actions, reasons, and humean causes. Analysis, 41(March), 77–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Honderich, T. (1982). The argument for anomalous monism. Analysis, 42(January), 59–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. (1989). Mental quausation. Philosophical Perspectives, 3, 47–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. (1997). Kim on mental causation and causal exclusion. Nous-Supplement: Philosophical Perspectives, 11, 165–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (2002). From reduction to type-type identity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65(3), 644–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P. (2002). Some problems for reductive physicalism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65(3), 648–654.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, M. (2005). Against functional reductionism in cognitive science. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 19(3), 319–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1984). Epiphenomenal and supervenient causation. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 9, 257–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1990). Explanatory exclusion and the problem of mental causation. In E. Villanueva (Ed.), Information, semantics, and epistemology (pp. 36–56). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1992). Multiple realization and the metaphysics of reduction. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52(1), 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1993a). Can supervenience and ‘non-strict laws’ save anomalous monism? In J. Heil & A. Mele (Eds.), Mental causation (pp. 19–26). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J (1993b). Events as Property Exemplification. In J. Kim, Supervenience and Mind (pp. 33–52). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1998). Mind in a physical world. Cambridge: MIT Press/Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1999). Making sense of emergence. Philosophical Studies, 95(1–2), 3–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2002). Responses. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65(3), 671–680.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2005). Physicalism, or something near enough. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2006). Philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2008). Reduction and reductive explanation. In J. Hohwy & J. Kallestrup (Eds.), Being reduced (pp. 93–114). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2009). Mental causation. In B. McLaughlin, A. Beckermann, & S. Walter (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mind (pp. 29–52). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marras, A. (2003). Methodological and ontological aspects of the mental causation problem. In S. Walter & H. D. Heckmann (Eds.), Physicalism and mental causation (pp. 243–264). Exeter: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B. (1993). On Davidson’s response to the charge of epiphenomenalism. In J. Heil & A. Mele (Eds.), Mental causation (pp. 27–40). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pineda, D. (2002). The causal exclusion puzzle. European Journal of Philosophy, 10(1), 26–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robb, D. (2008). Review of Harbecke. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, 9.

  • Rueger, A. (2004). Reduction, autonomy, and causal exclusion among physical properties. Synthese, 139(1), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sabates, M. (2002). Review of mind in a physical world. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65(3), 663–670.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1984). Mind–body interaction and supervenient causation. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 9(1), 271–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoutland, F. (1985). Davidson on intentional behavior. In E. Lepore & B. P. McLaughlin (Eds.), Actions and events: Perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson (pp. 44–59). New York: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walter, S. (2008). The supervenience argument, overdetermination, and causal drainage. Philosophical Psychology, 21(5), 673–696.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dwayne Moore.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Moore, D., Campbell, N. Functional Reduction and Mental Causation. Acta Anal 25, 435–446 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-010-0107-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-010-0107-8

Keywords

Navigation