Skip to main content
Log in

Pedagogy as a Framework for a Proper Dialogue between Science and Literature

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

An aim of science is to find truths about reality. These truths are collected together to form systematic knowledge structures called theories. Theories are intended to create a truthful picture of the reality behind the study. Together with all the other fields of science we get a (complete) scientific picture or a world view. This scientific world view is open in the sense that not all truths are known by scientists and not all present day theories are true. So, there is no reason to assume that any field of science has been or will be completed; science is essentially progressive, or an open ended approach. Science is not the only method of picturing, but the view that science is the best human method for knowledge acquisition is well justified. Knowledge is not all we humans are looking for; we need to make our lives meaningful. The meaningfulness may be achieved through science, art, or practical activity. It is interesting to compare literature and science. Both are expressed linguistically, but the aims of literature and science seem to be very different. We are looking for the theoretical interconnection between science and literature, but the proper dialogue can be found not through science, literature or philosophy, but through pedagogy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Allen, S. (Ed.) (1989). Possible Worlds in Humanities, Arts and Sciences. Proceedings of Nobel Symposium 65. Walter de: Gryter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1969).The Logical Structure of the World/Pseudoproblems in Philosophy, University of California Press

  • Cohn, D. (2006). Fiktion mieli, Gaudeamus

    Google Scholar 

  • Copeland, J. B. (2002). The genesis of possible worlds semantics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 31.

  • Davis, L. J. (1983). Factual fictions. the origins of the English novel. Columbia University Press.

  • Dolezel, L. (1989). ‘Possible Worlds and Literary Fictions’, in Sture Allen (ed.), Possible Worlds in Humanities, Arts and Sciences. Proceedings of Nobel Symposium 65, Walter de Gryter.

  • Gold, M. (1967). Language identification in the limit. Information and Control, 10.

  • Haaparanta, L. (1985). Frege's Doctrine of Being. Helsinki: Acta Philosophica Fennica.

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1999). The social construction of what? Harvard University Press.

  • Haug, M. C. (2014). Philosophical Methodology: The Armchair or the laboratory? Routledge.

  • Healey, R. (1989). The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics: An Interactive Interpretation. Cambridge University Press.

  • Hendricks, V. F. (2001). The Convergence of Scientific Knowledge – a View from the Limit. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heyting, A. (1971). Intuitionism: An introduction. North-Holland Publishing Co..

  • Hintikka, J. (1969). Models for modalities. D. Reidel Publishing Company.

  • Hintikka, J. (1975). The intentions of intentionality and other new models for modalities. D. Reidel Publishing Company.

  • Hintikka, J. (1979). Virginia Woolf and our Knowledge of the External World, The Journal of Aesthetic and Art Criticism, vol. 38 No. 1.

  • Hintikka, J. (1987). Self-Profile, in Bogdan, R. J. (ed.), Jaakko Hintikka. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

  • Hintikka, J. (2007). Socratic epistemology. Cambridge University Press.

  • Hintikka, J., & Remes, U. (1974). The Method of Analysis: Its Geometrical Origin and Its General Significance. D Reidel Publishing Company.

  • Hintikka, J., Halonen, I., & Mutanen, A. (2002). Interrogative logic as a General Theory of reasoning. In R. H. Johnson, & J. Woods (Eds.), Handbook of practical reasoning (pp. 295–337). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodges, W. (1985). Building models by games. Dover Publications Inc..

  • Kelly, K. (1996). The logic of reliable inquiry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach, E. (1976). On thought experiments, in Ernst Mach, Knowledge and Error, D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (1995). Science teaching: the role of history and philosophy of science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1999). Critical scientific realism. Oxford University Press.

  • Niniluoto, I. (1987). Truthlikeness. Springer.

  • Olsson, G. (1986). On doughnutting. In S. Allen (Ed.), Possible Worlds in Humanities Arts and Sciences: Proceedings of Nobel Symposium 65. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. H. (1986). Possible worlds in model-theoretic semantics: a linguistic perspective. In S. Allen (Ed.), Possible Worlds in Humanities Arts and Sciences: Proceedings of Nobel Symposium 65. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1980). From a Logical Point of View: 9 Logico-Philosophical Essays. Harvard University Press.

  • Rorty, R. (1980). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton University Press.

  • Rorty, R. (1991). Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers volume 1. Cambridge University Press.

  • Russell, B. (1993). Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, New York: Dover Publications (The edition is unabridged and unaltered republication of the second edition (1929) of the work first published in 1919 by George Allen & Unwin Ltd.)

  • Tarski, A. (1944). The semantic conception of truth and the foundations of semantics. In A. P. Martinich (Ed.), 2001, The Philosophy of Language (pp. 69–91). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraasen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Clarendon Press.

  • von Wright, G. H. (1989). Ajatus ja julistus, WSOY

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2014). What is naturalism?, in Haug 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1974). Philosophical grammar. Basil Blackwell.

  • Zahavi, D. (2003). Husserl’s Phenomenology. Stanford University Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Arto Mutanen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mutanen, A. Pedagogy as a Framework for a Proper Dialogue between Science and Literature. Philosophia 44, 167–180 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-015-9683-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-015-9683-6

Keywords

Navigation