Skip to main content
Log in

A Pragmatic Dissolution of Curry’s Paradox

  • Published:
Logica Universalis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Although formal analysis provides us with interesting tools for treating Curry’s paradox, it certainly does not exhaust every possible reading of it. Thus, we suggest that this paradox should be analysed with non-formal tools coming from pragmatics. In this way, using Grice’s logic of conversation, we will see that Curry’s sentence can be reinterpreted as a peculiar conditional sentence implying its own consequent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A similar paradox in physics is posed by the question: Could an unstoppable force (i.e. one that nothing can resist) move an immovable object?

  2. As for its philosophical relevance, it is worth noting that this paradox is Paul Kabay’s [33, ch. 2] main argument for trivialism, the thesis that all sentences are true.

  3. In Piscoya’s proposal, a paradox is technically defined as ‘a special type of contradiction constituted by a proposition P whose truth implies its falsity and whose falsity implies its truth’ [47, p. 205] (cf. [24, p. 233]).

  4. We justify the equivalence between this sentence and Curry’s expressions in Sect. 6

  5. Incidentally, my bachelor’s thesis deals with the Liar’s paradox [40] and my master’s with Russell’s [41]. This paper corresponds to my doctoral dissertation [43].

  6. This obviously raises the question of whether we can apply classical logical rules to self-referential statements, but this is beyond the scope of this investigation.

  7. Restall and Rogerson [53] play with the logical form of such expressions. For instance, let \(C \rightarrow _{0}A\) be equivalent to C, and \(C \rightarrow _{n + 1}A\) to \((C \rightarrow _{n}A) \rightarrow A\). Hence, whenever \(n = 0\), the expression \(C \rightarrow _{1}A\) would be equivalent to \((C \rightarrow _{0}A) \rightarrow A\), i.e., to \(C \rightarrow A\). Moreover, whenever \(n = 1\), the expression \(C \rightarrow _{2}A\) would be equivalent to \((C \rightarrow _{1} A) \rightarrow A\), i.e., to \((C \rightarrow A) \rightarrow A\). If we go on with this process, can make Curry’s conditional larger and larger, for we can indefinitely substitute C by \(C \rightarrow A\). This procedure is already found in Moh Shaw-Kwei [55], only with a different notation. The notation we use here is an adaptation of Moh Shaw-Kwei’s made by Robles and Méndez [54].

  8. A proof analogous to this is made by Meyer et al. [37].

  9. In Beall’s formalisation [5, p. 30], the set of normal worlds is defined as follows: \(1 \in v(A \rightarrow B,w) \leftrightarrow \) for ever world \(w' \in W,\) if \(1 \in v(A,w')\), then \(1 \in v(B,w')\). The set of non-normal worlds, instead, is defined as follows: \(1 \in v(A \rightarrow B,w) \leftrightarrow \) for every pair of worlds \(\langle w',w' \rangle \) such that \(wR \langle w',w' \rangle \), if \(1 \in v(A,w')\), then \(1 \in v(B,w')\).

  10. For instance, the following ones: verum sequitur ex quodlibet, which means that a true proposition is implied by any other: \(A \rightarrow (B \rightarrow A)\); ex falso quodlibet, which means that a false proposition implies any other: \(\lnot A \rightarrow (A \rightarrow B)\); necesarium sequitur ex quodlibet, which means that a necessary proposition is strictly implied by any other: \(\Box A \Rightarrow (B \Rightarrow A)\); and ex impossibile quodlibet, which means that an impossible proposition strictly implies any other: \(\lnot \Diamond A \Rightarrow (A \Rightarrow B)\).

  11. For an analysis of Curry’s paradox from a relevance logic framework, see Foukzon [20].

  12. A comparison is possible between this paradox and the Banach-Tarski paradox [3]. In the latter, from a sphere it is possible to obtain two of the same size as the original one just by rearranging its component parts in a special way. The Banach-Tarski paradox is a geometrical theorem and does not represent a logical contradiction, although it does contradict our common sense. It is in this sense that it is very similar to Curry’s paradox.

  13. The maxims of mode (it clearly increases the obscurity of the conversation by stating, ‘If I am right, ...’) and relevance (the conditional with self-reference in the antecedent is simply not relevant in a conversation) are also breached by Curry’s sentence. For the purposes of this paper, though, it is enough to show how at least one of Grice’s maxims is breached.

