Skip to main content

Women Philosophers in Antiquity and the Reshaping of Philosophy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Women's Perspectives on Ancient and Medieval Philosophy

Part of the book series: Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning ((LARI,volume 24))

  • 230 Accesses

Abstract

This paper is a response to and discussion of Maddalena Bonelli’s “Women philosophers in antiquity: Open questions and some results.” It also aims to advance the general discussion of the issues Bonelli raises. In it I contextualise Bonelli’s discussion, and take up three of her questions: What is the status of the work of restoring ancient women to the philosophical canon? What criteria ought we to use to decide who counts as a philosopher? What sort of philosophy did women practice in antiquity, and in what ways might the restoration of ancient women thinkers to the canon change the way we conceive of ancient philosophy itself? I consider the way in which Bonelli’s paper advances the discussion of each question, raise some worries about the discussions, and provide suggestions for how we might think about these issues further. I maintain that the reshaping of the philosophical canon that takes place when we integrate ancient women involves a reshaping of the discipline, and of our methods for accessing it. This is a result I argue we ought to embrace rather than resist. I conclude with a summary of the main contributions of Bonelli’s paper.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    All in-text citations refer to Bonelli’s paper in this volume, unless otherwise indicated.

  2. 2.

    My discussion will focus on women in ancient Greek philosophy, but some of these same questions could be asked about women in other traditions, and those examples could in turn inform analysis of the Western tradition.

  3. 3.

    That said, the seventeenth century saw some other, limited coverage of ancient women philosophers in doxographies. In addition to Ménage’s project, this includes the works of Jean de la Forge (1663) and Marguerite Buffet (1668). For other works in the period between Ménage and Waithe (1987) see Waithe (2015, pp. 25–26).

  4. 4.

    For a discussion of Ménage’s work see Rée (2002, pp. 648–649).

  5. 5.

    This “coat-tailing” trend is discussed by Waithe in a newer piece (2015), and the trend for describing ancient women philosophers relative to a male philosopher, or based on physical appearance, is discussed in Hawley (1994). Hutton (2019, pp. 686–687) discusses how this trend continues at least into the early modern period (albeit with different labels) and continues to exclude or marginalize women philosophers.

  6. 6.

    At least in the restrictive sense of being focused exclusively on women philosophers. Christine de Pizan’s Le Livre de la Cité des Dames (c. 1405), which includes some women philosophers, is an early example of engagement with women intellectuals more broadly construed.

  7. 7.

    Beginning perhaps with the misgivings of Clark (1988) and Dancy (1989) in their respective reviews. Deslauriers (2012) also makes some critical points aimed at Waithe’s 1987 analysis.

  8. 8.

    Among other things, this risks downplaying the degree to which women were excluded from philosophy, as Deslauriers (2012, p. 345) points out.

  9. 9.

    Without perhaps wanting to plug her own project (as editor), works by Davies (2020), Pellò (2020) and Salomoni (2020), mentioned by Bonelli, are part of the wave of promising new research, some discussion of which would add an encouraging forward-looking dimension to this discussion.

  10. 10.

    Waithe (1987, p. xix). Waithe’s introduction gives an account of the state of the evidence at the time she started assembling it, which is as surprising as it is depressing.

  11. 11.

    Bonelli compares the use of Plato’s dialogues as evidence for the ideas of the historical figure Diotima to that same question with respect to Socrates. But these are not readily comparable, since there is independent evidence for the existence of Socrates, and this is not the case for Diotima. Her point about “lack of direct transmission and the verifiability of our sources’ credentials as regards male philosophers” (Sect. 1.4) might more aptly be made by reference to figures such as Thales or Heraclitus, for instance, or Hypatia versus Pythagoras, as evoked by Waithe (2015, p. 27).

  12. 12.

    Readers would particularly benefit from acknowledgement and some discussion of the advances made on this question by works in feminist history of philosophy, such as (but by no means limited to) Alanen & Witt (2004).

  13. 13.

    Witt (2006) and Waithe (2015) also suggest and discuss relevant criteria.

  14. 14.

    This is not quite right: for instance, in her final chapter Waithe considers women such as Arete of Cyrene, for whom we have no direct writings or clear attributions of theories, at least insofar as the treatment in Waithe is concerned. Later, Bonelli characterises Waithe’s criterion as “the exclusive consideration of women who have thought or written about philosophy” (Sect. 1.3). This is more accurate.

  15. 15.

    See also Waithe (2015, p. 23).

  16. 16.

    The conditions for which will vary by time and place, as Waithe (2015, p. 22) notes.

  17. 17.

    For reflections on canonisation see Rée (2002), especially pp. 644–652, Witt (2006) and Waithe (2015).

  18. 18.

    Conversely, Waithe (2015, p. 22) argues that being designated a philosopher in one’s own time is not itself sufficient as a criterion, nor is calling oneself a philosopher.

  19. 19.

    There is plenty of interest in thinking about “philosophy as a way of life” in the ancient context—see, for instance, Hadot (1995). But this is usually focused on idiosyncratic male figures. Consideration of the sometimes painfully domestic realm women thinkers often occupied has not yet been an area of such reflection.

  20. 20.

    On genre as a means of excluding women and Indigenous philosophers see Waithe (2015, pp. 23–24).

  21. 21.

    O’Neill (2007, p. 36) makes this point regarding gender as a philosophical topic: “[…] issues concerning gender have, since the time of Kant, been viewed as external to philosophy proper; they are of “anthropological” interest, matters of the social sciences that are beyond the purview of philosophy proper. But feminist historians of philosophy, with our acceptance of gender issues as constituting an important set of philosophical concerns, and with our openness to exploring different styles and genres of philosophy, are in an excellent position to excavate many of the women’s long-forgotten texts, and to demonstrate the philosophical contributions that they make. The work will be hard, but the payoffs just may change the shape of our picture of western philosophy.”

  22. 22.

    On which see e.g. Hutton (2019, p. 693).

  23. 23.

    Hutton (2019), especially p. 694.

  24. 24.

    On which see Waithe (2015, pp. 29–30) on “burning issue” bias.

  25. 25.

    Rée (2002, pp. 651–652) extends this point, relating it not just to our discipline’s past but its future: “If a canon functions, in the first place, to give a present identity to an intellectual discipline by defining the past of which it takes itself to be the inheritor, it also serves, secondly, to shape its sense of its intellectual options for the future, and hence to determine the kinds of works that get written, and indeed the kinds of thoughts that get thought. But in the third place, changes in forms of canonicity can have retroactive effects, entailing wholesale changes in conventional interpretations, alterations in traditional rankings, and even the deletion of whole ranges of works that were previously well-regarded […] it will require a reconfiguration of philosophical inquiry itself and a systematic reworking of its relations to its future and its past.”

References

  • Adamson, P. (2014). Classical philosophy: A history of philosophy without any gaps, volume 1. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adamson, P. (2015). Philosophy in the Hellenistic and Roman world: A history of philosophy without any gaps, volume 2. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alanen, L., & Witt, C. (Eds.). (2004). Feminist reflections on the history of philosophy. Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonelli, M. (2021). Women philosophers in antiquity: Open questions and some results. In I. Chouinard, Z. McConaughey, A. Medeiros Ramos, & R. Noël (Eds.), Women’s perspectives on ancient and medieval philosophy. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffet, M. (1668). Nouvelles observations sur la langue française, avec l’éloge des illustres savantes tant anciennes que modernes. Jean Cusson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, G. (1988). Review of the book A history of women philosophers, vol. 1: Ancient women philosophers 600 B.C.–A.D. 500, by M. E. Waithe (Ed.). The Classical Review, 38(2), 429–430. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009840X00122620

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, R. M. (1989). On a history of women philosophers, vol. I [Review of the book A history of women philosophers, vol. 1: Ancient women philosophers 600 B.C.–A.D. 500, by M. E. Waithe (Ed.)]. Hypatia, 4(1), 160–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, R. (2020). Donne guardiane? Un ragionamento dirottato. In M. Bonelli (Ed.), Filosofe, maestre, imperatrici. Per un nuovo canone della storia della filosofia antica (pp. 3–15). Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deslauriers, M. (2012). Women, education, and philosophy. In S. L. James & S. Dillon (Eds.), A companion to women in the ancient world (pp. 343–353). Wiley-Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Forge, Jean de la (1663). Le cercle de femmes sçavantes. Chez Jean-Baptiste Loyson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadot, P. (1995). Philosophy as a way of life. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, R. (1994). The problem of women philosophers in ancient Greece. In L. J. Archer, S. Fischler, & M. Wyke (Eds.), Women in ancient societies (pp. 70–87). Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hutton, S. (2019). Women, philosophy and the history of philosophy. The British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 27(4), 684–701. https://doi.org/10.1080/09608788.2018.1563766

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ménage, G. (1690). Historia mulierum philosopharum. Apud Anissonios Joan. Posuel & Claudium Rigaud.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, E. (2007). Justifying the inclusion of women in our histories of philosophy: The case of Marie de Gournay. In L. M. Alcoff & E. F. Kittay (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to feminist philosophy (pp. 17–42). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellò, C. (2020). “Non solo uomini, ma anche donne…”. La presenza femminile nella filosofia greca: Il caso delle pitagoriche. In M. Bonelli (Ed.), Filosofe, maestre, imperatrici. Per un nuovo canone della storia della filosofia antica (pp. 55–78). Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rée, J. (2002). Women philosophers and the canon. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 10(4), 641–652. https://doi.org/10.1080/09608788.2002.10383083

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salomoni, S. (2020). Pompeia Plotina: l’imperatrice filosofa. In M. Bonelli (Ed.), Filosofe, maestre, imperatrici. Per un nuovo canone della storia della filosofia antica (pp. 131–161). Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, J. M. (1989). Women philosophers of the Hellenistic and Roman world. In J. M. Snyder, The woman and the lyre: Women writers in classical Greece and Rome (pp. 99–121). Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waithe, M. E. (Ed.). (1987). A history of women philosophers, volume I: Ancient women philosophers, 600 B.C.–500 A.D. Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waithe, M. E. (2015). From canon fodder to canon formation: How do we get there from here? The Monist, 98(1), 21–33. https://doi.org/10.1093/monist/onu004

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt, C. (2006). Feminist interpretations of the philosophical canon. Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society, 31, 537–552.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

My thanks to the Footnotes Writing Circle for helpful discussion of a draft of this paper. This paper is dedicated to Rachel Prideaux.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Katharine R. O’Reilly .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

O’Reilly, K.R. (2021). Women Philosophers in Antiquity and the Reshaping of Philosophy. In: Chouinard, I., McConaughey, Z., Medeiros Ramos, A., Noël, R. (eds) Women's Perspectives on Ancient and Medieval Philosophy. Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning, vol 24. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-73190-8_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics