1 Concept originalism (CO)

According to Sainsbury and Tye (S&T) (2011, 2012), Tye (2014), and Sainsbury (2015), “atomic concepts are to be individuated by their historical origins, as opposed to their semantic or epistemic properties” (S&T 2012, p. 40).Footnote 1 What makes a concept that very concept is its origin, more particularly its “originating use” (ibid, 42). Each concept, as a contingent abstract object, has many contingent concrete “correlates”, namely its tokens (ibid, 41). To use a concept is to use a token of it. A non-originating use of a concept has two characteristics: (1) it involves “deference” to other uses of the concept (namely, to intend to use the concept as it has been used already) and (2) it makes the accumulation of information from the other uses possible. An originating use of a concept, in contrast, contains neither a “deferential intention” nor “informational accumulation” (ibid, 43); this is a use in which the concept is originally introduced.Footnote 2 Thus, the main principle of Concept Originalism (CO) is (ibid, 44):

(O) Necessarily: concept C1 = concept C2 iff the originating use of C1 = the originating use of C2.Footnote 3

According to CO, concept transmission is nothing but “standing in the ancestral of a deference involving relation R to the originating use” (S&T 2012, p. 44). Deference, the key notion, is not to be understood semantically: “[it] can be modeled (rather over-intellectually) as the recognition that others already use a concept, together with desire to use the very concept they use, [...]. It does not require the notion of an expert, nor does one need to think of “correct use” as use to form a true thought [...]” (ibid, 70). Therefore, although using the same concept involves the intention to use it in accordance with some previous uses, it does not involve the actual satisfaction of this intention. CO holds that the learner of a concept needs to intend to refer to its reference, but she may acquire the concept even if this intention fails.Footnote 4

2 CO’s terminology

Well-formed expressions of natural language have/express (are semantically associated with)Footnote 5 concepts or structures of concepts: Names and other referring expressions have nominative concepts (e.g. ‘Fido’ has Fido as its concept), predicates have predicative concepts (e.g. ‘bark’ has bark as its concept), logical operators have logical concepts (e.g. ‘and’ has and as its concept), and so on (ibid, 21).Footnote 6 Declarative sentences have properly structured concepts or thoughts (ibid, 47). For example,

1. Fido barks

expresses a thought that may be represented by:

1T. < Fido, bark>

(1T) is a unary atomic thought constituted of a nominative concept, Fido, and a predicative one, bark, properly linked together.Footnote 7 We may have negative thoughts, conjunctive thoughts, and the like.

A concept or a thought has a content. The content of a nominative concept, at a world, is its actual referent, if any, (which is the same as the actual referent of the corresponding name) (ibid, 48); ‘Fido’ has Fido as its nominative concept and the latter has Fido, the individual, as its content. The content of a predicative concept, at a world, is its actual referent, if any, (which is the same as the actual referent of the corresponding predicate); ‘barks’ has bark as its concept and the latter has the property of barking as its content. Hence, properties are not concepts; in fact, concepts represent (or refer to) properties (ibid, 2). The content of a unary atomic thought is the set of all possible worlds w in which each constituent concept of the thought has a content and “the content of the nominative concept at w possesses the property that is the content of the predicative concept at w” (ibid, 48). The content of a negative thought or a conjunctive thought, in turn, can recursively be defined. Therefore, “a thought is true iff the actual world is a member of the associated set [of worlds] and is otherwise false” (ibid, 49). In addition to concepts, thoughts, and contents, S&T (2012) introduce extensions: “The extension of a nominative concept is its referent (just as for the naïve Millianism), of a predicative concept the things of which it is true, and of a thought, its truth-value. This notion can be relativized to worlds” (S&T 2012, p. 32). Now, to (inadvertent) reference-shift.

3 CO and the ‘Madagascar’ case

Gareth Evans (1973), announcing the ‘Madagascar’ case as “decisive against the Causal Theory of Names”, describes it as follows:

Change of denotation is similarly decisive against the Causal Theory of Names. Not only are changes of denotation imaginable, but it appears that they actually occur. We learn from Isaac Taylor’s book: Names and their History, 1898:

“In the case of ‘Madagascar’ a hearsay report of Malay or Arab sailors misunderstood by Marco Polo... has had the effect of transferring a corrupt form of the name of a portion of the African mainland to the great African Island.”

(Evans 1973, pp. 195–196)

Kripke (1980, p. 163) leaves “the problem for further work” and as John P. Burgess (2014, p. 195) rightly points out, he “has not yet provided any such extended discussion in print.” CO, however, is immune to the ‘Madagascar’ case. According to CO, different tokens of a proper name may refer to different objects since the nominative concept expressed by the name, may refer to different objects at different times:

Marco Polo heard some locals using the word ‘Madagascar’ (or some similar word) and was thereby introduced to a concept. He had appropriate deferential intentions: his plan was to use the concept in the way the locals did. He was confused about its referent: the locals used it to refer to Mogadishu, the town on the mainland, whereas he thought they used it to refer to the island Madagascar (hundreds of miles away). Marco Polo’s mistaken usage of the concept became standardized, and the usage of the locals had negligible later effects [...]. In this case, it seems more appropriate, to say that the original concept Madagascar changed its referent.

(S&T 2012, p. 71)

CO can easily explain the ‘Madagascar’ case away. Given CO, concept transmission is pretty much like reference borrowing with regard to names, with no significant semantic or epistemic restriction on the deference relation involved. In fact, CO generalizes the possibility of (inadvertent) reference shift to all concepts, and thus all terms:

The concept MEAT used in the fifteenth century had as its reference anything edible; in our terms, its content was the property of being edible. The concept MEAT we use now has as its reference only flesh; in our terms, its content is the property of being flesh. One option is to say that earlier concept is the same as the current concept, but that its content has changed. Another option is to say that a new concept, expressed by a word spelled and pronounced the same way, was introduced at some point, and each of the two concepts have retained their original and distinct contents. We prefer the first story. It is a case of gradual drift, with no event that seems a good candidate for the introduction of a new concept.

(S&T 2012, p. 46)

To sum up, CO allows reference-shift over a single causal chain of reference borrowing. This is exactly the point that Evans’s objection to the Causal Theory of Reference tries to make. But Evans’s objection is no objection to CO since a causal chain of communication of a concept doesn’t need to deliver a single reference for it; at different nodes of the chain, as it were, different tokens of the concept may have different references. In fact, this is part of the view.Footnote 8

We claim, however, that CO’s semantics of belief reports does not accommodate belief reports containing terms with reference-shift. To see the problem, we must briefly explain CO’s semantics of belief reports.Footnote 9

4 CO’s semantics of belief reports

Consider:

2. S believes that PFootnote 10

According to CO, \(^{\lceil }\hbox {P}^{\rceil }\) is the thought put on display in (2); it is a thought of the attributer, who is not explicitly represented in (2). If the subject of the attribution (attributee), S, is appropriately related to a thought \(^{\lceil }\hbox {Q}^{\rceil }\) (not necessarily identical with \(^{\lceil }\hbox {P}^{\rceil })\) which itself stands in an R-relation to \(^{\lceil }\hbox {P}^{\rceil }\), then (2) is true, and vice versa (S&T 2012, p. 118).Footnote 11 CO accepts a relational analysis of belief states but denies a relational analysis of belief reports: “Even though one who entertains a thought is in a relational state, of which a thought is a relatum, it does not follow that ascriptions of such states are semantically or syntactically relational, referring to the thought as a relatum”(S&T 2012, p. 32). Consequently, the view rejects the so-called “Specification Assumption”, namely a true belief report must specify the thought the believer (i.e. the ascribee) has in her belief box.Footnote 12

To illustrate, consider:

3. Mark Sainsbury believes that he is tall.

4. Michael Tye believes that he is tall.

In (3) and (4), ‘he’ refers to Mark Sainsbury. Mark and Michael believe the “same thing”,Footnote 13 i.e. that Mark Sainsbury is tall. However, in a sense, there may be no single thought that is what they both believe or are belief-related to.Footnote 14 They may believe the same thing in virtue of being belief-related to two different thoughts. For example, Mark may be belief-related to the thought represented by:

3M. <I, being tall>Footnote 15

And Michael may be belief-related to the thought represented by:

4M. <Sainsbury, being tall>

These thoughts are not identical; they have different constituents and different properties. The thought put on display in the belief reports, i.e. in (3) and (4), in turn, may be represented by:

3/4T. <He, being tall>Footnote 16

This thought is in an R-relation to the thoughts represented by (3M) and (4M).

5 Belief reports containing ‘Madagascar’

Suppose that Sainsbury makes the following belief report:

5. Adam believed that Madagascar is not an island.

Adam is the local from whom Marco Polo learned ‘Madagascar’. By assumption, Adam used ‘Madagascar’ to refer to Mogadishu and Sainsbury, following Marco Polo’s usage, uses ‘Madagascar’ to refer to Madagascar. Given CO, there is one concept Madagascar, once entertained by Adam and now employed by Sainsbury, that refers to different objects at different times. Given that Adam and Sainsbury use the same concept of being an island and not, we may suppose that the thought to which Adam was belief-related and the thought put on display in (5) are the same since they have the same constituents and the same structure. This thought may be represented by:

5T. <not < Madagascar, being an island \({>>}\)

This suggests, independently of Specification Assumption, that (5) should be a truthful belief report. Intuitively speaking, however, this is not the case: (5) attributes to Adam the belief that Madagascar is not an island, which is now false, whereas Adam’s belief, at his own time, was that Mogadishu is not an island, which is now true. Something is going wrong.Footnote 17

S&T are aware of the problem, though they do not discuss it for singular terms:

On our version of originalism, there are some qualifications on the claim that if the subject of the attribution stands in the appropriate relation to the very thought displayed in the attribution, the attribution is true. This is because we allow that a concept’s content can shift over time. A \({\mathrm{fifteenth}}\)-century person, Harold, might be belief-related to the thought that spinach is meat, and we might display this thought in the \({\mathrm{twenty\; first}}\)-century attribution “Harold believed that spinach is meat.” The attribution is certainly misleading, and it is doubtful whether it is true. It’s misleading, because it suggests that Harold’s thought had the same content as ours, in which case he believed something obviously false, whereas what he believed, at the time he believed it, was true. Hence the best candidate for a sufficient condition is identity of thought and sameness of content.

(S&T 2012, pp. 118–119, n.12)

CO’s solution is to strengthen the sufficient condition for truthful belief reports. A belief report of the form \(^{\lceil }\)S believes that \(\hbox {P}^{\rceil }\) is true if (a) the thought put on display, i.e. \(^{\lceil }\hbox {P}^{\rceil }\), is identical to the thought that the attributee, S, is/was belief-related to and (b) the thought in question has the same content across time.Footnote 18 Having this sufficient condition handy, it is not strange why (5) is not a truthful belief report: (b) does not hold. The content of (5T), namely the set of possible worlds in which the constituent concepts of (5T) have reference and (5T) is true, roughly speaking, at the time of Adam, contains the actual world whereas now it does not. So, the thought in question does not have the same content across time. This can explain why (5)’s being misleading and false does not contradict CO.Footnote 19 If the sufficient condition were not strengthened, then (5) would satisfy it and thus would become true (contradicting our intuition that the report is misinforming and incorrect). Now, the new condition cannot be met. Hence, there is room to take (5) as false. This solution, however, fails, or so we will argue next.

