Skip to main content
Log in

Transcending the ultimate duality

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Asian Journal of Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In many philosophical traditions, it is held that reality is non-dual. Of course, to be non-dual, as opposed to dual, is itself to partake of a certain duality. If reality really is non-dual, it must transcend this duality too. But what could this mean? Can one make coherent sense of it? To keep the discussion focussed, I will locate it in one specific tradition: the Mahāyāna Buddhist tradition. The idea that ultimate reality is non-dual goes back to the earliest Mahāyāna sūtras at the turn of the Common Era. Thereafter, the question of what it means to transcend duality plays a central role in Buddhist philosophy. The point that reality must transcend even the duality between duality and non-duality plays a significant role in the Chinese Sanlun philosopher Jizang (, 549–623). His discussion points the way to an answer to our problem which may be articulated with the techniques of contemporary paraconsistent logic, as we will see.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For discussion, see Priest (2014), ch. 6.

  2. Della Rocca (2020).

  3. For discussion, see Priest (2021a).

  4. See Siderits (2019).

  5. See Ronkin (2018).

  6. Actually, over the next 1500 years, Mahāyāna itself fragmented into many different kinds. See, e.g., Williams (2009).

  7. The Sanskrit term satya is difficult to translate. The standard scholarly translation is truth, but reality is clearly a better translation sometimes. I will use whichever word seems most appropriate for the context.

  8. Price and Wong (1990), p. 51.

  9. Conze (1979), p. 651. The meaning of non-duality will concern us greatly in what follows. Dharmas are the elements of reality. We do not need to worry here about the meanings of the other terms of Buddhist philosophy.

  10. Conze (1973), pp. 271–2. Conze capitalizes “suchness.” I have removed the capitalization.

  11. Conze (1973), pp. 307–8. A Tathāgata (one thus gone) is a Buddha.

  12. Garfield (2002), p. 132, v. 16.

  13. See Thurman’s preface and introduction to Thurman (2014), and Priest (2018), 6.5.

  14. In Mahāyāna Buddhism, a bodhisattva is someone who follows the path to enlightenment, for themself and for all others.

  15. Thurman (2014), p. 73 ff.

  16. Thurman (2014), p. 77.

  17. See Deguchi et al. (2021), pp. 58–63.

  18. See Priest (2018), 7.2.

  19. Translations from Jizang are from Deguchi et al. (2021), pp. 64–70. The quotes make reference to the notion of emptiness (Chin: kong, ; Skt: śūnyata). Emptiness is a somewhat vexed notion that is central to Mahāyāna Buddhism. Fortunately, we do not have to worry about the matter here.

  20. In the passages cut out, Jizang identifies the duality between being and non-being with two others: that between permanence and impermanence, and that between saṃsāra and nirvāṇa. So he may naturally be understood as identifying all dualities.

  21. See Priest (2018), 7.6, and Deguchi et al. (2021), pp. 68–70.

  22. See Priest (2018), 7.7.

  23. See Priest (2018), 9.12.

  24. Another can be found in Priest (2018), chs. 5, 6.

  25. This way of understanding ineffability was first suggested to me by Maiko Yamomori, who, sadly, passed away earlier this year.

  26. A paraconsistent logic is a logic in which the principle of Explosion, \(A\wedge \lnot A\models B\) fails, Such a logic which accommodates contradictions but quarantines them, so that they do not spread. For a brief and informal introduction to paraconsistent logic, see Priest (2004) and (2021b). For a much longer and technical introduction, see Priest (2002).

  27. For a fuller discussion of the point, see Priest (2018), ch. 10.

  28. On second-order LP, see Priest (2002), 7.2.

  29. If one replaces this constraint with the simpler \(Y^{+},Y^{-}\subseteq D_{1}\), one has the logic FDE. This would do equally well for our purpose.

References

  • Conze, E. (1973). The perfection of wisdom in eight thousand lines and its verse summary. Delhi: Sri Satguru Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conze, E. (1979). The large sutra on perfect wisdom. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deguchi, Y., Garfield, J., Priest, G., & Sharf, R. (2021). What can’t be said: Paradox and contradiction in East Asian thought. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Della Rocca, M. (2020). The Parmenidean ascent. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Garfield, J. (2002). Empty words: Buddhist philosophy and cross-cultural interpretation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, A. F., & Wong, M. L. (1990). The Diamond Sūtra and the Sūtra of Hui-Neng. Boston: Shambhala.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2004). What’s so bad about contradictions?’. Journal of Philosophy, 95, 410–426. Reprinted as ch. 1 of Priest, G., Beall, J., & Armour-Garb, B. (eds.), New essays on the law of non-contradiction, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2002). Paraconsistent logic. In D. Gabbay F. Guenthner (Eds.) Handbook of philosophical logic. 2nd edn, (Vol. 6 pp. 287–393). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Priest, G. (2014). One. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2018). The fifth corner of four. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2021a). Review of Della Rocca’s the Parmenidean Ascent. Philos Rev, 130, 628–632.

