Skip to main content
Log in

The Taxon as an Ontological Problem

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Biosemiotics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Although the term taxon is one of the most common concepts in biology, a range of its meanings cannot be comprehended by an universal definition. Usually, biologists construe their knowledge of “the same” taxon by substantially different interpretations, so they find themselves in need either to justify this “multiplication of taxon essences”, or to surmount their plurality unifying its interpretations into a single explanation of what a taxon is. In both cases, an ontological status (“reality”) of that taxon is questioned. Therefore, discrepancy between universality of the taxon concept in biology and unavoidable plurality of its interpretations can be regarded as a source of problem of the taxon ontology. The present work aims to clarify the premises of this discrepancy using phenomenological approach. Three ways of the taxon positing (as a class, as a place in the world, and as a individualized body) have been distinguished. Taxon as a class is established by common essence that is shared by a set of living beings. These living beings are regarded as speculative objects beyond an idea of the world, i.e. as objects of the experimental science. A question about ontology of taxon as a class refers to the scholastic problem of universalia; its status can be defined within the scope of the nominalism/realism opposition. Taxon as a place of common appearance of the specimens is regarded in the context of the etiological relations unifying various entities into the entire world. Taxon as a place refers to a certain position in the Natural System that is construed as an etiological map of the world. In this case a specimen of a living being is known as a curiosity, i.e. representant of its relationships as well as of the place of its origin. Ontological status of a taxon as a place is to be clarified within the framework of the natural/artificial opposition. The positing of a taxon as a collective body marked off by limits of joint survival of living beings is characteristic for biology in the strict sense which arose in the very beginning of the 19 century. A taxon as a body established by the techniques of disciplinary power sensu M. Foucault extended from the human bodies to bodies of other living beings. The ontological status of a taxon as a collective body can be defined within the scope of the wild/domesticated opposition. Therefore, the discrepancy between the universality of the taxon concept and the plurality of its interpretations is underlayed by interpenetration of three distinct modi of taxon establishing. Distinguishing between these three modi can clarify sources of ontological problems concerned with the term taxon in each case when they arise.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Aristotle. (1998). The metaphysics. London: Penguin-Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1962). How to do things with words. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boethius, A. M. S. (1990). Commentary on Porphyry’s isagoge. In G. G. Mayorov (Ed.), A. M. S. Boethius. “Consolation of philosophy” and other treatises. Moscow: Nauka. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chebanov, S. V. (1983). Unity of conceptualizing the ordering procedures. Theory and methodology of biological classifications (pp. 18–28). Moscow: Nauka. in Russian.

  • Chebanov, S. V. (1996). Logical basics of typology in linguistics. Vilnius: VLANI. in Russian.

  • Chernykh, V. V. (1986). Integrity of higher taxa from palaeontologist’s point of view. Moscow: Nauka. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cracraft, J. (1987). Species concepts and ontology of evolution. Biology and Philosophy, 2, 329–346.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahlgren, R. (1975). A system of classification of the angiosperms to be used to demonstrate the distribution of characters. Botaniska Notiser, 128, 119–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Queiroz, K. (1999). The general lineage concept of species and the defining properties of the species category. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essayes (pp. 49–89). Cambridge: The MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1981). Natural kinds and biological taxa. Phylosophical Review, 90, 66–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1999). On the imposibility of a monistic account of species. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essayes (pp. 3–22). Cambridge: The MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (1992). Eliminative pluralism. Philosophy of Science, 59, 671–690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2001). The poverty of the Linnaean hierarchy: A philosophical study of biological taxonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1978). The will to knowledge, The history of sexuality: I. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1979). Discipline and punish. The birth of the prison. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. (1974). A radical solution to the species problem. Systematic Zoology, 23, 536–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gross, E. (2001). Forces. Gender Studies (Kharkov), 6, 61–72 (in Russian).

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry, D. P. (1997). Predicables and categories. In N. Kretzman, A. Kenny, & J. Pinborg (Eds.), The Cambridge history of later medieval philosophy (pp. 128–142). Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetterscheid, W. L. A., & Brandenburg, W. A. (1995). Culton versus taxon: conceptual issues in cultivated plant systematics. Taxon, 44, 161–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hetterscheid, W. L. A., Van den Berg, R. G., & Brandenburg, W. A. (1996). An annotated history of the principles of cultivated plant classification. Acta Botanica Neerlandica, 45(2), 123–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1965). The effect of essentialism on taxonomy: two thousand years of stasis. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 15, 314–326. 16: 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1922). Ideen zur einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologische Philosophie. Buch 1. Allgemeine Einführung in die reine Phänomenologie. Halle: Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ibáñez, J. J. & Ruiz-Ramos, M. (2006). A mathematical comparison of classification structures: The case of the USDA. Soil Taxonomy. Eurasian Soil Science, 39(7), 712–719.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, F. (1970). La logique du vivant (p. 354). Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagansky, V. L., & Kazantsev, N. N. (1979). On specificity of the mapping linguage. New themes, contents, and methods of the economic mapping (1975-1977) (pp. 43–49). Moscow: MFGO. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagansky, V. L., & Shreider, Y. A. (1992). Map as a general mode of the knowledge representation (geography beyond the geography. Scientific and Technical Information/VINITI. Ser. 2. Information Processes and Systems, 5, 1–6. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1984). Species. Philosophy of Science, 51, 308–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitts, D. B., & Kitts, D. J. (1979). Biological species as natural kinds. Philosophy of Science, 46, 613–622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lidén, M., & Oxelman, B. (1989). Species—pattern or process? Taxon, 38(2), 228–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Linnaeus, C. (1768). Systema naturae. Tomus III, [Regnum lapideum]. p. 262. Holmiae: Impensis Laurentii Salvii.

  • Linnaeus, C. (1780). Philosophia botanica. Berlin: C.F. Rimburgi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lubarski, G. Y. (1996). Archetype, style and rank in biological systematics. Moscow: KMK. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lubishchev, A. A. (1982). On criteria of reality in taxonomy. In S.V. Meyen & Y.V. Chaykovsky (Eds.), A. A. Lubishchev. Problems of form, systematics and evolution of organisms (pp. 113–131). Moscow: Nauka. in Russian.

  • Markov, A. V., & Neimark, E. B. (1998). Quantitative regularities of macroevolution. Moscow: Geos. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1966). Animal species and evolution. Cambridge: Belknap.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyen, S. V. (1978). Principal aspects of organisms’ typology. Zhurn Obshchei biologii, 39(4), 495–508. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyen, S. V. (1984). Principles of historical reconstructions in biology. In Y. A. Shreider (Ed.), The systems and evolution (pp. 7–31). Moscow: Nauka. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyen, S. V., & Shreider, Y. A. (1976). Methodological aspects of the classification theory. Voprosy filosofii, (12), 67–79. (in Russian).

  • Mishler, B. D., & Donoghue, M. J. (1982). Species concepts: a case for pluralism. Systematic Zoology, 31(4), 491–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oskolski, A. A. (2003). Curiosity: Its place and misplacement. In E. E. Surova (Ed.), Cultural space of travels (pp. 41–43). St. Petersburg: Centre of Cultural Research. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oskolski, A. A. (2005). Biology of a project of disciplinary power. Science and faith. Issue 7 (pp. 169–175). St. Petersburg: VRFS. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pavlinov, I. Y. (2006). Classical and non-classical systematics: where is the border? Zhurnal Obshchej Biologii, 67(2), 83–108. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Podoroga, V. A. (1995). Phenomenology of body. Moscow: Ad Marginem. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1969). Natural kinds. Ontological relativity and other essays (pp. 114–138). New York: Columbia Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel, O. (2005). Monophyly, paraphyly, and natural kinds. Biology and Philosophy, 20, 465–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1971). Gregg’s paradox: a proposed revision to Buck and notes on Hull’s solution. Systematic Zoology, 20, 239–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1987). Biological species: natural kinds, individuals, or what? The British Journal for the Philosphy of Science., 38(2), 225–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sennikov, A. A. (2003). Taxonomical concept in the genus Hieracium L. s.l. (Asteraceae). Turczaninowia, 6(2), 16–41. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sharov, A. A. (1995). Analysis of Meyen’s typological concept of time. In A. P. Levich (Ed.), On the way to understanding the time phenomenon: The constructions of time in natural sciences. Part 1. Interdisciplinary time studies (pp. 57–67). Singapore: World Scientific.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shatalkin, A. I. (1996). Essentialism and typology. Modern systematics: methodological aspects (pp. 123–154). Moscow: Moscow State University Press. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shatalkin, A. I. (1997). Classification and phylogeny. Predicative and genealogical concepts of a systematic group. Uspekhi sovremennoj biologii, 117(1), 5–17. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shreider, Y. A. (1984). Multi-level and system structure of the reality explored by the science. The systems and evolution (pp. 69–82). Moscow: Nauka. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, G. G. (1961). Principles of animal taxonomy. New York: Columbia Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1975). Animal liberation. New York: Avon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokoloff, D. D. (2001). Fractals, self-similarity, sturctures. In A. A. Oskolski (Ed.), Homology in botany: Experience and reflections (pp. 144–151). St.Petersburg: St. Petersburg Union of Scientists and Scholars. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Timonin, A. K. (1993). Towards the biologized systematics…. Zhurn Obshchei Biologii, 54(3), 369–372. in Russian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Valen, L. (1976). Ecological species, multispecies, and oaks. Taxon, 25, 233–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Uexküll, J. (1973). Theoretische Biologie. Frankfurt a. M: Suhrkamp. 378 S.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiley, E. O. (1981). Phylogenetics. The theory and practice of phylogenetic systematics (p. 439). New York: Wiley-Interscience.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkerson, T. E. (1993). Species, essences and the names of natural kinds. The Philosophical Quarterly, 43(170), 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zakharov, B. P. (2005). Transformational typological systematics. Moscow: KMK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zavadsky, K. M. (1961). The theory of species. Leningrad: Leningrad State Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am sincerely thankful to S.V. Chebanov, A.G. Cherniakov, A.A. Stekolnikov, I.Ya. Pavlinov and A.V. Shipunov for very productive discussions and some important comments on the manuscript of this paper. Special thanks go to E. Ramsay for his great assistance in the translation of this text into English. The research reported here was supported by the Russian Foundation of Basic Research (grants # 06-04-48003 and 09-04-00618).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexei Oskolski.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Oskolski, A. The Taxon as an Ontological Problem. Biosemiotics 4, 201–222 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-010-9099-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-010-9099-4

Keywords

Navigation