6 CO’s solution fails

Consider a belief report whose ‘that’-clause contains an atomic simple sentence containing a singular (or general) term with reference-shift such that the thought expressed by the sentence is necessarily false all along. Since the reference-shift does not change the identity of the concept, there would be no change in the identity of the thought. Thus, condition (a) holds. On the other hand, the content of a thought, according to CO, is a set of possible worlds w in which each constituent concept of the thought has a content (reference) and the thought is true. Therefore, if the thought is necessarily false, its content would be the empty set all along. Hence, there would be no change in its content. Hence, condition (b) holds too. However, intuitively speaking, the belief report is not truthful.

For instance, suppose that Adam, mistakenly, believed that Atlantis, the mythical island, exists and is the same as Mogadishu. Assume that he has been belief-related to the thought represented by:

(6T) < Madagascar, =, Atlantis>

By assumption, Adam and we use the same concept Madagascar, only with reference-shift. (Also, by assumption, Adam and we use the same empty concept Atlantis.) Given CO’s semantics of belief reports, (6) should be true:

(6) Adam believed that Madagascar is Atlantis.

First, the thought put on display in (6) is the same as the thought entertained by Adam; they are constituted of the same concepts and have the same structure. Therefore, condition (a) holds. Second, the thought entertained by Adam has the same content as the thought put on display in (6), namely the empty set: there is no possible world in which Madagascar and Atlantis have one and the same reference, as we use them. Recall that CO allows empty concepts (S&T 2012, pp. 139–144): an empty concept has no content at any world (ibid, 48), and all identity thoughts containing such concepts are necessarily false (ibid, 141). Therefore, there is no change in the content of the thought represented by (6T) over time. Hence, condition (b) holds. Nevertheless, (6) is misleading and it is doubtful that it is true; Adam believed that Mogadishu, not Madagascar, is Atlantis. That what Adam believed is necessarily false should not conceal the point that Adam had some belief about Mogadishu, not Madagascar. (6) misrepresents Adam’s mental state; in particular, (6) misrepresents the subject matter of Adam’s belief.

As another example, consider a belief report whose ‘that’-clause contains an atomic simple sentence containing a singular (or general) term with reference-shift such that the thought expressed by the sentence is necessarily true all along and its truth requires the existence of one set of objects.

For instance, to have an example of reference-shift in general terms, consider a mathematical predicative concept with reference-shift. Suppose that the concept being perfect in number theory has gradually changed its semantic reference from the property of being equal to the sum of all or some of the proper divisors of a number, in 1000 BC, to the property of being equal to the sum of all the proper divisors of a number, now. The two properties are similar, though distinct. Suppose that Harold, in 1000 BC, was belief-related to the thought that 6 is a perfect number. This thought may now be represented by:

7T. <6, being perfect>

By assumption, Harold and we use the same concept being perfect. Given CO’s semantics of belief report, the following belief report should be true:

7. Harold believed that 6 is perfect.

The thought put on display in (7), is the same as the thought to which Harold was belief-related. Hence condition (a) holds. Moreover, this very thought is necessarily true all along: 6 has both the property of being equal to the sum of all or some of its proper divisors and the property of being equal to the sum of all its proper divisors necessarily. Finally, note that 6 is a necessary object and exists in all possible worlds. Hence the content of the thought represented by (7T) is the set of all possible worlds all along. Therefore, there is no change in its content. Hence, condition (b) holds. Nevertheless, (7) is misleading and it is doubtful that it is true: what Harold believed of 6, as a perfect number, is significantly different from what one believes of 6, as a perfect number, now. In some sense, it is by mere coincidence that the thought put on display in (7) has the same content across time. If instead of 6, Harold had thought of 12, the content of his thought, as well as its extension (truth-value), would have changed (12 only possesses the property of being equal to the sum of all or some of its proper divisors, and not the property of being equal to the sum of all its proper divisors). (7) is misleading and it is doubtful that it is true since it misrepresents the conceptual content of Harold’s belief state.

7 Objections and replies

First, it might be thought that the above counterexamples are hypothetical and thus have no counterparts in natural language. CO, the objection continues, provides a theory of the concepts expressed in natural language. Thus, remote possibilities of reference-shift shall not count as actual evidence against the view. We believe that this objection fails. Admittedly, the counterexamples are hypothetical; they may not be, historically speaking, true stories. This, however, shall not, and does not, affect their theoretical value. CO is a theory of the concepts expressible (and not necessarily expressed) in natural language.

