Skip to main content

Why Aristotle’s Virtuous Agent Won’t Forgive: Aristotle on Sungnōmē, Praotēs, and Megalopsychia

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Conflict and Resolution: The Ethics of Forgiveness, Revenge, and Punishment

Abstract

For Aristotle, some wrongdoers do not deserve blame, and the virtuous judge should extend sungnōmē, a correct judgment about what is equitable, under the appropriate excusing circumstances. Aristotle’s virtuous judge, however, does not forgive; the wrongdoer is excused from blame in the first place, rather than being forgiven precisely because she is blameworthy. Additionally, the judge does not fail to blame because she wishes to be merciful or from natural feeling, but instead, because that is the equitable action to take under the circumstances. Moreover, while Aristotle does claim in his discussions of the virtues of megalopsychia and praotēs that the virtuous person will sometimes fail to become angry at blameworthy wrongdoers, Aristotle’s reasons for repudiating anger or forestalling blame have little to do with the sorts of reasons that one would or could be forgiving for. Although an Aristotelian virtuous agent does let go of anger for her own reasons, she does not forgive. As a result, I argue that since Aristotle’s account of equity entails that forgiveness is positively vicious, forgivingness is not merely a virtue left out of Aristotle’s account, but is in fact incompatible with his account.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Sadler 2008 and Carter 2018.

  2. 2.

    As Curzer 2012 does.

  3. 3.

    Konstan 2010 and Phillips-Garrett 2017 have previously argued for the claim that Aristotle lacks an account of forgiveness. What I defend here goes further: not only does Aristotle lack an account of forgiveness, but forgiveness is positively vicious on his account.

  4. 4.

    As with many other conceptual definitions, alternative definitions have been proposed. Here, though, I rely on the most paradigmatic ways of understanding forgiveness. My definition bears a close definition to the one given in Hughes 2015.

  5. 5.

    Recent claims that this represents “the standard view” include Murphy 2001, 561; Darwall 2006, 72; Kekes 2009, 488–490; Westlund 2009, 507; Zaibert 2009, 388; and Warmke 2013, 915.

  6. 6.

    That the forgiver may forgive rightly even when the wrongdoer does not deserve it is precisely what some object to about standard views of forgiveness. Some critics (e.g., see Griswold 2007, 121–122 and Konstan 2010, 5–14) do contend that the wrongdoer must take steps to show that he is committed to restoration, but this does not mean that he thereby deserves forgiveness on this view, only that he is a viable candidate for it. Even on these views, however, such a wrongdoer cannot be said to deserve the wronged party’s forgiveness, who does nothing wrong if she elects to withhold forgiveness.

  7. 7.

    Hughes 2015. See also Griswold 2007, 7; MacLachlan 2008, 57–58; and Morton 2012, 7–8.

  8. 8.

    For more on this, see MacLachlan 2008, 57–58 and Morton 2012, 7–8.

  9. 9.

    I use “wrongdoer” to refer to anyone who has done a wrong action (that is, an action that does not hit the mean and hence was not what an agent ought to do). However, as will become clear in my discussion of wrong action and wrongdoers, Aristotle does not think agents are always blameworthy for their wrong actions.

  10. 10.

    I utilize Kennedy’s 2007 translation here. Kennedy’s translation prefers “fairness” for the Greek epieikeia, but I will use equity and fairness interchangeably since (in my view) “equity” captures the flavor a bit more precisely, but “fairness” sounds a bit more congenial to modern ears.

  11. 11.

    This is a slightly revised version of Ross’s 1984 translation.

  12. 12.

    See Phillips-Garrett 2017 for a detailed defense of the claim that sungnōmē is a cognitive judgment of excuse and a more thorough discussion of epieikeia and its relationship to sungnōmē.

  13. 13.

    We usually expect adult human agents to be responsible, but some adults lack the capacity for decision altogether (e.g., those that Aristotle calls “bestial” in NE VII.5 = EE VI.5) or they may temporarily lack the capacity to choose (as Aristotle suggests happens with the agents who are overstrained in NE III.1, 1110a23-26).

  14. 14.

