Skip to main content
Log in

Abstract

In the mid of nineteenth century, the hypothesis, “machine can think,” became very popular after Alan Turing’s article on “Computing Machinery and Intelligence.” This hypothesis, “machine can think,” established the foundations of machine intelligence and claimed that machines have a mind. It has the power to compete with human beings. In the first section, I shall explore the importance of Turing thesis, which has been conceptualized in the domain of machine intelligence. Turing presented a completely different view of the machine itself. It addressed philosophers, rather than the mathematicians, and proclaimed that digital computers might be considered as intelligent machines. This approach was wholly new, both philosophically and technically, and started many philosophical debates which continue to this day. He proposed an imitation game, as a test, what is now referred to as a Turing test to evaluate if a machine thinks. That is to say that the main aim of machine intelligence not only constructs challenging programs to solve our day-to-day problems but also reproduce mentality in machines and claimed that all the mental qualities are ascribable to machines. What will be attempted in this paper is a critical evaluation of the arguments against the Turing test put forward by many philosophers.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Turing (1950, p. 433).

  2. Ibid. p. 442.

  3. Ibid.

  4. See, Nath (2009a, b).

  5. Searle (1996, p. 41).

  6. Searle (1980, pp. 417–457).

  7. https://nptel.ac.in/content/storage2/courses/109101003/downloads/Lecture-notes/Lecture-19-20-21.pdf.

  8. Turing (1950, p. 438).

  9. Dennett (1981, pp. 152–154).

  10. This is quoted by John R. Searle, in his Minds, Brains and Science, p. 29.

  11. Haikonen (2007, p. 185).

  12. Clark and Chalmers (1998, p. 8).

  13. Putnam (1975/1985).

  14. Shagrir (2005, p. 236).

  15. Putnam (1975/1985, p. 227).

  16. Clark and Chalmers (1998, pp. 7–19).

  17. Ibid.

  18. See, Nath (2009a, b).

  19. Lucas (1964, p. 44).

  20. Ibid.

  21. Ibid, p. 46.

  22. Ibid.

  23. Ibid, p. 47.

  24. Putnam (1998, p. 4).

  25. Putnam (1989, pp. 74–75).

  26. Ibid, p.83.

  27. See, Nath (2009a, b).

  28. Dreyfus (1979, p. 198).

  29. Weizenbaum (1967, p. 479).

  30. McGinn (1987, p. 280).

  31. Ibid, p.281.

  32. Nath (2009a, b pp. 441–458).

  33. Penrose (1989, p. 407).

  34. Penrose (1994, p. 12).

  35. Lumer et al. (1998, pp. 1930–1934).

  36. Brown and Norcia (1997, pp. 2401–2408).

  37. Tononi et al. (1998, pp. 3198–3203).

  38. Logothetis et al. (1996, pp. 621–624).

  39. Edelman (2004, p. 5).

  40. Laureys (2006, p. 81).

  41. Velpula and Nath (2019, pp. 167–181).

  42. Penrose (1989, p. 26).

  43. Ibid, p.17.

  44. This is quoted by R. Penrose, in his The Emperor’s New Mind, p. 424.

  45. Searle (1996, p. 14).

  46. Searle (1994, p. 1).

  47. Searle (1996, p. 28).

  48. Ibid., 31.

  49. Ibid, 32.

  50. Ibid., p. 37.

  51. Ibid., p 37.

  52. See, Churchland (1989, pp. 338–394).

  53. Pradhan (2002, p. 100).

  54. Searle (1998, p. 386).

  55. Searle (1994, p. 57).

  56. Ibid., p. 56.

  57. See, Nath (2015., pp. 40–53).

References

  • Brown, R. J., & Norcia, A. M. (1997). A method for investigating binocular rivalry in real-time with the steady-state VEP. Vision Research,37(170), 2401–2408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (1989). Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified understanding of the mind/brain. USA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis,58(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1981). Brainstorms: Philosophical essays on mind and psychology. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (1979). What computers cannot do: The limits of artificial intelligence. New York: Harper Colophon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G. M. (2004). Wider than the sky: The phenomenal gift of consciousness. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haikonen, P. O., & Brains, R. (2007). Circuits and systems for conscious machines. England: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • https://nptel.ac.in/content/storage2/courses/109101003/downloads/Lecture-notes/Lecture-19-20-21.pdf. Accessed 11th December 2019.

  • Laureys, S. (2006). The boundaries of consciousness: Neurobiology and neuropathology. The Netherlands: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Logothetis, N. K., Leopold, D. A., & Sheinberg, D. L. (1996). What is rivalling during binocular rivalry? Nature,380(6575), 621–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, J. R. (1964). Mind, machines, and Gödel. In A. R. Anderson (Ed.), Minds and machines (pp. 43–59). Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall. Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lumer, E. D., et al. (1998). Neural correlates of perceptual rivalry in the human brain. Science,280(5371), 1930–1934.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1987). Could a machine be conscious? In Mindwaves: Thoughts on intelligence, identity, and consciousness, Colin Blakemore and Susan Greenfield: Basil Blackwell Ltd., Oxford.

  • Nath, R. (2009a). Machine intelligence, competence and creativity. Artificial Intelligence and Society,23(3), 441–458. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-007-0080-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nath, R. (2009b). Philosophy of artificial intelligence. Florida: Universal Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nath, R. (2015). Turing & His Critics. Ravenshaw Journal of Philosophy, 1, 40–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1989). The emperor’s new mind. Oxford, and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1994). Shadows of the mind. Oxford, and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pradhan, R. C. (2002). Why consciousness cannot be deconstructed: Towards a positive theory of consciousness. In S. Menon, A. Sinha, & B. V. Sreekanthan (Eds.), Science and metaphysics: A discussion on consciousness (pp. 98–106). Bangalore: National Institute of Advanced Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975/1985). Mind, language, and reality: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Putnam, H. (1989). Representation, and reality. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1998). Renewing philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1980). Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,3(3), 417–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1994). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1996). Minds, brains and science. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1998). How to study consciousness scientifically. Brain Research Reviews,26(2/3), 379–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir, O. (2005). The rise and fall of computation functionalism. In Y. Ben-Menahem (Ed.), Hilary Putnam. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tononi, G., et al. (1998). Investigating neural correlates of conscious perception by frequency-tagged neuromagnetic responses. In Proceedings of the national academy of science of the United States of America (Vol. 95, pp. 3198–3203).

  • Turing, A. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind,59(236), 433–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velpula, S., & Nath, R. (2019). Consciousness is the concomitance of life. Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research,36, 167–181. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-018-0165-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weizenbaum, J. (1967). Contextual understanding by computers. Communication for ACM,10(8), 474–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rajakishore Nath.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nath, R. Alan Turing’s Concept of Mind. J. Indian Counc. Philos. Res. 37, 31–50 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-019-00188-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-019-00188-0

Keywords

Navigation