Skip to main content
Log in

Towards a Kantian Argument for a Universal Basic Income

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper defends that it is possible to offer a Kantian argument for justifying the introduction of Universal Basic Income (UBI). It first briefly presents Philippe van Parijs’ argument for UBI based on the concept of real freedom for all. In doing so, it will focus on its general structure and central insight, without entering too much into other issues like the economic feasibility of UBI. It second briefly presents Kant’s concept of external freedom and especially focuses on some of its components to assess whether there is some closeness to van Parijs’ concept of real freedom. It further considers whether UBI is not only compatible with a Kantian position, but can be justified from such a position because it represents a tool for concretely realizing external freedom as presented in the Doctrine of Right and for attaining the ethical ideal of virtuosity presented in the Doctrine of Virtue.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data Availability

Not applicable.

Code Availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. The introduction of UBI can be defended on the basis of different arguments such as the communitarian argument (Freeden 1992), the compensation argument (first used by Thomas Paine in Agrarian Justice: see Paine 1995), or the basic needs argument. None of them, however, can be defended from a Kantian perspective. I cannot prove this in this context, though.

  2. On this controversial thesis see Mészáros 1995, Rifkin 1995 and Gorz 1999. On the future of mechanization see Brynjolfsson and McAfee 2014.

  3. Children, particularly from poor families, may face many external obstacles to their education, even when there is a public system of education: schools may be too far away in the absence of public transport; parents may take children out of school because they need their help at home or to provide another source of income, etc.

  4. On Kant’s concept of external freedom see among others Ripstein 2009, Bird and Hruschka 2010, Horn 2014, as well as Pinzani 2017, 2021b.

  5. Quotations from Kant are marked by referring to the English translation I used (Kant 1996) and by indicating the volume and the page of the Akademie-Ausgabe of his works.

  6. It shares this formality with Kant’s metaphysical concept of right, which he defines as “the sum of the conditions under which the choice [Willkür] of one can be united with the choice of another in accordance with a universal law of freedom” (Kant 1996, 387; 06: 230).

  7. According to Kant, the criminal loses his “dignity of a citizen” through his crime, and, “though he is kept alive, he is made a mere tool of another’s choice (either of the state or of another citizen).” Now, Kant goes on, “whoever is another’s tool (which he can become only by a verdict and right) is a bondsman (servus in sensu stricto) and is the property (dominium) of another, who is accordingly not merely his master (herus) but also his owner (dominus) and can therefore alienate him as a thing, use him as he pleases (only not for shameful purposes) and dispose of his powers though not of his life and members” (471 f.; 06: 229 f.).

  8. See Hobbes 1996, 91 (Leviathan, chapter XIV) and Hayek 2011, 58 and passim.

  9. On this see Horn 2014, who convincingly argues for a non-individualistic justification for the existence of the state in Kant.

  10. On Kant on taxation see Penner 2010.

  11. It is noteworthy that the political community has a duty of self-preservation and therefore a duty to assist its poorest members while these have no corresponding subjective right to such assistance. On the contrary, it is evidently expected that they help themselves through work, since laziness is not admitted and since only individuals who, for different reasons, are not able to work are eligible for public assistance.

  12. As Paul infamously put it: “If anyone will not work, then let him not eat” (2 Thessalonians, 3:10). On Luther see Geremek 1994, 180.

  13. An example of this can be observed in the case of the abolishment of the Brazilian social program Bolsa Familia (one of the largest of the world) by the government of President Bolsonaro.

  14. Karen Stohr called my attention to this point.

  15. One could also claim that it represents a violation of human dignity (see Mieth and Williams 2022), but Kant’s view of this concept is not as unequivocal as it is often assumed (for an exhaustive analysis see Sensen 2011), and I would rather leave this issue aside since I think that the argument according to which poverty is a hindrance to the fulfillment of our duties already offers a good reason for eradicating it.

  16. Once again, I thank Karen Stohr for calling my attention to this point.

References

  • Bird S, Hruschka J (2010) Kant’s Doctrine of Right. A commentary. Cambridge UP, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brittan S (1975) The economic contradictions of democracy. Br J Polit Sci 5(2):129–159

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brynjolfsson E, McAfee A (2014) The second machine age. Norton, New York

  • Freeden M (1992) Liberal communitarianism and basic income. In: van Parijs P (ed) Arguing for basic income. Verso, London, pp 185–191

    Google Scholar 

  • Geremek B (1994) Poverty. A history. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilabert P (2010) Kant and the claims of the poor. Philos Phenomenol Res 81(2):382–418

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gorz A (1999) Reclaiming work. Polity Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasan R (2018) Freedom and poverty in the kantian state. Eur J Philos, 1–21

  • Hayek F (2011) The Constitution of Freedom. Chicago UP, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes T (1996) Leviathan, ed. by R Tuck. Cambridge UP, Cambridge

  • Holtman S (2004) Kantian justice and poverty relief. Kant-Studien 95:86–106

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horn C (2014) Nichtideale Normativität. Ein neuer Blick auf Kants politische Philosophie. Suhrkamp, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1996) Practical philosophy, transl. by M Gregor, ed by A Wood. Cambridge UP, Cambridge

  • Mészáros I (1995) Beyond capital. NYU Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mieth C, Williams G (2022) Poverty, dignity, and the kingdom of ends. In: van der Rijt JW, Cureton A (eds) Human dignity and the kingdom of ends. Kantian perspectives and practical applications. Routledge, Abingdon, pp 206–223

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray C (1984) Losing ground. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Otteson J (2009) Kantian individualism and political libertarianism. Indep Rev 13:389–409

    Google Scholar 

  • Paine T (1995) Rights of man, common sense and other political writings. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Penner J (2010) The state duty to support the poor in Kant’s Doctrine of Right. Br J Polit Int Relat 12(1):88–110

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinheiro Walla A (2020) A Kantian foundation for welfare rights. Jurisprudence 11(1):76–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinzani A (2017) Gibt es eine ethische Pflicht, äußerlich frei zu sein? In: Dörflinger B, Hüning D, Kruck G (eds) Das Verhältnis von Recht und Moral in Kants praktischer Philosophie. Olms, Hildesheim, pp 171–190

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinzani A (2021) Witness for the prosecution can Kant’s justification of poverty last in the court of reason? In: Serck-Hanssen C, Himmelmann B (eds) The court of reason, vol I. De Gruyter, Berlin, pp 209–226

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pinzani A (2021) Wie kann äußere Freiheit ein angeborenes Recht sein? In: von Freiin C, Merle J (eds) Kants Metaphysik der Sitten. Der Zusammenhang von Recht- und Tugendlehre. De Gruyter, Berlin, pp 79–94

    Google Scholar 

  • Rifkin J (1995) The end of work. Putnam, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ripstein A (2009) Force and freedom. Kant’s legal and political philosophy. Harvard UP, Cambridge (MA)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sensen O (2011) Kant on human dignity. De Gruyter, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stohr K (2011) Kantian beneficence and the problem of obligatory aid. J Moral Philos 8(1):45–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Parijs P (1983) L’allocation universelle. Ecolo-Infos 16(7 February):4–7

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Parijs P (1991) Why surfers should be fed: The liberal case for an unconditional basic income. Philos Public Affairs 20:101–131

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Parijs P (ed) (1992) Arguing for basic income. Verso, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Parijs P (1995) Real freedom for all. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Parijs P, Vanderborght Y (2017) Basic income. A radical proposal for a free society and a sane economy. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (MA)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van der Veen RJ, Groot L (eds) (2000) Basic income on the agenda. Amsterdam University Press, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Varden H (2014) Patriotism, poverty, and global justice. Kantian Rev 19(2):251–266

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinrib E (2012) Poverty and property in Kant’s system of rights. In: Weinrib E (ed) Corrective justice. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 263–297

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Williams H (1986) Kant’s political philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, Abingdon, pp 901–912

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The research leading to this paper was funded by CNPq with grant nr. 302590/2018-8. I thank for their suggestions and critiques the two anonymous reviewers of a first version of the paper, as well as Claudia Blöser, Violetta Igneski, Corinna Mieth, Reza Mosayebi, Oliver Sensen, Martin Sticker, Karen Stohr, Garrath Williams, and Ariel Zylberman. I would also like to thank Kim Butson for reviewing the text.

Funding

CNPq grant nr. 302590/2018-8

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Not applicable.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alessandro Pinzani.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of Interest/Competing Interests

Not applicable

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pinzani, A. Towards a Kantian Argument for a Universal Basic Income. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 26, 225–236 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-022-10339-z

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-022-10339-z

Keywords

Navigation