    This brings to mind cases of tragic dilemmas, but seems to apply more broadly than just those cases. See also Rhet. I.13.16, 1374b4-6, where Aristotle extends sungnōmē to personal failings and mistakes since they are not the result of wickedness, but rather human weakness.

  15. 15.

    It is also important to note that this does not simply let anyone off the hook for any emotions that might overwhelm her; the relevant passions are only those that are essential to human nature. Passions that are neither natural nor human do not justify excuse, as Aristotle explicitly states that ignorant actions that are caused by such passions are not to be offered sungnōmē (NE V.8 = EE IV.8, 1136a8-9).

  16. 16.

    As suggested in Curzer 2012, 161n21.

  17. 17.

    This and subsequent passages utilize Taylor’s 2006 translation.

  18. 18.

    Cf. EE II.5, 1222b1-4.

  19. 19.

    It is not merely even revenge (an eye for an eye) that the irascible person seeks, but punishment over and beyond that. As Aristotle explains in Rhet. II.2, an agent is angry in response to a slight, which is a particular kind of perceived injustice. Reclaiming what one is owed (whether that is property, honor, or something else) may require punishment or blame, but the demands of rectificatory justice require that an agent receive precisely what would make her even, and not more than that (NE V.4, 1132a6-20). Thus, the agent who gets angry in the right amount, towards the right people, in the right situations, and for the correct length of time is just; she knows what she deserves, and she demands no more and no less. Since good temper concerns justice in relation to anger and retaliation, it concerns whether a wronged person’s anger and retaliatory strategies are proportional to the wrong suffered, so that the wronged person will receive both her property (or whatever else has been damaged or taken) and her honor back. She, however, does not additionally gain from the wrong done; she is merely recompensed. To gain additionally (through additional acts of revenge, for instance) would not be just, and this is what the irascible person seeks.

  20. 20.

    Cf. EE III.3, 1231b5-27.

  21. 21.

    Curzer 2012, 160–161.

  22. 22.

    Curzer 2012, 158 and 161.

  23. 23.

    See also Rhet. I.9, 1367a19-20, where Aristotle says that it is noble (kalon) to avenge and not to come to terms with the one who has harmed you: “to retaliate is just, and the just is honorable, and not to be defeated is characteristic of a brave man.” And in EE III.4, 1231b11-15, Aristotle says the servile person is one who is “abject in the face of insults.”

  24. 24.

    For others who agree with this underlying assumption, see Cairns 2003, 17, 39–40; Konstan 2010, 25; and Curzer 2012, 146–147 and 157–159.

  25. 25.

    Rhet. II.3, esp. II.3.5-6, 1380a14-26 and II.3.14, 1380b13-15.

  26. 26.

    See Homer, Iliad 24.54.

  27. 27.

    Konstan goes even further, claiming that the appeasing of anger in Aristotle’s account is “focused entirely on relations of status and power” (2010, 25).

  28. 28.

    Cf. Aristotle, De Anima 403a29ff.

  29. 29.

    This, of course, does not mean that his life is aimed exclusively at honor (Aristotle rejects this as the best sort of life at 1095b23 and 1159a22-25), nor that honor is the central thing the megalopsychos aims at rather than virtue. Rather, the megalopsychos certainly values and seeks virtue for its own sake, but he also recognizes that honor is the greatest of the external goods (1123b20), and as such, is worth pursuing.

  30. 30.

    Along with these tendencies, Aristotle also describes the great-souled person as moving and speaking slowly and in a deep voice (1125a12-16), although it is hard to see directly why those characteristics are relevant. I suspect they are relevant because Aristotle is attempting to reconcile Homeric honor culture with his own theory of the virtues, and as a result, Aristotle is importing cultural values that were generally held then. My suggestion is not the stronger claim that Aristotle is simply importing cultural values without modification, but the weaker claim that Aristotle is attempting to combine what he sees as the good parts of those cultural factors with his own account of virtue.

  31. 31.

    And more generally, 1124b9-15.

  32. 32.

    Curzer 2012, 124–125.

  33. 33.

    See Held 1993, 103.

