Skip to main content
Log in

Re-assessing ecology of tool transparency in epistemic practices

  • Published:
Mind & Society Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, the radical view that transparent equipment is the result of an ecological assembly between tool users and physical aspects of the world is critically assessed. According to this perspective, tool users are normally viewed as plastically organized hybrid agents. In this view, such agents are able to interact with tools (artefacts or technologies) in ways that are opportunistic and fully locked to the local task environment. This intimate and flexible interaction would provide grounds for the thesis that cognitive agents and tools constitute literal extended cognitive systems. By contrast, a revised understanding of tool use transparency will be attempted. In this perspective, the interplay between on-line and off-line thinking is understood in terms of a socially reified cognitive delegation that subsumes the advantages normally associated to the so-called ‘open-ended ecological controllers.’ Thus, the notion of transparent technologies can be explored on the basis of a derived or mediated cognitive delegation. This view will be complemented by the notion of communities of practice (CoP). Special sorts of CoP will be proposed as suitable and flexible cognitive environments for the development of tool transparency.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Nontrivial Causal Spread, and the PEA are clearly presented and contextualized in Clark (2008).

  2. This intends to suggest that, in connection with the HEM, the characterization of epistemic tool use has not incorporated a well-balanced account of the relation between certain ecologically-coupled/decoupled processes.

  3. This process refers to how domain-specific minds of certain archaic primates may have evolved into modern human mind. The term is characterized in Mithen 1996 and 2000.

  4. This process refers to the actual material externalization of internal representations.

  5. This process refers to the re-internalized neural codification of external representations.

  6. Wilson (2010) also summarizes the varied research background that is normally related to these kinds of arguments.

  7. Manipulative abduction and epistemic mediators are introduced and illustrated in Magnani 2001a, b.

  8. Supposedly in a real sense, Clark (2008), and others, considers language to be our best tool.

  9. E.g.: Familiar teaching strategies that need to suit new learning objectives; or workplaces that need to be further engineered to accommodate new tasks.

  10. I am using this notion in the terms presented by Richard Cooper (1996).

  11. Following Sterelny’s argument that our ability to use epistemic artefacts depends on mental representations whose elaboration is based, precisely, on the use of this kind of artefacts (Sterelny 2004) as discussed in Sect. 2.1.

  12. In the case of multi-purpose rules of action (M-P RA), a certain commitment to their application in special contexts of occurrence will be necessary. This point will be elaborated in forthcoming sections.

  13. See Kirsh and Maglio (1994) and reference to “epistemic actions” in Sect. 2.1.

  14. Especially along the lines of what Sterelny refers to as “cumulative downstream epistemic engineering”, a process by means of which humans modify their epistemic environment and “affect information structures and opportunities presented to each subsequent generation.” (cited in Clark 2008, p. 66).

  15. A grammar model developed by the Australian linguist M.A.K. Halliday. See Halliday and Hasan (1976) for a comprehensive view of the model.

  16. See Dourish (2001) and Wheeler (2005). This point will not be further pursued in this paper. In connection with this symbiotic relationship, suffice it to highlight the relatively explicit ontological commitment to a naturalized notion of experience. I take this project to be one important motivation behind the reactive view of cognition I critically address in this paper.

  17. This is, for example, the sort of capacities that Clark (2006) considers to initially support the appeal to complex, distributed coordination dynamics that takes place when language is understood as an artefact. Language, in this view, is actually understood as the ultimate artefact or a “cognitive super-niche”, in that it allows us to construct an open-ended sequence of other cognitive niches.

  18. Clark (2003) provides and discusses plenty of examples.

  19. See Wenger et al. (1998) for relevant empirical findings.

  20. i.e. the sort of tools/artifacts/technologies without which such constellations do not seem to be recognized as being interrelated to one another.

  21. This is something that can also be supported by the findings connected with the relevance of highly structured training environments informed by recent studies on primate cognition (Iriki and Sakura 2008).

  22. In this paper, I have characterized this space in terms of the notion of CoP.

  23. See, for example, Magnani et al. (1999), Magnani and Nersessian (2002), Magnani (2006b) and Magnani and Li (2007) .

  24. Inferential reasoning can be understood as both sentential and model-based, where the cognitive character of external representations in MBR is based on semiotic disembodiment of mind.

References

  • Bass EJ, Pritchett AR (2006) Human-Automated Judgment Learning: Enhancing Interaction with Automated Judgment Systems. In: Kirlik A (ed) Adaptive perspectives on human-technology interaction: Resources for cognitive engineering and human-computer interaction. Oxford University Press, New York, NY, pp 114–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1997) Being there. putting brain, body, and world together again. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2001) Mindware. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2003) Natural-Born Cyborgs: Minds, Technologies, and the Future of Human Intelligence. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2006) Language, embodiment, and the cognitive niche. Trends Cogn Sci Vol.10 No.8: 370-374

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2007a) Soft Selves and Ecological Control. In: Ross Don et al (eds) Distributed Cognition and the Will. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 101–122

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2007b) Curing cognitive hiccups: A defense of the extended mind. J Philos 104(4):163–192

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2008) Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A, Chalmers D (1998) The Extended Mind. Analysis 58:10–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins SH, Ruina AL, Tedrake R, Wisse M (2005) Efficient bipedal robots based on passive-dynamic Walkers. Science 307:1082–1085

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper R (1996) Perseverative subgoaling in production system models of problem solving. In: Cottrell GW (ed) Proceedings of the 18th Annual Conference Cogn Science Society. San Diego, pp. 397–402

  • Donald M (2001) A mind so rare. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dourish P (2001) Where the Action Is: The Foundations of Embodied Interaction. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson JJ (1977) The theory of affordances. In: Shaw RE, Bransford J (eds) Perceiving, acting, and knowing. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale

    Google Scholar 

  • Gooding D (1990) Experiment and the Making of Meaning. Kluwer, Dordrecht

  • Halliday MAK, Hasan R (1976) Cohesion in English. Longman, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins E (1996) Cognition in the Wild. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Iriki A, Sakura O (2008) The neuroscience of primate intellectual evolution: natural selection and passive and intentional niche construction. Phil Trans R Soc B 363:2229–2241

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson-Laird, P.N. (2005). Mental models, sentential reasoning, and illusory inferences. In: Held C, Knauff M, Vosgerau G (eds) Mental Model in Cognitive Psychology, Neuroscience and Philosophy. Elsevier, Berlin

  • Kirlik A (ed) (2006) Adaptive perspectives on human-technology interaction: Resources for cognitive engineering and human-computer interaction. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh D, Maglio P (1994) On distinguishing epistemic from pragmatic action. Cogn Sci 18(4):513–549

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani L (2001a) Abduction, Reason, and Science. Processes of Discovery and Explanation. Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani L (2001b) Philosophy and Geometry. Theoretical and Historical Issues. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani L (2006a) Multimodal abduction. External semiotic anchors and hybrid representations. Log J IGPS 14(1):107–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani L (ed) (2006b) Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Engineering. Cognitive Science, Epistemology, Logic. College Publications, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani L (2007) Semiotic brains and artificial minds. How brains make up material cognitive systems. In: Gudwin R, Queiroz J (eds) Semiotics and Intelligent Systems Development. Idea Group Inc., Hershey, pp 1–41

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani L (2008) Chances, affordances, niche construction. In: I Lovrek, R J. Howlett, LC Lakhmi (eds) Knowledge-Based Intelligent Information and Engineering Systems, 11th International Conference, KES 2007, Vietri sul Mare, Italy, September 12-14, 2007, Proc, Part II, Series: LNCS/LNAI 4693, pp. 917–926

  • Magnani L (2009) Abductive Cognition. The Epistemological and Eco-Cognitive Dimensions of Hypothetical Reasoning. Series: Studies Cognitive Systems Monographs, vol 2. Springer, Berlin/New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani L, Nersessian NJ (eds) (2002) Model-Based Reasoning. Scientific Discovery, Technological Innovation, Values. Kluwer/Plenum, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani L, Nersessian NJ, Thagard P (eds) (1999) Model-Based Reasoning in Scientific Discovery. Kluwer/Plenum, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani L, Li P (eds) (2007) Model-Based Reasoning in Science, Technology, and Medicine, Series: Stud Comp Intell, vol 64. Springer, Berlin/New York

  • Mithen S (1996) The Prehistory of the Mind: The Cognitive Origins of Arts, Religion and Science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mithen S (2000) Mind, Brain and Material Culture: An Archaeological Perspective. In: Carruthers P, Chamberlain A (eds) Evolution and the Human Mind: Modularity, Language and Metacognition. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 207–217

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mithen S (2007) Creations of Pre-Modern Human Minds: Stone Tools Manufacture and Use by Homo habilis; heidelberggensis; and neanderthealensis. In: Margolis Laurence (ed) Creations of the Mind. Theories of Artefacts and their Representations. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian N (2008) Creating Scientific Concepts. The MIT Press, London; Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Norman D (1988) The Psychology of Everyday Things. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce CS (1877) The Fixation of Belief. Collected Papers (CP), 5.358–5.387

  • Peirce CS (1878) How to Make Our Ideas Clear, Collected Papers (CP), 5.388–5.410

  • Simon HA (1993) Altruism and economics. Am Econ Rev, Papers and Proceedings of the 105th Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association 83(2): 156–161

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2004) Epistemic Artefact and the Extended Mind. In: Schantz Richard (ed) The Externalist Challenge. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Webb B (1996) A Cricket Robot. Sci Am 275:62–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wenger E (1998) Communities of Practice: Learning, Meaning, and Identity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge/New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wenger E, White N, Smith J, Rowe K (2004) Technologies for communities. Available from the author at http://technologyforcommunities.com/CEFRIO_Book_Chapter_v_5.2.pdf. Accessed 29 Sept 2009

  • Wheeler M (2005) Reconstructing the Cognitive World. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson RA (1994) Wide Computationalism. Mind 103(411):351–372

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson M (2002) Six Views of Embodied Cognition. University of California, Santa Cruz. Psychon Bull Rev. 9(4): 625–636

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson R (2010). Meaning Making in the Mind of the Externalist. In Richard Menary (editor) The Extended Mind (to be published by Ashgate). Available from the author at <http://www.arts.ualberta.ca/~raw/>. Accessed 22 Sept 2009

  • Zhang J, Patel VL (2006) Distributed cognition, representation, and affordance. Pragmat Cogn 14(2):333–341

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Professor Lorenzo Magnani for his helpful comments and criticisms of all the drafts of the present paper, and especially for his generous and hospitable support during my stay in Pavia as a research intern at the Department of Philosophy and Computational Philosophy Laboratory, University of Pavia. To the other members of the CPL academic community, I would also like to extend my gratitude for their unwavering support and encouragement. Errors in this paper are my responsibility. This paper is part of a research project sponsored by FONDECYT (Government of Chile). Project No. 1095020. It is also a further development of my research internship at the University of Pavia. This postgraduate internship was made possible thanks to the awarded scholarship “Beca 2008 de estadías cortas de investigación para estudiantes tesistas de magíster y doctorado de la Vicerrectoría de Asuntos Académicos, Universidad de Chile”.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bernardo Pino.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Pino, B. Re-assessing ecology of tool transparency in epistemic practices. Mind Soc 9, 85–110 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-010-0071-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-010-0071-4

Keywords

Navigation