Second, one might object that the belief reports in question appear misleading only if one reads them de re. It is only when one characterizes (6) as reporting a belief about, or of, Mogadishu, that (6) might appear misleading. If one reads them de dicto, the contrary intuitions should fade away. This objection fails for two reasons: first, the originalist formulation of pure de re belief reports does not support this claim and second the problem is not restricted to de re belief reports. Here is S&T’s characterization of pure de re belief reports:Footnote 20

Setting aside hybrid cases, Sally thinks of Hesperus that it is visible iff for some de re concept C, whose referent is Hesperus, Sally thinks a thought whose first element is C and whose second element is R-related to the concept is visible. As before, the R-relation will sometimes but not always be identity.

(S&T 2012, p. 122)

According to the above characterization, (6) should count as a pure de re belief report. Thus, if its de re reading is misdealing and false, intuitively speaking, appeal to de re/de dicto distinction does not block our counterexamples.

More importantly, a belief report like (7), in which reference-shift occurs in a predicative concept (not in a nominative one), has nothing to do with S&T’s treatment of de re belief reports, or in general with the de re/de dicto distinction. What makes such a belief report misleading is not that the subject-matter of the attributee’s belief state is misrepresented; rather, the distortion occurs in the representation of a different part of the belief state, i.e. the predicative concept. In general, given CO, concepts of other kinds, e.g. logical or adverbial, may suffer the same kind of misrepresentation. Hence, the de re/de dicto distinction is not the key to the problem.

8 CO’s diagnosis of the root of the problem is misguided

S&T maintain that the belief report in their spinach example, namely:

8. Harold believed that spinach is meat.

is “misleading, because it suggests that Harold’s thought had the same content as ours, in which case he believed something obviously false, whereas what he believed, at the time he believed it, was true” (S&T 2012, p. 71), emphasis is our. We agree that (8) is misleading. Nonetheless, S&T’s diagnosis of the root of this problem is misguided.

Recall that ‘content’, given CO, gives birth to two different kinds of entity: on the one hand, the content of a nominative concept or that of a predicative one is an individual or a property, and on the other hand, the content of a unary atomic thought (expressed by a declarative atomic simple sentence) is the set of possible worlds w in which each constituent concept of the thought has a content (reference) and the thought is true, roughly speaking. Thus, the content of a thought, in a sense, does not represent the contents of its constituents. (8) is misleading, and perhaps false, not because it suggests that Harold’s thought had the same content, in the originalist sense of ‘content’, as ours. Rather, it is misleading and perhaps false since it suggests that Harold believed a structured content, or a Russellian proposition, he could not have. Consider the following two Russellian propositions:

9P. <Spinach, Being edible>

10P. <Spinach, Being flesh>.Footnote 21

What makes the belief report in question incorrect is that it suggests that Harold’s belief box contained the proposition represented by (10P), rather than the one represented by (9P). Note that, according to CO, Russellian propositions are not legitimate entities; they are neither thoughts, nor their contents, and not even their extensions (truth-values). They differ from thoughts in that they are constituted of individuals and properties, not concepts. They differ from the contents of thoughts in that they are structured objects, not sets of possible worlds. Neither the originalist ‘thoughts’ nor their ‘contents’ do what Russellian propositions do. The problem, we believe, is rooted in the fact that S&T do not avail themselves of a theoretical apparatus equivalent to Russellian propositions.

9 Two initially appealing ways out of the problem fail

In a recent critical notice of S&T’s book, Horwich (2014) suggests an alternative solution to S&T’s meat example:

I suspect these difficulties could have been avoided had the authors applied their theory to ‘meat’ in a rather different way. It might be simpler and better for them to say: (i) that some person at a specific time introduced the new use of ‘meat’ with an unconstrained, nondeferential utterance of ‘Meat is flesh’; (ii) that this new ‘concept’ spread gradually through the community over the next few hundred years; (iii) that during this period both ‘concepts’ were in play; and (iv) that by now the new one has completely supplanted the old one.

(Horwich 2014, p. 1131)

Admittedly, Horwich’s proposal describes a possible scenario in which the problem of misleading belief reports may not arise in the form discussed by S&T. Nonetheless, as we believe S&T are well aware, Horwich’s proposal is not a solution to the problem. The problem we are concerned with is rooted in the possibility of reference-shift in concepts.Footnote 22 CO is committed to the view that a single concept may change its reference over time and preserves its identity. Horwich’s proposal may block the problem in some cases but it does not provide a genuine solution to it in general.

Horwich’s proposal can be a solution if it is brought to its extreme by claiming that there is no possibility of reference-shift and all cases of misleading belief reports are cases of twin concepts whose expressions are spelled and pronounced similarly when one may prevail over the other, given enough time. Denying the possibility of reference-shift, however, has two implausible consequences for CO: First, Gareth Evans’s objection to the causal theory of reference will be back: There are cases in which, intuitively speaking, reference-shift is admissible when the causal-chain of reference borrowing does not allow it. Second, and worse, if reference-shift is not permitted, it means that there is no single concept with two references over time. Otherwise put, it says that a change in a concept’s reference is enough to change the identity of the concept. A concept’s reference, after all, is a semantic property of the concept. And this implies that some semantic properties, e.g. reference, contribute to the individuation of concepts. This violates the founding idea of CO, namely “atomic concepts are to be individuated by their historical origins, as opposed to their semantic or epistemic properties” (S&T 2012, p. 40).

Alternatively, one might try to revise CO by introducing Russellian propositions as the contents of thoughts. If so, then the misleading belief reports do not satisfy S&T’s second condition for a truthful belief report (namely the thought put on display in a belief report should have the same content as the thought to which the attributee is/was belief-related) and thus, given CO, it does not follow that they are true (in other words, CO can accommodate such belief reports as false). Accordingly, concepts may change their references but since the content of a thought is a Russellian proposition, all changes of the contents of the constituent concepts of the thought would be visible, so to speak, through the content of the thought. For example, there is no necessity to take a belief report like (7), namely ‘Harold believed that 6 is perfect’, to be true. This is so because the content of the thought put on display in (7), i.e. the Russellian proposition represented by:

7P. <6, Being equal to the sum of all the proper divisors of a number>

is distinct from the content of the thought to which Harold was belief-related, i.e. the Russellian proposition represented by:

7’P. <6, Being equal to the sum of all or some of the proper divisors of a number>.

This proposal faces three serious problems. First, CO’s resistance to accept Russellian propositions as useful entities:

Originalism differs from Millianism in finding no use for propositions, conceived as sequences of objects and properties. It accounts for many Fregean data in terms of sameness and difference among concepts, rather than in terms of guises, notions or modes of presentation. (S&T 2012, p. 30)

Second, the problem of empty concepts will be back. If the contents of concepts, nominative or predicative, may be empty, namely there may be no corresponding individuals or properties, and the content of a thought is a structured entity constituted of individuals and properties, it is not clear what the content of a thought containing an empty concept, e.g. the thought associated with ‘Vulcan exists’, will be. It is hard to accept that such a thought has no content, if its content is the ultimate truth-value bearer. After all the thought seems to be false and S&T need to explain this. Moreover, introducing an unfilled proposition or a gappy content flies in the face of both S&T’s originalist approachFootnote 23 and Tye’s solution to the problem of the content of a hallucinatory experience. Last but not least, there are independent reasons against gappy contents.Footnote 24 Third, the proposal pushes CO toward a version of Russellianism and, thus, makes it less attractive. The Russellian would wonder why she should buy all the apparatus of concepts, if at the end of the day Russellian propositions should do the most important theoretical tasks.

10 Does adding the Reference to the picture solve the problem?

One might further strengthen the sufficient condition for a truthful belief report by requiring the sameness of the references of the corresponding constituent concepts of the thought entertained by the attributee and the one put on display in the belief report. It might be suggested that this solves the problem of misleading belief reports for CO without deviating from its principal elements. This is not the case, we will explain.

The suggestion may be developed in different ways; we use S&T’s notion of isomorphic thoughts:

Isomorphism: Thoughts are isomorphic iff they share a complete tree structure, and their corresponding terminal nodes are concepts with the same content [i.e. the same referent].

Isomorphism is not necessary for sameness of content [in the originalist sense] (though it is sufficient in extensional contexts).

(S&T 2012, p. 50)

Thus, on behalf of S&T, one might suggest that a belief report of the form \(^{\lceil }\hbox {S}\) believes that \(\hbox {P}^{\rceil }\) is true if (a) the thought put on display, i.e. \(^{\lceil }\hbox {P}^{\rceil }\), is both (a) isomorphic and (b) identical to the thought that the attributee, S, is/was belief-related to (we suppose that isomorphism guarantees the sameness of the truth value, or the content, of the thought in question over time). Even this is not a strong enough sufficient condition, given CO, as we will shortly show. Before doing so, let’s quickly see how one might use the idea, in a slightly different form, to explain the falsehood of the misleading belief reports discussed above, S&T’s meat example included. If isomorphism is introduced as a necessary condition for a truthful belief report, then the misleading belief reports are false (and thus misleading) because they violate this necessary condition. Reference-shift in a concept brings about difference in its content and difference in its content undermines isomorphism. To illustrate, consider (6) again, namely ‘Adam believed that Madagascar is Atlantis’. Even though the thought put on display in the belief report and the thought to which Adam was belief-related are identical (and have the same truth value), they are not isomorphic. Our concept Madagascar and Adam’s concept Madagascar, though identical, have different contents: one refers to Madagascar and the other to Mogadishu, by assumption. Therefore, the two thoughts having these concepts as their constituents are not isomorphic. Thus, the necessary condition is not met and this explains why the belief report is not truthful.

Unfortunately, even this seemingly promising strategy cannot solve the general problem of misleading belief reports. CO acknowledges cases of apparent reference-shift in empty concepts; let’s call them “purported-reference-shift”. These cases make the task of furnishing a semantics for belief reports puzzling unless one spells out the nature of “purported reference” and get them integrated into the truth conditions of belief reports, something that has not yet been done nor is it clear how to do it. Here is an example:

Joke: A small group, as a kind of “in” joke, decides to use “Holmes” for Watson and “Watson” for Holmes. Then all the texts are destroyed in some cataclysm. People learning from the small group don’t realize there has been a jocular inversion. These benighted souls become the only users of the specific names.

Although the purported referent of “Watson” used to be Watson (the side-kick), it has become Holmes (the detective), and the purported referent of “Holmes” is now Watson. We again apply the principle that semantic reference is conventionalized speaker’s reference. In the example, the purported reference of empty names has changed.

(Sainsbury 2015, p. 213)

Note that ‘Holmes’ and ‘Watson’, by assumption, are genuinely empty, they have no semantic reference; they only purport to refer. Nonetheless, as Sainsbury claims, they may undergo purported-reference-shift. Suppose that before the shift, Harold mistakenly believed that Holmes and Watson really exist and have some properties. He believed, for example, that Holmes is smart. More precisely, assume that before the purported-reference-shift Harold was belief-related to the thought represented by (9T):

9T. <Holmes, being smart>

Now, consider the following belief report made after the shift:

9. Harold believed that Holmes is smart.

For the sake of simplicity, we can assume that the post-shift attributer (who is not explicitly represented in (9)) does not know anything about the purported-reference-shift and mistakenly believes, like Harold, that Holmes and Watson really exist.Footnote 25 (9) is intended to describe Harold’s belief state before the shift.Footnote 26 Therefore, the epistemic states of Harold and his post-shift belief attributer are similar to those of Adam and his post-shift belief attributer in Sect. 6. Recall:

(6) Adam believed that Madagascar is Atlantis.

In the case of (6), Adam believes something false, namely that Mogadishu is Atlantis. In the case of (9), similarly, Harold believes something false, namely Holmes (as a real person) is smart. In the case of (6), the problem is how to correctly ascribe (after the shift) the false belief Adam has (before the shift) to him, given CO. We argued that S&T’s strengthened sufficient condition for a truthful belief report is inappropriate because (6) satisfies this condition but it ascribes a different false belief to Adam, one about Madagascar (due to the reference-shift in ‘Madagascar’). In the case of (9), again similarly, the problem is how to correctly ascribe (after the shift) the false belief Harold has (before the shift) to him, given CO. We submit that the further strengthened sufficient condition for a truthful belief report (by adding isomorphism) is inappropriate because (9) satisfies this condition but it ascribes a different false belief to Harold, one purportedly about Watson (due to the purported-reference-shift in ‘Holmes’). Let us explain.

The thought put on display in the belief report (9) and the thought that Harold had in his belief box, i.e. (9T), are both isomorphic and identical, since they are constituted of similar concepts with the same contents.Footnote 27 More precisely, their first concepts are genuinely empty and their second concepts refer to the property of being smart. This guarantees that (9T) has one and the same truth-value, or content, over time, i.e. falsehood. Therefore, (9) satisfies the sufficient condition proposed above. Nonetheless, (9) is misleading and perhaps false because it suggests that Harold believed something that was purportedly about Watson (recall, ‘Holmes’ after the purported-reference-shift purports to refer to Watson), whereas Harold, by assumption, believed something that was purportedly about Holmes. Moreover, in cases of purported-reference-shift like Joke and reports like (9), since isomorphism, strictly speaking, is not violated, the falsehood of the misleading belief report may not be explained by appeal to isomorphism as a necessary condition of a truthful belief report either. The problem simply persists since CO extends ‘reference’-shift to empty concepts.

To properly represent that Harold had a belief that was purportedly about Holmes, not Watson, one also needs to get the purported-reference of ‘Holmes’ involved in the semantics of belief reports. Something that has not yet been done, nor is it clear how to do it within CO without seriously deforming the view. Note that postulating nonexistent objects as the (purported) referents of the so-called empty names and then appealing to isomorphism as a sufficient or necessary condition for a truthful belief report, has three odd consequences for CO: first, it pushes the view toward a version of ‘Meinongianism’ and thus makes it less appealing. Second, it makes the whole apparatus of concepts as useful means to tackle the problem of negative existentials redundant: If there are nonexistent objects and they may be referred to by proper names, then one may truly attribute nonexistence to them as well. Third, this proposal threatens one of the primary motives for CO, i.e. the view acknowledges genuinely empty names as legitimate proper names of natural language. To repeat, CO is insistent that “empty concepts can be intelligible; even though they all have the same content” (S&T 2012, pp. 143).Footnote 28

11 Concluding remarks

We argued that CO’s semantics of belief reports is defective and no easy solution is foreseeable. Horwich’s (2014) proposal is a local solution and its generalized form undermines CO’ s founding idea. CO is pretty new; it has not yet been under critical assessment from a perspective similar to ours.Footnote 29 Providing an identification criterion for concepts cannot be done independently of furnishing a semantics for attitude ascriptions and the latter needs to be based on the semantic properties of concepts and thoughts. Allowing (inadvertent) reference-shift makes concepts semantically unstable and extending it to purported-reference-shift makes concepts semantically untrackable. Neither thoughts nor their contents, not even the contents of the constituent concepts of thoughts, promise to help with the semantics of belief reports, as long as ‘reference’-shift is allowed for all concepts (referring and non-referring). CO opens the Pandora’s box of reference-shift in a wide range of cases without providing the necessary semantic means to take care of them.