  34. 34.

    Curzer 2012, 127n17 and 161n21. Curzer takes the category of forgiveness to be quite broad, but it is unclear what exactly he takes Aristotle to be sanctioning here, since he immediately follows this by noting that forgiving or excusing the unforgivable (presumably as laid out by Aristotle’s conditions on sungnōmē) would be inirascible (the vice of deficiency in relation to good temper). This is in response to Griswold 2007, 8, who claims that the megalopsychos is not forgiving on the grounds that the megalopsychos has no need to be forgiven because he is morally perfect, and hence sees no role for forgiveness in an account of ethics.

  35. 35.

    Taylor 2006, 225.

  36. 36.

    Griswold 2007, 8–9 and 16 suggests this type of response would be characteristic of the megalopsychos as well. See also Annas 1995, 119n239 on the indifference of the megalopsychos as well.

  37. 37.

    Dover 1974, 195.

  38. 38.

    I am grateful for the written comments on earlier drafts of this paper from David Riesbeck, Don Morrison, Tim Schroeder, George Sher, Hilary Mackie, and Krisanna Scheiter, as well as the illuminating conversations about this material with Stephen White and Victor Saenz.

References

  • Annas, Julia. 1995. The morality of happiness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1984. Nicomachean ethics, rev. ed. In The complete works of Aristotle, Trans. W. D. Ross, rev. J. O. Urmson, and ed. Jonathan Barnes. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. On rhetoric: A theory of civic discourse, 2nd ed. Trans. George A. Kennedy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Eudemian ethics. Trans. and ed. Brad Inwood and Raphael Woolf. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cairns, Douglas L. 2003. Ethics, ethology, terminology: Iliadic anger and the cross-cultural study of emotion. Yale Classical Studies 32: 11–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, Jason W. 2018. Aristotle and the problem of forgiveness. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 92 (1): 49–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Curzer, Howard J. 2012. Aristotle and the virtues. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, Stephen. 2006. The second person standpoint: Morality, respect, and accountability. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dover, K.J. 1974. Greek popular morality in the time of Plato and Aristotle. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griswold, Charles L. 2007. Forgiveness: A philosophical exploration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Held, Dirk T. 1993. Megalopsychia in Nicomachean ethics IV. Ancient Philosophy 13 (1): 95–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, Paul M. 2015. Forgiveness. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015 ed.). Ed. Edward N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries /forgiveness/

  • Kekes, John. 2009. Blame versus forgiveness. The Monist 92 (4): 488–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konstan, David. 2010. Before forgiveness: The origins of a moral idea. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacLachlan, Alice. 2008. The nature and limits of forgiveness. Doctoral dissertation, Boston University, Publication No. 3279942. Ann Arbor: ProQuest/UMI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morton, Adam. 2012. What is forgiveness? In Ancient forgiveness: Classical, Judaic, and Christian, ed. Charles L. Griswold and David Konstan, 3–14. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Jeffrie. 2001. Forgiveness. In Encyclopedia of ethics, ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker, 561. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips-Garrett, Carissa. 2017. Sungnōmē in Aristotle. Apeiron 50 (3): 311–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadler, Gregory. 2008. Forgiveness, anger, and virtue in an Aristotelean perspective. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 82: 229–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. C. W., ed. 2006. Nicomachean ethics Books II-IV, by Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warmke, Brandon. 2013. Two arguments against the punishment-forbearance account of forgiveness. Philosophical Studies 165 (3): 915–920.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Westlund, Andrea C. 2009. Anger, faith, and forgiveness. The Monist 92 (4): 507–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zaibert, Leo. 2009. The paradox of forgiveness. Journal of Moral Philosophy 6 (3): 365–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carissa Phillips-Garrett .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Phillips-Garrett, C. (2022). Why Aristotle’s Virtuous Agent Won’t Forgive: Aristotle on Sungnōmē, Praotēs, and Megalopsychia. In: Satne, P., Scheiter, K.M. (eds) Conflict and Resolution: The Ethics of Forgiveness, Revenge, and Punishment. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-77807-1_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics