Skip to main content
Log in

Must Choices and Decisions be Uncaused by Prior Events or States of the Agent?

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is an important but unorthodox view within the philosophy of action that when it comes to certain mental actions of a person—her decisions and choices—these actions cannot be caused by her beliefs and desires or by any prior event or state of her at all. The reason for this, it is said, is that there is something in the very nature of a person’s decisions and choices that entails that they cannot be caused in this way. The arguments for this view, however, have largely gone unexamined. This paper, therefore, critically examines the arguments that have been proposed for this view. It concludes, however, that they are unpersuasive. There is, as yet, no good reason offered as to why we should think that decisions and choices must be uncaused by prior events or states of the agent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Thus, this is not the view that only a person’s freely made decisions and choices must be uncaused by prior events or states of her. It is the broader-in-scope view that her decisions and choices per se cannot be so caused.

  2. See, for instance, Clarke (1992), Nelkin (2004) and Roxbee Cox (1963).

  3. Of course, it would still follow given this criticism of (1), and granting (2), that decisions cannot be deterministically caused, which would be a significant result. But the issue here is whether decisions and choices are incompatible with causation by prior events or states per se, and not just deterministic causation by such events or states. And this claim is not well-supported by Ginet’s argument. (In later work, Ginet (2007) changed his mind about the anti-causal status of decisions, arguing that while decisions per se can be caused by prior events or states, a person’s freely willed decisions cannot be so caused.)

  4. Exceptions include Palmer (2016) and Timpe (2011), but these discussions are brief.

  5. When I say that a choice or decision cannot be caused, I mean they cannot be caused by prior events or states of the agent. Whether they can be caused in any other way—say by the agent as an irreducible substance (so-called “agent-causation”)—is not something I address in this paper. Both Goetz and McCann are skeptical that decisions and choices can be caused in this way, but they offer different explanations as to why not.

  6. He writes: “When we decide, we mean to be deciding, and we mean to decide exactly as we do—that is, we intend for the content of our decision to be precisely what it is. This is not a matter of our carrying out some prior intention to decide: spur of the moment decisions are just as intentional as those made after long deliberation…Intentionality does not have to be conferred on our decisions; they are intentional by their very nature” (2012, p. 254).

  7. That this is the argument they really have in mind is suggested by Goetz’s (2008) characterization of choices as “essentially” intrinsically active, as well as McCann’s claim that decisions are “intentional by their very nature” (2012, p. 254).

  8. Not all intrinsic properties are essential properties. That I am conscious is an intrinsic property of me, but it is not essential. I could be knocked momentarily unconscious.

  9. As I explained at the end of the last section, I am happy to grant McCann the claim, for the sake of argument, that decisions are essentially intentional and spontaneous. The issue here is why it would follow that if a person’s decisions and choices can be caused by antecedent events or states it would be possible for them not to have these features.

  10. In fact, causalists often take the challenge presented by causal deviance cases to be to spell out what “non-deviant” causation by prior events or states would consist in. For some influential causalist attempts to do this, see Bishop (1989), Mele (1992), and Peacocke (1979).

  11. Of course, decisions will have some essential features that intentional bodily actions do not. Decisions, for examples, are essentially mental. But the fact that decisions are essentially mental is no reason to think that they cannot be caused deviantly or that if they cannot be caused deviantly, then they cannot be caused at all.

  12. I would like to thank Jordan Baker and two anonymous reviewers for this journal for very valuable and much appreciated help with this paper.

References

  • Bishop, J. (1989). Natural Agency: An essay on the Causal Theory of Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. (1992). Deliberation and beliefs about one’s abilities. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 73, 101–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. (2003). Libertarian Accounts of Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R., Capes, J., & Swenson, P. (2021). “Incompatibilist (nondeterministic) theories of free will,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2021/entries/incompatibilism-theories/.

  • Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, C. (1962). Can the will be caused? Philosophical Review, 71, 49–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, C. (2007). An action can be both uncaused and up to the agent. In C. Lumer & S. Nanini (Eds.), Intentionality, deliberation and autonomy. Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goetz, S. (1997). Libertarian choice. Faith and Philosophy, 14, 195–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goetz, S. (2008). Freedom, Teleology, and evil. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCann, H. (1998). The works of agency. Cornell University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McCann, H. (2012). Making decisions. Philosophical Issues, 22, 246–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (1992). Springs of Action. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, D. (2004). Deliberative alternatives. Philosophical Topics, 32, 215–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, D. (2016). Goetz on the noncausal libertarian view of free will. Thought, 5, 99–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1979). Holistic explanations: Action, space, and interpretation. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roxbee Cox, J. (1963). Can I know beforehand what I am going to decide? Philosophical Review, 72, 88–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Timpe, K. (2011). Review of Goetz, Freedom, Teleology, and Evil. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 3, 460–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Palmer.

Ethics declarations

Competing Interests

The author has no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Palmer, D. Must Choices and Decisions be Uncaused by Prior Events or States of the Agent?. Erkenn (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-023-00729-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-023-00729-9

Navigation