  • Priest, G. (2021b). Dao De Jing and Mūlamadhyamakakārikā: Making sense of ineffability’. East Asian Journal of Philosophy, 1, 57–69.

  • Ronkin, N. (2018). Abhidharma. In E. Zalta (Ed.) Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/abhidharma/.

  • Siderits, M. (2019). Buddha. In E. Zalta (Ed.) Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/buddha/.

  • Thurman, R. (2014). The holy teachings of vimalakīrti. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, P. (2009). Mahāyāna Buddhism: The doctrinal foundations, 2nd edn. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

A talk based on an earlier version of this paper was given at the (virtual) conference Monism, Ancient, and Modern, at the University of St Andrews, July 2021. I am grateful to a number of members of the audience for their helpful thoughts and comments. Thanks, too, go to two anonymous referees for this journal.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Graham Priest.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

In this Appendix, I spell out the full technical details of the model described informally in 3.2.

The language of second-order LP contains predicates and constants. The connectives are ∧, ∨, and \(\lnot \); and there are first- and second-order variables and quantifiers. (We suppose, for simplicity, that the second-order predicates and variables are monadic.)Footnote 28

An interpretation is a triple, \(\left \langle D_{1},D_{2},\delta \right \rangle \). For every term, t, δ(t) ∈ D1. D2 is a set of pairs, \(\left \langle Y^{+},Y^{-}\right \rangle \), such that Y+Y = D1.Footnote 29 For every predicate, P, δ(P) ∈ D2. Let us write δ(P) as \(\left \langle \delta ^{+}(P),\delta ^{-}(P)\right \rangle \).

Write \(\Vdash ^{+}A\) and \(\Vdash ^{-}A\) to mean that A is true, resp. false, in an interpretation. Then the truth/falsity conditions are as follows:

  • \(\Vdash ^{+}Pt\) iff δ(t) ∈ δ+(P)

  • \(\Vdash ^{-}Pt\) iff δ(t) ∈ δ(P)

  • \(\Vdash ^{+}\lnot A\) iff \(\Vdash ^{-}A\)

  • \(\Vdash ^{-}\lnot A\) iff \(\Vdash ^{+}A\)

  • \(\Vdash ^{+}A\wedge B\) iff \(\Vdash ^{+}A\) and \(\Vdash ^{+}B\)

  • \(\Vdash ^{-}A\wedge B\) iff \(\Vdash ^{-}A\) or \(\Vdash ^{-}B\)

  • \(\Vdash ^{+}A\vee B\) iff \(\Vdash ^{+}A\) or \(\Vdash ^{+}B\)

  • \(\Vdash ^{-}A\vee B\) iff \(\Vdash ^{-}A\) and \(\Vdash ^{-}B\)

For the quantifiers, we assume that the language has been augmented with constants, kd for dD1, such that δ(kd) = d, and Kd for dD2, such that δ(Kd) = d. Ax(d) is A with every fee occurrence of x replaced by d. (Similarly for second-order variables.) Then:

  • \(\Vdash ^{+}\forall xA\) iff for all dD1 \(\Vdash ^{+}A_{x}(k_{d})\)

  • \(\Vdash ^{-}\forall xA\) iff for some dD1 \(\Vdash ^{-}A_{x}(k_{d})\)

  • \(\Vdash ^{+}\forall XA\) iff for all dD2 \(\Vdash ^{+}A_{X}(K_{d})\)

  • \(\Vdash ^{-}\forall XA\) iff for some dD2 \(\Vdash ^{-}A_{X}(K_{d})\)

An inference is valid, Σ⊧A, iff for every interpretation, if \(\Vdash ^{+}B\) for every B ∈Σ, \(\Vdash ^{+}A\).

Now, let t (tathāta) be ultimate reality. To obtain the model, we require, \(\mathfrak {M}\), take it to satisfy the conditions:

  • tD1

  • for all \(\left \langle Y^{+},Y^{-}\right \rangle \in D_{2}\), tY

  • for every \(Z\subseteq D_{1}\), there is a Y such that \(\left \langle Z,Y\right \rangle \in D_{2}\).

It is immediate that in \(\mathfrak {M}\), \(\Vdash ^{+}\forall X\lnot Xk_{t}\), that is, \(\Vdash ^{+}\lnot \exists X Xk_{t}\). t has no properties; it is ineffable. Let \(Z=\{d\in D_{1}: \Vdash ^{+}\lnot \exists X Xk_{d}\}\). Then tZ. But for some Y, \(d=\left \langle Z,Y\right \rangle \in D_{2}\), so in \(\mathfrak {M}\), \(\Vdash ^{+}K_{d}k_{t}\). Hence, \(\Vdash ^{+}\exists X Xk_{t}\). t has some properties—notably, the property of being ineffable. So it is effable.

Note that the contradictions in \(\mathfrak {M}\) need spread no further than t. If d is any other member of D1, it may behave quite consistently.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Priest, G. Transcending the ultimate duality. AJPH 2, 9 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s44204-023-00060-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s44204-023-00060-8

Keywords

Navigation