  14. This Cartesian expression has been the subject of much discussion. In this paper, we assume that it cannot be a conditional since, in order to be, one needs not to think first. Rather, both occur at the same time. However, it is recognised that the expression, ‘It is not true that I think and that I am not’, is a better formulation than the original, ‘If I think, then I am’, even though they are logically equivalent.

References

  1. Anderson, A.R., Belnap, N.: Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1975)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Bacon, A.: Curry’s paradox and \(\omega \)-inconsistency. Stud. Logica. 101(1), 1–9 (2011)

  3. Banach, S., Tarski, A.: Sur la décomposition des ensembles de points en parties respectivement congruentes. Fundam. Math. 6, 244–277 (1924)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Barrero, T., Carnielli, W.: Tableaux sin refutación. Matemáticas: Enseñanza Universitaria 8(2), 81–99 (2005)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Beall, J.C.: Spandrels of Truth. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2009)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  6. Beall, J.C., Murzi, J.: Two flavors of Curry’s paradox. J. Philos. 110(3), 143–165 (2013)

  7. Beall, J.C., Shapiro, L.: Curry’s paradox, In: Zalta, E.N. (ed.) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Winter (2018). https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/curry-paradox

  8. Beall, J.C., Brady, R., Hazen, A., Priest, G., Restall, G.: Relevant restricted quantification. J. Philos. Logic 35, 587–598 (2006)

  9. Bobenrieth, A.: Inconsistencias, por qué no? Tercer Mundo, Un estudio filosófico sobre la lógica paraconsistente (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Bocheński, I.M.: A History of Formal Logic. University of Notre Dame Press (1961)

  11. Carrara, M., Martino, E.: Curry’s paradox. A new argument for trivialism. Logic Philos. Sci. 9(1), 199–206 (2011)

  12. Clark, M.: Paradoxes from A to Z. Routledge (2012)

  13. Cook, R.: Paradoxes. Polity (2013)

  14. Curry, H.: The inconsistency of certain formal logics. J. Symb. Logic 7, 115–117 (1942)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  15. Díez Martínez, A.: Introducción a la filosofía de la lógica. Universidad Nacional de Educación a Distancia (2013)

  16. Echave, D., Urquijo, M., Guibourg, R.: Lógica, proposición y norma. Astrea (2008)

  17. Ferrater Mora, J.: Qué es la lógica? Columba (1960)

  18. Ferrater Mora, J.: Diccionario de filosofía. Ariel (1994)

  19. Field, H.: Saving Truth from Paradox. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2008)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  20. Foukzon, J.: Relevant first-order logic LP\(^{\#}\) and Curry’s paradox. Pure Appl. Math. J. 4, 6–12 (2015)

  21. Frege, G.: Begriffsschrift. Louis Nebert (1879)

  22. Frege, G.: In: Geach, P., Black, M. (eds.), Philosophical Writings. Blackwell (1952)

  23. García Suárez, A.: Modos de significar. Una introducción temática a la filosofía del lenguaje, Tecnos (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  24. García Zárate, Ó.: Lógica. CEPREDIM (2007)

  25. Gamut, L.T.F.: Logic, Language, and Meaning, vol. 1. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1991)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  26. Goldstein, L.: Epimenides and Curry. Analysis 463, 117–121 (1986)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  27. Goldstein, L., Brennan, A., Deutsch, M., Lau, J.Y.F.: Logic: Key Concepts in Philosophy. Bloomsbury (2005)

  28. Grice, P.: Logic and Conversation. In: Colé P., Morgan J.L. (ed.): Syntax and Semantics. Vol. 3, pp. 41–59. Academic Press (1975)

  29. Gupta, A., Belnap, N.: The Revision Theory of Truth. MIT Press (1993)

  30. Hamblin, Ch.L.: Fallacies. Methuen (1970)

  31. Haverkate, H.: Las máximas de Grice y los diálogos del Quijote. In: Villegas, J. (coord.), Actas Irvine-92. vol. 1, pp. 179–186. Academic Press (1992)

  32. Hegenberg, L., Ferreira, M.: Novo dicionário de lógica. Pós-Moderno (2005)

  33. Kabay, P.D.: A Defense of Trivialism (PhD thesis). The University of Melbourne (2008)

  34. Kleene, S.C.: On a notation for ordinal numbers. J. Symb. Logic 3, 150–155 (1938)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Kripke, S.A.: Outline of a theory of truth. J. Philos. 72, 690–716 (1975)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Łukowski, P.: Paradoxes. Springer, Berlin (2011)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  37. Meyer, R., Routley, R., Dunn, J.: Curry’s paradox. Analysis 39, 124–128 (1979)

  38. Miranda, H., Guzmán, M.: Análisis pragmático de las máximas griceanas en textos orales y escritos. Literatura y Lingüística 26, 229–246 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Miró Quesada Cantuarias, F.: Las lógicas heterodoxas y el problema de la unidad de la lógica. In: Rosales Papa, D. (ed.) Lógica: Aspectos formales y filosóficos, pp. 13–43. Pontificia Universidad Católica del Perú (1978)

  40. Mora Ramirez, R.F.: Análisis lógico de la paradoja de Epiménides (Bachelor’s thesis). Universidad Nacional Mayor de San Marcos (2014)

  41. Mora Ramirez, R.F.: La evolución de la paradoja de las clases propuesta por Bertrand Russell (Master’s thesis). Universidad Nacional Mayor de San Marcos (2016)

  42. Mora Ramirez, R.F.: El valor de la lógica: Ensayo apologético. Editorial Académica Española (2019)

  43. Mora Ramirez, R.F.: La paradoja de Curry: un examen crítico (Doctoral thesis). Universidad Nacional Mayor de San Marcos (2020)

  44. Neurath, O., Hahn, H., Carnap, R.: The Scientific Conception of the World: The Vienna Circle. In: Neurath, M., Cohen, R.S. (eds.) Empiricism and Sociology, pp. 299–318. D. Reidel (1973)

  45. Pailos, F.: La paradoja de Curry. In: Barrio, E. (ed.), Paradojas, paradojas y más paradojas, pp. 41–52. College Publications (2014)

  46. Perelman, Ch.: Formal Logic and Informal Logic. In: Meyer, M. (ed.) From Metaphysics to Rhetoric, pp. 9–14. Dordrecht (1989)

  47. Piscoya, L.: Investigación científica y educacional. Amaru (1995)

  48. Priest, G.: What is non-normal world? Logique et Analyse 139–40, 291–302 (1992)

  49. Priest, G.: In: Contradiction. Oxford University Press (2006)

  50. Priest, G.: Doubt Truth to Be a Liar. Oxford University Press (2006)

  51. Ramsey, F.: Philosophical Papers. Cambridge University Press (1990)

  52. Rescher, N.: Paradoxes. Carus (2001)

  53. Restall, G., Rogerson, S.: Routes to triviality. J Philos. Logic 33, 421–436 (2004)

  54. Robles, G., Méndez, J.: Curry’s paradox, generalized the modus ponens axiom and depth relevance. Stud. Logica. 102(1), 185–217 (2014)

  55. Shaw-Kwei, M.: Logical paradoxes for many-valued systems. J. Symb. Logic 19(1), 37–39 (1954)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  56. Uxía, M.: Pragmática. In: Vega, L., Olmos, P. (eds.), Compendio de lógica, argumentación y retórica, pp. 473–478. Trotta (2012)

  57. Wittgenstein, L.: Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Kegan Paul (1922)

  58. Wittgenstein, L.: Philosophical Investigations. Macmillan (1953)

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to sincerely thank the members of the jury of the Francisco Miró Quesada Logic Prize 2021: Verónica Borja Macías, Walter A. Carnielli, Aldo Figallo-Orellano, and David Villena Saldaña. I would also like to thank Professor Óscar García Zárate, who was the advisor of the doctoral thesis on which this article was based [43]. Finally, I would like to thank Luis Felipe Bartolo Alegre, organiser of the prize, for having translated this document and converted it into LaTeX.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rafael Félix Mora Ramirez.

Additional information

To the young students of the humanities that strive every day to show the world that we can have a pure vocation for knowledge beyond profit, and also to those who hope that one day we can live in peace, without privilege, without hatred, and, above all, in harmony with nature.

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Translated by Luis Felipe Bartolo Alegre (UNMSM)

Winner of the First Edition of the Francisco Miró Quesada Cantuarias Logic Prize (Peru 2021) and contestant of the 2nd World Logic Prizes Contest at UNILOG’2022.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mora Ramirez, R.F. A Pragmatic Dissolution of Curry’s Paradox. Log. Univers. 16, 149–175 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-022-00294-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-022-00294-9

Keywords

Mathematics Subject Classification

Navigation