Skip to main content

Introduction: Ernest Nagel and the Making of Philosophy of Science a Profession

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Ernest Nagel: Philosophy of Science and the Fight for Clarity

Abstract

This chapter provides an overview of the life (Sect. 1.1) and philosophy (Sect. 1.2) of Ernest Nagel, as well as a summary of the chapters in this volume (Sect. 1.3). Regarding Nagel's philosophy, we focus on his role and activities to stabilize analytic philosophy (of science) and make it a profession, his views about the role and nature of history and sociology of science, naturalism, and socially engaged philosophy, and finally his understanding of the relation between science, society, and philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Dudley Meek to Ernest Nagel and Morris R. Cohen, January 18, 1944; quoted from Nagel (ms).

  2. 2.

    The quotations are taken from the interview with Nagel published in this volume.

  3. 3.

    Recently, Matthew Brown (2012) has tried to rehabilitate John Dewey’s philosophy of science in more accessible terms.

  4. 4.

    This does not mean, however, that Nagel was unfamiliar with the main trends in logical empiricism. He read some of Carnap’s and Reichenbach’s writings as early as the late 1920s, and published a paper in Erkenntnis about measurement already in 1931. On these early encounters, see Sander Verhaegh’s paper in this volume.

  5. 5.

    Ernest Nagel to Rudolf Carnap, January 5, 1935.

  6. 6.

    Ernest Nagel to Rudolf Carnap, March 6, 1935. Karl Menger (1994) has confirmed this impression that he was somewhat of a skeptical outsider concerning the Wittgensteinian choir.

  7. 7.

    Some of these issues are reconstructed in Yvonne Nagel’s and Fons Dewulf’s chapters. For further details, see Dewulf (2018).

  8. 8.

    On the influence and history of Gödel’s Proofs, see Hodges (2008) and Feferman (2009).

  9. 9.

    While they are not widely discussed among historians of philosophy of science, Nagel did edit other influential volumes, such as a collection of readings on Meaning and Knowledge (Nagel 1965) that introduced many classical analytic thinkers to the community of epistemologists.

  10. 10.

    It might be worth hypothesizing about the idea that Nagel (similarly to Schlick and Feigl) had his manifesto about the role and nature of philosophy of science within society; see Nagel (1943/1954 and 1947/1954).

  11. 11.

    In the Preface to Structure, Nagel noted that further topics in philosophy (such as the evaluation of knowledge claims, concept formation, etc.) are reserved for a volume that is under “active preparation” (1961, p. ix). Although he also confirmed his intentions to Hempel a few years later (“I want to work on the sequel to the Structure of Science”), he had other obligations, and seemingly gave up on the publication of any systematic work that would function as volume two (Nagel to Hempel, June 18, 1964, quoted from Tuboly (ms.)).

  12. 12.

    A few years before, Nagel formulated this broad approach as follows: “the task of logic is to make explicit the structures of methods and assumptions employed in the search for reliable knowledge in the all fields of inquiry” (1956b, p. ix).

  13. 13.

    See also Koslow (2012), Suppes (2012), Chen (2019); reduction is still the most frequently discussed Nagelian topic. See Klein (2009), van Riel (2011), Kaiser (2012), and Schaffner (2012).

  14. 14.

    It would be highly constructive to consider Nagel’s relation to Carnap and Frank in detail, especially because Nagel thanked both Carnap and Frank for their invaluable help in his The Structure of Science (1961, p. x) and in the introduction to Logic Without Metaphysics (1956b, p. xii). Some of these issues are taken up by Thomas Mormann in this volume.

  15. 15.

    It should also be borne in mind that three decades earlier, Nagel had distinguished between at least four different meanings of “method of science”: (a) methods in the sense of different instruments and specialized techniques; (b) methods as various disciplinary approaches and outlooks; (c) methods extracted from the behavior and anthropology of scientists; and (4) methods as ways of evaluating concerning evidence and principles. Nagel (1950b, p. 20) calls the fourth type the “logic of inquiry” (original emphasis) and states that the first three presuppose or come down to different or numerous scientific methods (in fact, the third approach has shown that “there is apparently no such thing as scientific method,” ibid.).

  16. 16.

    This passage is taken from Nagel’s commentary on A.C. Crombie’s and Joseph T. Clark’s papers about history and philosophy of science, published in Marshall Clagett’s Critical Problems in the History of Science. Nagel notes that he is not a historian of science with first-hand knowledge, for example, of medieval science, but as some of the major points of the discussion turned on “philosophical interpretations,” he is “perhaps not completely miscast as a discussant” (Nagel 1959/1969, p. 153).

  17. 17.

    On Nagel’s role in the formation of analytic philosophy, see Schliesser (2013).

  18. 18.

    In an interview, Joseph Margolis told an interesting story about Nagel and Marxism: At a discussion, John Sommerville—then a well-known Marxist philosopher at Columbia—talked about Marxism. Sommerville “was rather well-known but not a very strong figure, and his commentator was Ernest Nagel. Nagel said, I remember it to this day, after Summerville gave his account: well, since Professor Summerville hasn’t told you what Marxism is, I’ll begin by defining it, which he then did very well” (Margolis 2014, p. 306). This story once more confirms Nagel’s wide and deep knowledge of history of philosophy.

  19. 19.

    Nagel is concerned here with the continuity or rebirth of European philosophies (such as idealism, voluntarism, and positivism) in America. As he says, “America shares with western Europe a comparable literary and religious heritage, a similar social and economic structure, and above all an identical science” (1947/1954, p. 51).

  20. 20.

    In 1950, when talking about the methods of science, Nagel noted that scientists should also consult the history and sociology of science to become acquainted with all the ways in which things could go astray. Nagel’s list contains factors other than cognitive ones—the premature delimitation of variables, the influence of intellectual fashions and tacitly accepted philosophies, the pressure to justify results to a larger community, and the reluctance to abandon favored but doubtful ideas (1950b, p. 22). This may indicate that for Nagel, the sociology and history of science are mainly the sociology and history of errors, and not those of truth (as others would have it). The same could also be said of history of science; at one point, Nagel claims (in the context of education) that history of science is “the history of magnificent victories as well as of tragic defeats for human intelligence in its endless war against native ignorance, childish superstitions, and baseless fears” (1959, p. 57).

  21. 21.

    Note that only a decade later, Bernard Barber, who was a close colleague of Robert Merton (one of the leaders of this project), and who also had links to Frank, published his famous paper (quoted in Structure by Kuhn as well) on “Resistance by Scientists to Scientific Discovery” (Barber 1961).

  22. 22.

    For further details, see Reisch (2019, Ch. 10), and Reisch and Tuboly (2021).

  23. 23.

    In this respect, Otto Neurath and Philipp Frank were, of course, exceptions. See Uebel (2000) and Tuboly (2017).

  24. 24.

    One might even wonder how Neurath, given his non-reductive, pluralist naturalism, could disagree to such an extent with Nagel. Moreover, Neurath also repeatedly called attention to the dangers of formalism and systematization throughout his writings in the 1930s and 40s.

  25. 25.

    Public inspection, intersubjectivity and accountability are such terms and norms, which also played a significant role within the so-called left-wing of the Vienna Circle; see Uebel (2020).

  26. 26.

    In these contexts, Nagel often uses the term “responsibility.” See, for example, his introduction to Logic Without Metaphysics where he talks about the “responsible critiques of cognitive claims” (1956b, p. ix).

  27. 27.

    This paper was an editorial-like introduction to an issue of Scientific American about automatization in industry and the workplace. Nagel argues further that automatization, mechanization, the extreme use of quantitative issues and algorithms would not deprive humanity of all qualitative considerations and values immanent to our life and thinking. He even says, “there is no reason why liberation from the unimaginative drudgery which has been the lot of so many men throughout the ages should curtail opportunities for creative thought and for satisfaction in work well done” (1952, p. 47).

  28. 28.

    Regarding many of these journals and associations and their role in professionalizing the philosophy of science, see Dewulf (2021).

References

  • Anonymous. (1945). Descriptions of education manuals: Prepared or selected by the editorial staff of the United States Armed Forces Institute. Educational Services Section, Bureau of Naval Personnel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barber, B. (1961). Resistance by scientists to scientific discovery. Science, 134(3479), 596–602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, M.J. (2012). Dewey's logic of science. HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, 2(2), 258–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R., Hahn, H., & Neurath, O. (1929/1973). The scientific conception of the world: The Vienna Circle. In M. Neurath & R.S. Cohen (Eds.), Otto Neurath: Empiricism and sociology (pp. 299–318). Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, B. (2019). Revisiting the logical empiricist. Criticism of vitalism. Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science, 7, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, M. R., & Nagel, E. (1934). An introduction to logic and scientific method. Harcourt, Brace and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1943). Anti-naturalism in extremis. Partisan Review, 10, 24–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J., Hook, S., & Nagel, E. (1945). Are naturalists materialists? The Journal of Philosophy, 42, 515–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewulf, F. (2018). A genealogy of scientific explanation: The emergence of the deductive-nomological model at the intersection of German historical and scientific philosophy. Doctoral dissertation, Universiteit Gent.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewulf, F. (2021). The institutional stabilization of philosophy of science and its withdrawal from social concerns after the Second World War. British Journal for the History of Philosophy. Online first, https://doi.org/10.1080/09608788.2020.1848794.

  • Eastman, G. (1966). John Dewey’s literary style: Theory and practice. Educational Theory, 16(2), 110–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feferman, S. (2009). Gödel, Nagel, minds, and machines. The Journal of Philosophy, 106(4), 201–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forman, P. (1971). Weimar culture, causality, and quantum theory: Adaptation by German physicists and mathematicians to a hostile environment. Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, 3, 1–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodges, A. (2008). In retrospect: Gödel’s proof. Nature, 454, 829.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hook, S. (1930). A personal impression of contemporary German philosophy. The Journal of Philosophy, 27(6), 141–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hook, S. (1943). The new failure of nerve. Partisan Review, 10, 2–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jewett, A. (2011). Canonizing Dewey: Naturalism, logical empiricism, and the idea of American philosophy. Modern Intellectual History, 8(1), 91–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaiser, M. I., et al. (2012). Why it is time to move beyond Nagelian reduction. In D. Dies (Ed.), Probabilities, laws, and structures (pp. 245–262). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, C. (2009). Reduction without reductionism: A defence of Nagel on connectability. The Philosophical Quarterly, 59(234), 39–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koslow, A. (2012). The explanation of laws: Some unfinished business. The Journal of Philosophy, 109(8/9), 479–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C. I. (1934). Experience and meaning. The Philosophical Review, 43, 125–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J. (2014). Interview with Joseph Margolis. European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, 6(2). Retrieved from http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/301.

  • Menger, K. (1994). Reminiscences of the Vienna Circle and the mathematical colloquium. Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R.K. (1952/1973). The neglect of the sociology of science. In N.W. Storer (Ed.), The sociology of science: Theoretical and empirical investigations (pp. 210–220). University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Misak, C. (2013). The American pragmatists. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgenbesser, S., Suppes, P., & White, M. (Eds.). (1969). Philosophy, science, and method: Essays in honor of Ernest Nagel. St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1929). Intuition, consistency, and the excluded middle. The Journal of Philosophy, 26, 477–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1929). Can logic be divorced from ontology. The Journal of Philosophy, 26, 705–712.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1930). On the logic of measurement. Privately printed.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1931). Measurement. Erkenntnis, 2, 313–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1932). Reviews of Das Unendliche in der Mathematik, Felix Kaufmann; Philosophy der Logik und Mathematik, Hugo Dingler; and Das Problem des Satzes von Ausgeschlossenen Dritten, Paul Hofmann. The Journal of Philosophy, 29, 401–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1933). A frequency theory of probability. The Journal of Philosophy, 30, 533–554.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1936a). Impressions and appraisals of analytic philosophy in Europe. The Journal of Philosophy, 33(1), 5–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1936b). Impressions and appraisals of analytic philosophy in Europe. The Journal of Philosophy, 33(2), 29–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1936c). Review of Wahrscheinlichkeitslehre by Hans Reichenbach. Mind, 45(180), 501–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1936d). The meaning of probability. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 31(193), 10–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1938/1939). The fight for clarity: Logical empiricism. The American Scholar, 8(1), 45–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1939). Principles of the theory of probability. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1943/1954). Malicious philosophies of science. Nagel, (1954a), 17–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1944/1956). Logic without ontology. Nagel, (1956a), 55–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1947/1954). Philosophy and the American Temper. Nagel, (1954a), 50–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1950). Memorial address for Felix Kaufmann. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 10(3), 464–469.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1950). The methods of science: What are they? Can they be taught? The Scientific Monthly, 70(1), 19–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1952). Automatic control. Scientific American, 187(3), 44–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1953). On the method of Verstehen as the sole method of philosophy. The Journal of Philosophy, 50(5), 154–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1953/1956). A formalization of functionalism. Nagel, (1956a), 247–283.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1954/1956). Naturalism reconsidered. Nagel, (1956a), 3–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1954a). Sovereign reason and other studies in the philosophy of science. The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1954b). The perspectives of science and the prospects of men. Nagel, (1954a), 296–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1956a). Logic without metaphysics and other studies in the philosophy of science. The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1956b). Introduction. Nagel, (1956a), ix–xviii.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1959). The place of science in a liberal education. Daedalus, 88(1), 56–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1959/1969). Commentary on the papers of A.C. Crombie and Joseph T. Clark. In M. Clagett (Ed.), Critical problems in the history of science (pp. 153–161). The University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science: Problems in the logic of explanation. Harcourt, Brace & World Inc.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1963). Assumptions in economy theory. The American Economic Review, 53(2), 211–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1978). Introduction. In B. McGuinness (Ed.), Felix Kaufmann: The infinite in mathematics (pp. ix–xv). D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1979a). Teleology revisited and other essays in the philosophy and history of science. Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1979b). Introduction. Nagel, (1979a), 1–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (Ed.). (1965). Meaning and knowledge: Systematic readings in epistemology. Harcourt, Brace & World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E., & Newman, J. R. (1958). Gödel’s proof. New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E., Tarski, A., & Suppes, P. (Eds.). (1962). Logic, methodology and philosophy of science. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Y. (ms). Ernest Nagel: A biography told through letters 1901–1985. Unpublished manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, O. (1937/1987). The new encyclopedia. In B. McGuinness (Ed.), Unified science (pp. 132–141). D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman, J. R. (1950). BOOKS: The 50 years and the popularizing of science: A listing of 20 good examples. Scientific American, 183(3), 97–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes, N., & Conway, E.R. (2010). Merchants of doubt. Bloomsbury Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2017). Ernest Nagel’s naturalism: A microhistory of the American reception of logical empiricism. In A. Preston (Ed.), Analytic philosophy: An interpretive history (pp. 160–174). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Reisch, G. (2005). How the Cold War transformed philosophy of science: To the icy slopes of logic. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reisch, G. (2019). The politics of paradigms: Thomas S. Kuhn, James B. Conant, and the Cold War “Struggle for Men's Minds”. SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reisch, G., & Tuboly, A.T. (2021). Philipp Frank: A crusader for scientific philosophy. In G. Reisch & A.T. Tuboly (Eds.) Philipp Frank: The humanistic background of science (pp. 1-67). SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. F. (2012). Ernest Nagel and reduction. The Journal of Philosophy, 109(8/9), 534–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, M. (1936). Meaning and verification. Philosophical Review, 45, 339–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schliesser, E. (2013). Philosophic prophecy. In M. Lærke, J. E. H. Smith, & E. Schliesser (Eds.), Philosophy and Its history: Aims and methods in the study of early modern philosophy (pp. 209–235). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1994). Ernest Nagel: 1901–1985. In Biographical memoirs. National Academy of Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (2012). Reflections on Ernest Nagel’s 1977 Dewey lectures ‘Teleology Revisited.’ The Journal of Philosophy of Science, 109(8/9), 503–515.

