Skip to main content
Log in

Practical knowledge first

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This idea that what is distinctive of intentional performances (or at least of those intentional performances that amount to skilled actions is one’s practical knowledge in it—i.e., knowledge of what one is doing while doing it—famously traces back to Anscombe ([1963] 2000). While many philosophers have theorized about Anscombe’s notion of practical knowledge (e.g., Setiya, 2008; Thompson et al., 2011; Schwenkler, 2019; O’Brien, 2007), there is a wide disagreement about how to understand it. This paper investigates how best to understand practical knowledge for it to play the desired explanatory role in a reductive theory of intentional action, of intention-in-action, and of control-in-action. I argue that practical knowledge ought to be construed as a dynamic knowledge state and that structured practical senses are needed to model it.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some textual evidence for Anscombe’s anti-reductionism can be found in Anscombe (1971, p. 137).

  2. This is by no means the only objection to a practical knowledge condition on intentional action. For example, Setiya (2008) argue that in case of basic actions, one might intentional perform an action without knowledge or belief that one is doing so. I bracket these objections here. See Pavese (2021a, 2020b) for discussion of these issues.

  3. For worries about the margin for error principle, see Berker (2008). For recent defenses of a margin for error principle for knowledge, see instead Srinivasan (2015).

  4. Anscombe often emphasizes that practical knowledge causes the success of the action and in this respect shares intentions’ direction of fit. By thinking of practical knowledge as closely related to intention-in-action, we might be able to account for the idea that practical knowledge is the cause of the action that it represents, and so accounts for its having both directions of fit.

  5. I think the converse (that if one intentionally \(\phi \) then one intends-in-action to \(\phi \)) might not hold true, due to the sort of counterexamples to the so-called Simple View (i.e., that intentionally \(\phi \) requires intending to \(\phi \)) which Bratman (1987) raised. I cannot discuss this complex issue here, so I will bracket it.

  6. Christensen et al. (2016) argue that cognitive control is present in expert skillful performance in the form of ‘higher-order action control’. Wu (2016) focuses on agentive control, which he thinks ‘yields phenomena of central philosophical interest: moral, rational, reason-based, skilled, conscious, epistemic and free agency’ (Wu, 2016, p. 101). Verbruggen and McLaren (2014) argue that adaptive and goal-directed behavior is to be understood in terms of agentive or executive control, in virtue of which people can regulate their behavior according to higher-order goals or plans. Finally, Toner et al. (2015) argue that skilled athletes use cognitive (or executive) control to maintain or improve their performance proficiency (see also Christensen et al., 2015, 2019; Fridland, 2014, Shepherd, 2014, 2021; Wu, 2011). These psychologists and philosophers all seem to consider it to be a hallmark of skillful performance that it is, in some sense to be specified, under the agent’s control.

  7. Stanley (2011, p. 161) responds to the articulability objection by pointing out that there is a sense in which propositional knowledge is always verbalizable. A punch-drunk boxer, who can demonstratively refer to his re-enactment of the way of boxing against southpaws, and says, “This is the way I fight against a southpaw,” intuitively knows that this is the way he fights against southpaws. This knowledge has an essential demonstrative component. But the same goes for much of other propositional knowledge, for example the knowledge we express by saying, “This is the tool for the job,” or “That is going to be trouble.” So, the response goes, know-how is verbalizable just like propositional knowledge is supposed to be verbalizable. However, this reply to the articulability objection assumes that ways to execute tasks are always ostensible and as such can always be picked up by a demonstrative. This does not need to be so: on any single occasion, one may only act on parts of a way. So for example, consider a swimmer who knows how to swim, and so, according to intellectualism, knows a proposition about how to swim. And yet when he swims, he only swims in a particular way, that adapts well to the circumstances in which he finds himself.

  8. It is also worth noting that in the recent literature, others have noted independently (cf. in particular Setiya, 2007, p. 25) that even Davidson’s carbon copier objection, and similar other cases, can be satisfactorily addressed when practical knowledge is understood along these lines. In Davidson’s example, someone is writing heavily on a page, intending to produce 10 legible carbon copies (Davidson, 1978). While writing, the agent does not know that they are producing ten legible carbon copies. Still, if they succeed in their goal, it seems that they did so intentionally. According to Epistemic Theory*, that is so because although the carbon copier might not know that they are producing ten carbon copies, they must know that they are writing firmly on a stack of copies in order to produce ten carbon copies. So the practical knowledge condition is satisfied. Indeed, the standard way of dealing with Davidson’s carbon copier objection (cf. in particular Setiya, 2007, p. 25) already provides a satisfactory response to Baseball.

  9. An interesting question that I have not attempted to address here is whether an epistemic theory of intentional action is more defensible than the more familiar commitments of knowledge-first epistemology. An anonymous referee notes that some of the major challenges to Knowledge-First epistemology (as traditionally construed) do not obviously generalize to an epistemic theory of intentional action. For example, Brown (2008) has challenged knowledge norms of practical reasoning using high stakes cases; Roeber (2018) has argued that these challenges can be generalized beyond high stakes scenarios. While I am not myself fully persuaded by these challenges to the knowledge-first account of evidence, it may well turn out that an epistemic theory of intentional action is more defensible than the more familiar commitments of Knowledge First epistemology.

References

  • Aarnio, M. L. (2010). Unreasonable knowledge. Philosophical Perspectives, 24, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. ([1963] 2000). Intention. Harvard University Press.

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1971). Causality and determination: An inaugural lecture. CUP Archive.

  • Beddor, B., & Pavese, C. (2021). Practical knowledge without luminosity. Mind. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzab041

  • Berker, S. (2008). Luminosity regained. Philosophers’ Imprint, 8(2), 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. (1984). Two faces of intention. The Philosophical Review, 93(3), 375–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. (1987). Intention, plans, and practical reason (Vol. 10). Harvard University Press.

  • Brown, J. (2008). Subject-sensitive invariantism and the knowledge norm for practical reasoning. Noûs, 42(2), 167–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, J. (2009). Anti-reductionism. In H. Beebee (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 279–298). Oxford University Press.

  • Cath, Y. (2019). Knowing how. Analysis, 79(3), 487–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cath, Y. (2020). Know how and skill: The puzzles of priority and equivalence. In E. Fridland & C. Pavese (Eds.), Routledge handbook of skill and expertise. Routledge.

  • Christensen, W., Bicknell, K., McIlwain, D., & Sutton, J. (2015). The sense of agency and its role in strategic control for expert mountain bikers. Psychology of Consciousness: Theory, Research, and Practice, 2(3), 340.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, W., Sutton, J., & Bicknell, K. (2019). Memory systems and the control of skilled action. Philosophical Psychology, 32(5), 692–718.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, W., Sutton, J., & McIlwain, D. J. (2016). Cognition in skilled action: Meshed control and the varieties of skill experience. Mind & Language, 31(1), 37–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1978). Intending. In Y. Yovel (Ed.) Philosophy of history and action (pp. 41–60). Springer.

  • Fridland, E. (2014). They’ve lost control: Reflections on skill. Synthese, 191(12), 2729–2750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frost, K. (2019). A metaphysics for practical knowledge. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 49(3), 314–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbons, J. (2001). Knowledge in action. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(3), 579–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Littlejohn, C., Carter, A., Gordon, E., & Jarvis, B. (2017). How and why knowledge is first. In J. A. Carter, E. C. Gordon & B. W. Jarvis (Eds.), Knowledge first: Approaches in epistemology and mind (p. 19). Oxford University Press.

  • Mele, A., & Moser, P. (1994). Intentional action. Nous, 28, 39–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, J. (2017). Factive and nonfactive mental state attribution. Mind & Language, 32(5), 525–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newstead, A. (2006). Knowledge by intention? On the possibility of agent’s knowledge. In S. Hetherington (Ed.), Aspects of knowing. Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2005). Anti-intellectualism. Analysis, 65(288), 278–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, L. (2007). Self-knowing agents. Oxford University Press.

  • Paul, S. K. (2009). How we know what we’re doing. Michigan Publishing, University of Michigan Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2015). Practical senses. Philosopher’s Imprint, 15(29), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2019). The psychological reality of practical representation. Philosophical Psychology, 32(5), 784–821.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2020a). Practical representation. In E. Fridland & C. Pavese (Eds.), Routledge handbook of philosophy of skills and expertise (pp. 226–44). Routledge.

  • Pavese, C. (2020). Probabilistic knowledge in action. Analysis, 80(2), 342–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2021). Know-how, action, and luck. Synthese, 198(7), 1595–1617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2021). Knowledge, action, and defeasibility. In J. Brown & M. Simion (Eds.), Reasons, justification, and defeaters (pp. 177–200). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2021). Knowledge and mentality. Philosophical Perspectives (A Supplement to Nous), 35(1), 359–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2021). Practical concepts and productive reasoning. Synthese, 199, 7659–7688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C., & Beddor, B. (2022). Skills as knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2022.2056753

  • Phillips, J., Buckwalter, W., Cushman, F., Friedman, O., Martin, A., Turri, J., Santos, L., & Knobe, J. (2021). Knowledge before belief. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 44, 1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piñeros Glasscock, J. S. (2019). Practical knowledge and luminosity. Mind, 129(516), 1237–1267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rödl, S., Sebastian, R., et al. (2007). Self-consciousness. Harvard University Press.

  • Roeber, B. (2018). The pragmatic encroachment debate. Noûs, 52(1), 171–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (2002). Amazing knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 99(4), 200–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwenkler, J. (2019). Anscombe’s intention: A guide. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Setiya, K. (2007). Reasons without rationalism. Princeton University Press.

  • Setiya, K. (2008). Practical knowledge. Ethics, 118(3), 388–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shepherd, J. (2014). The contours of control. Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 395–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shepherd, J. (2021). The shape of agency: Control, action, skill, knowledge. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shepherd, J., & Carter, J. A. (2021). Knowledge, practical knowledge, and intentional action. Ergo.

  • Singh, K. (2020). Anscombe on acting for reasons. In R. Chang & K. Sylvan (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of practical reason (pp. 172–184). Routledge.

  • Srinivasan, A. (2015). Are we luminous? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(2), 294–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2011). Know how. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy, 98(8), 411–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teh, N. J. (2013). Anscombe on non-reductionistic accounts of human action. In G. De Anna (Ed.), Willing the good: Empirical challenges to the explanation of human behavior (p. 227). Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

  • Thompson, M., Hornsby, J., & Stoutland, F. (2011). 7. Anscombe’s intention and practical knowledge. In A. Ford, J. Hornsby & F. Stoutland (Eds.),Essays on Anscombe’s intention (pp. 198–210). Harvard University Press.

  • Toner, J., Montero, B. G., & Moran, A. (2015). Considering the role of cognitive control in expert performance. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14(4), 1127–1144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vekony, R., Mele, A., & Rose, D. (2020). Intentional action without knowledge. Synthese, 197, 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verbruggen, F., & McLaren, I. (2014). Banishing the control homunculi in studies of action control and behavior change. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 9(5), 497–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1997). Knowledge as evidence. Mind, 106(424), 717–741.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wu, W. (2011). Confronting many-many problems: Attention and agentive control. Noûs, 45(1), 50–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, W. (2016). Experts and deviants: The story of agentive control. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 93(1), 101–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carlotta Pavese.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

No conflict of interest to declare.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pavese, C. Practical knowledge first. Synthese 200, 375 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03848-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03848-y

Keywords

Navigation