Skip to main content
Log in

Replies to Kane, McCormick, and Vargas

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This is a reply to discussions by Robert Kane, Kelly McCormick, and Manuel Vargas of Shaun Nichols, Bound: Essays on Free Will and Responsibility.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In Bound, I reserve the term “revisionism” for the connotational revisionist, who uses a liberal reference convention. Vargas points out that on his taxonomy, one can also be a denotational revisionist, who maintains that there is a strict reference convention, but we can replace the empty notion of free will with a revised one. Indeed, Vargas notes that his account doesn’t exclude the possibility of a revisionist theory that doesn’t specify the revision. (p. 5, n4). It’s also true that in various formulations of revisionism, it includes eliminativism (e.g., 2005, p. 408), and the most recent characterization does not explicitly exclude eliminativism (Vargas 2013, 85). Vargas deserves an enormous amount of credit for setting out the revisionist program so systematically. But the general notion of revisionism seems quite expansive, and my interest is primarily in distinctions within this capacious set. Given the number of possibilities, I find it more efficient to use distinct labels for the positions. But one might also simply label them all “revisionist” with appropriate subscripts (e.g., revisionismconnotational, revisionismeliminativist, revisionismunspecified-replacement) since they might all count as revisionist under Vargas’ characterization.

References

  • Balaguer, M. (2010). Free will as an open scientific problem. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson, F. (1718). An historical essay concerning witchcraft. London: Knaplock and Midwinter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kozuch, B., & Nichols, S. (2011). Awareness of unawareness: folk psychology and introspective transparency. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18, 135–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (1988). Judgement and justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. (2015). Bound: Essays on free will and responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., Pinillos, A., & Mallon, R. (2016). Ambiguous reference. Mind, 125(497), 145–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Notestein, W. (1911). A history of witchcraft in England from 1558 to 1718. Washington: The American Historical Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scot, R. (1584). The discoverie of witchcraft. London: William Brome.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (2005). The revisionist’s guide to moral responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 125, 399–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (2013). Building better beings: A theory of moral responsibility. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Angel Pinillos and Heather Battaly for comments on an earlier draft of these comments. Thanks also to Dan Speak for organizing the symposium.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Shaun Nichols.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nichols, S. Replies to Kane, McCormick, and Vargas. Philos Stud 174, 2511–2523 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0742-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0742-z

Keywords

Navigation