    Google Scholar 

  • A.T. Tuboly (Ed.) (ms), The philosophical and personal correspondence of Ernest Nagel and Carl Gustav Hempel. Unpublished manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuboly, A. T. (2017). Philipp Frank’s decline and the crisis of logical empiricism. Studies in East European Thought, 69(3), 257–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, T. (2000). Logical empiricism and the sociology of knowledge: The case of Neurath and Frank. Philosophy of Science, 67(3), 138–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, T. (2007). Empiricism at the crossroads. The Vienna Circle’s protocol-sentence debate. Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, T. (2020). Intersubjective accountability. Perspectives on Science, 28(1), 35–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Riel, R. (2011). Nagelian reduction beyond the Nagel model. Philosophy of Science, 78(3), 353–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are grateful to Yvonne, Alexander, and Sidney Nagel for their support of the project and for their permission to use the archive materials of Ernest Nagel. Carnap's letters are quoted from the Rudolf Carnap Papers, Archives of Scientific Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh. All rights reserved. Papers of the volume were first presented at the “Ernest Nagel and the Making of Philosophy of Science” conference organized at the Institute of Philosophy, Hungarian Academy of Sciences (October 4, 2019). Adam Tamas Tuboly was supported by the MTA Lendulet Morals and Science Research Group and by the MTA Premium Postdoctoral Scholarship during the editorial work. We thank Christoph Gottstein for his help with the linguistic corrections, and all our authors for their work and time devoted to this project. We are also indebted to the numerous referees who read and commented the individual chapters, and to the two anonymous referees of the press who read through the whole volume and provided helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Neuber, M., Tuboly, A.T. (2022). Introduction: Ernest Nagel and the Making of Philosophy of Science a Profession. In: Neuber, M., Tuboly, A.T. (eds) Ernest Nagel: Philosophy of Science and the Fight for Clarity. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 53. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-81010-8_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics