Skip to main content
Log in

Deliberating About the Public Interest

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Although the idea of the public interest features prominently in many accounts of deliberative democracy, the relationship between deliberative democracy and the public interest is rarely spelt out with any degree of precision. In this article, I identify and defend one particular way of framing this relationship. I begin by arguing that people can deliberate about the public interest only if the public interest is, in principle, identifiable independently of their deliberations. Of course, some pluralists claim that the public interest is an implausible idea, which casts doubt on the idea that there might be something for people to deliberate about. Yet while, following Brian Barry, we can get around this problem by defining the public interest as an interest in which everyone shares qua member of the public, what still needs to be explained is why people should be prepared to privilege this particular capacity. I argue that the account of political equality with which deliberative democracy is bound up offers a compelling explanation of this sort, even if it also gives rise to some difficult questions of feasibility. I conclude by considering the charge that any political scheme that framed the relationship between deliberative democracy and the public interest in this way would be undesirable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For the purposes of this article, I take it that ‘the public interest’ is the same as ‘the common good’, ‘the public good’, ‘the general interest’, ‘the national interest’ etc. For of a discussion of the various distinctions that might be drawn between these concepts, see Douglass 1980; Barry 1990 [1965]. As I suggest in the main body of the text, as they are typically defined, the basic feature of these concepts is their describing a good that is common to an entire society. For a discussion of alternatives to this ‘common to all’ approach to the definition of ‘the public interest’, see Held 1970.

  2. One might naturally wonder about the status of the claim that ‘our lives are intertwined’. The thought here appeals to a familiar ‘golden rule’: insofar as our decisions have implications for others, we should be careful not to treat them in ways that we ourselves would not like to be treated. Of course, this injunction can itself be understood in moral or prudential terms, which will colour how we understand the idea of the public interest (see Douglass 1980). The argument of this article is primarily moral, as should be clear from the main body of the text.

  3. Deliberative democrats argue that preferences or wants should not be taken simply as given, but should instead be shaped through discussion and debate. Still, deliberative democrats typically define preferences as wants, even if they think that the only wants that are relevant to democratic decision-making are those that can be justified in open political debate (e.g., Sunstein 1993).

  4. Brian Barry imputes this latter view to John Miller (Barry 1964, p. 2; ref. to Miller 1962, p. 40). Although Barry does not elaborate, this view seems to have been fuelled by the nefarious ideological purposes for which the notion of ‘real interests’ has been used.  In particular, liberals (or economists of a liberal bent) are generally wary of separating interests and preferences too much, since that separations seem to ‘imply a decision-maker who stands outside and apart from the people whose interests he is assessing’ (Jones 1998, p. 18; for a general discussion, see Douglass 1980).

  5. Even here, of course, there may be scope for disagreement: people may reasonably disagree in their over-arching role as members of the public about what is in the public interest. But the point remains that different interests attach to different roles, even if that in itself does not settle all disagreements (see Goodin 1996, p. 339).

  6. As Robert Goodin puts it, ‘How extensive such shared concerns may be varies from place to place and waxes and wanes with time’ (Goodin 1996, p. 339).

  7. Virginia Held argues that Barry’s ‘approach appears to have serious difficulties, as it assigns no role in evaluations of the public interest to anyone’s net interest, which would seem to be what any individual asserting his interests in a set of activities would actually and justifiably ground them upon’ (Held 1970, p. 118). This criticism is unjustified, since Barry clearly says that where our special interest outweighs our share of the public interest, the public interest may have to give way. What Barry fails to explain, however, is whether balancing acts of this sort need to be based on pragmatic considerations only, or whether normative considerations also come into play (and, if so, which ones).

  8. Rehfeld offers a second defence of majority rule, based on the median voter thesis, which essentially says that in a two party system with many floating voters, candidates and parties will seek to please as many people as possible by moving to the middle of the political spectrum (Rehfeld 2008, pp. 226–227). Those conditions might obtain in the case on which Rehfeld focuses—the United States—but there are also many cases where they do not obtain. Even where they do hold, catering to the middle of the political spectrum might leave many minority interests unrepresented (i.e., parties might move closer together, but some sections of society might remain just as far apart as ever).

  9. In concluding their defence of the place of self-interest within deliberative democracy, Mansbridge and her co-authors ask: ‘Will legitimating self-interest, even in constrained from, undermine the capacity of the democratic deliberative ideal to inspire transformations in the direction of the common good? In practice, perhaps yes’ (Mansbridge et al. 2010, p. 78). Ultimately, it seems that Mansbridge is more concerned with taking pluralism seriously than with advancing the public interest in a decision.

References

  • Barry, Brian. 1964. The public interest. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 38 (supplementary volume): 1–18.

  • Barry, Brian. 1990 [1965]. Political argument: A reissue with a new introduction. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

  • Benhabib, Seyla. 1996. Toward a deliberative model of democratic legitimacy. In Democracy and difference: Contesting the boundaries of the political, ed. Seyla Benhabib, 67–94. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohman, James, and Henry Richardson. 2009. Liberalism, deliberative democracy, and ‘reasons that all can accept’. The Journal of Political Philosophy 17(3): 253–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christiano, Thomas. 1997. The significance of public deliberation. In Deliberative democracy: Essays on reason and politics, ed. James Bohman, and William Rehg, 243–277. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Joshua. 1989. Deliberative democracy and democratic legitimacy. In The good polity, ed. Alan Hamlin, and Phillip Pettit, 17–34. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Joshua. 1994. Pluralism and proceduralism. Chicago-Kent Law Review 69(3): 589–618.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Joshua. 1996. Procedure and substance in deliberative democracy. In Democracy and difference: Contesting the boundaries of the political, ed. Seyla Benhabib, 95–119. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahl, Robert. 1989. Democracy and its critics. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diggs, B.J. 1973. The common good as reason for political action. Ethics 83(4): 283–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglass, Bruce. 1980. The common good and the public interest. Political Theory 8(1): 104–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, Jon. 1998. Deliberation and constitution making. In Deliberative democracy, ed. Jon Elster, 109–111. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, Robert. 1992. Motivating political morality. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, Robert. 1996. Institutionalising the public interest: The defence of deadlock and beyond. American Political Science Review 90(2): 331–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, Amy, and Dennis Thompson. 1996. Democracy and disagreement: Why moral conflict cannot be avoided and what should be done about it. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1984. The theory of communicative action vol. 1: Reason and the rationalisation of society, trans. Thomas McCarthy. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy, trans. William Rehg. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Held, Virginia. 1970. The public interest and individual interests. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, Michael. 2004. Deliberative democracy and the plural polity. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, Peter. 1998. Intense preferences, strong beliefs and democratic decision-making. Political Studies 36(1): 7–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manin, Bernard. 1987. On legitimacy and political deliberation. Political Theory 15(33): 338–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mansbridge, Jane. 1998. On the contested nature of the public good. In Private action, the public good, ed. Walter Powell, and Elizabeth Clemens, 3–19. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mansbridge, Jane. 2006. Conflict and self-interest in deliberation. In Deliberative democracy and its discontents, ed. Samantha Besson, and José Martí, 107–132. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mansbridge, Jane with James Bohman, Simone Chambers, David Estlund, Andreas Føllesdal, Archon Fung, Cristina Lafont, Bernard Manin and José Martí. 2010. The place of self-interest and the role of power in deliberative democracy. The Journal of Political Philosophy 18(1): 64–100.

  • Mill, John Stuart. 1991 [1861]. Considerations on representative government. In John Stuart Mill: On liberty, ed. John Gray, 203–467. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Miller, John. 1962. The nature of politics. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Flynn, Ian. 2007. Review article: Divided societies and deliberative democracy. British Journal of Political Science 37(4): 731–751.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pateman, Carole. 1970. Participation and democratic theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Phillip. 2004. The common good. In Justice and democracy: Essays for Brian Barry, ed. Keith Dowding, Robert Goodin, and Carole Pateman, 150–169. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1996. Political liberalism, 2nd ed. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rehfeld, Andrew. 2008. The concept of constituency: Political representation, democratic legitimacy and institutional design. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, Jürg, André Bächtiger, Marcus Spörndli, and Marco Steenbergen. 2004. Deliberative politics in action: Analysing parliamentary discourse. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass. 1993. Democracy and shifting preferences. In The Idea of democracy, ed. Jean Hampton, and John Roemer, 196–230. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taagepera, Rein, and Matthew Shugart. 1989. Seats and votes: Effects and determinants of electoral systems. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, Iris. 1990. Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Earlier drafts of this article were presented at conferences in Southampton and Glasgow. I learned a great deal from audience members on each occasion. For insightful written comments, I am indebted to Peter Jones, Stephen Elstub, David Russell, the editors of this journal and anonymous reviewers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ian O’Flynn.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

O’Flynn, I. Deliberating About the Public Interest. Res Publica 16, 299–315 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-010-9127-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-010-9127-x

Keywords

Navigation