Skip to main content
Log in

Evolutionary Contingency, Stability, and Biological Laws

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The contingency of biological regularities—and its implications for the existence of biological laws—has long puzzled biologists and philosophers. The best argument for the contingency of biological regularities is John Beatty’s evolutionary contingency thesis, which will be re-analyzed here. First, I argue that in Beatty’s thesis there are two versions of strong contingency used as arguments against biological laws that have gone unnoticed by his commentators. Second, Beatty’s two different versions of strong contingency are analyzed in terms of two different stabilities of regularities. Third, I argue that Beatty and his commentators have focused on the more ineffective trajectory stability version of the argument, whereas the constancy stability version provides a more substantial and applicable argument against the existence of biological laws. Fourth, I develop a counterexample to Beatty’s thesis. Finally, I discuss the possibility of evolution producing repeatable and general non-lawlike regularities and patterns by utilizing the notion of generative entrenchment and by criticizing the thesis of multiple realizability of biological properties.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Bergmann’s rule is presented by Beatty (1995, 58–59) as an example of an evolutionary contingent regularity. If the lack of trajectory stability of the rule can be challenged, this casts doubt both on Beatty’s reasoning and on his examples of evolutionary contingent regularities.

  2. For the sake of argument, I presume that multiple realizability holds in the case of heredity information. Note that the argument presented here for the stability of generatively entrenched traits is independent of the truth of the multiple realizability thesis in the sense that, even if the thesis is presumed to be true, generatively entrenched traits are still capable of displaying trajectory stability. At the same time, if the multiple realizability thesis can be questioned, then generatively entrenched traits become even more stable in the sense of displaying high degrees of trajectory stability, because the functional necessities or generatively entrenched traits become realization “necessities” as well.

  3. Beatty developed his evolutionary contingency thesis as an elaboration of Gould’s ideas of the contingency of macroevolution (for an excellent review of Gould’s ideas, see Powell 2012). Beatty (2006) develops Gould’s evolutionary contingency further, distinguishing between the unpredictability notion and the causal dependency notion of evolutionary contingency. According to the unpredictability notion, evolutionary contingency means that unpredictable outcomes arise from the same or indistinguishable prior states. According to the causal dependency notion, evolutionary contingency means that a particular evolutionary outcome depends on which particular states preceded it. Both notions capture some elements of my trajectory stability version of strong contingency, yet neither is identical to it. I will not discuss Beatty’s two notions here; Powell (2009, 2012) and Turner (2010) already provide criticisms of them as meaningful interpretations of evolutionary contingency in the context of macroevolution. It suffices to point out that Powell’s (2009, 2012) idea of radical contingency, a notion that is meant both to unify the two Beattyan contingency concepts above and to give them a fair Gouldian reading, comes very close to my meaning of trajectory stability.

  4. The strict law like nature of CEP and its “same-level” explanations to exceptions are discussed by the author in detail in two other articles (under review).

References

  • Alroy, J. (1998). Cope’s rule and the dynamics of body mass evolution in North American fossil mammals. Science, 280, 731–734.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. W. (2000). Multiple realizablity and universality. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51, 115–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J. (1995). The evolutionary contingency thesis. In G. Wolters & J. G. Lennox (Eds.), Concepts, theories, and rationality in the biological sciences (pp. 45–81). Konstanz: Universitätsverlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J. (2006). Replaying life’s tape. Journal of Philosophy, 101, 336–362.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Mundale, J. (1999). Multiple realizability revisited: Linking cognitive and neutral states. Philosophy of Science, 66, 175–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrier, M. (1995). Evolutionary change and lawlikeness. Beatty of biological generalizations. In G. Wolters & J. G. Lennox (Eds.), Concepts, theories, and rationality in the biological sciences (pp. 83–97). Konstanz: Universitätsverlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrier, M. (1998). In defense of psychological laws. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 12, 217–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chesson, P. (2000). Mechanisms of maintenance of species diversity. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 31, 343–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chesson, P., & Huntly, N. (1997). The roles of harsh and fluctuating conditions in the dynamics of ecological conditions. American Naturalist, 150, 519–553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crow, J. F. (1979). Genes that violate Mendel’s rules. Scientific American, 240, 134–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1991). You can fool some of the people all of the time, everything else being equal; hedged laws and psychological explanations. Mind, 100, 19–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hairston, N. G. (1989). Ecological experiments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heatwole, H., & Davis, D. (1965). Ecology of three sympatric species of parasitic insects of the genus Megarhyssa (Hymenoptera: Ichneumonidae). Ecology, 46, 140–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hecnar, S. J. (1999). Patterns of turtle species’ geographic range size and a test of Rapoport’s rule. Ecography, 22, 436–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson, G. E. (1961). The paradox of the plankton. American Naturalist, 95, 137–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Irving, L. (1959). The usefulness of Scholander’s views on adaptive insulation of animals. Evolution, 11, 257–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (1993a). Natural laws and the problem of provisos. Erkenntnis, 38, 233–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (1993b). Lawlikeness. Noûs, 27, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2005). Ecological laws: What would they be and why would they matter? Oikos, 110, 394–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. D. (1997). Pragmatic laws. Philosophy of Science, 64, S468–S479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. D. (2000). Dimensions of scientific law. Philosophy of Science, 67, 242–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, G. J. (2009). Laws of biological design: A reply to John Beatty. Biology and Philosophy, 25, 379–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paine, R. (1966). Food web complexity and species diversity. American Naturalist, 100, 65–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, P., & Rey, G. (1995). When other things aren’t equal: Saving ceteris paribus laws from vacuity. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46, 81–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Powell, R. (2009). Contingency and convergence in macroevolution: A reply to John Beatty. Journal of Philosophy, 106, 390–403.

    Google Scholar 

  • Powell, R. (2012). Convergent evolution and the limits of natural selection. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2, 335–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raerinne, J., & Eronen, M. (2012). Multiple realizability and biological laws. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 34, 521–539.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. E. (1973). The philosophy of biology. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. F. (1995). Comments on Beatty. In G. Wolters & J. G. Lennox (Eds.), Concepts, theories, and rationality in the biological sciences (pp. 99–106). Konstanz: Universitätsverlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schank, J. C. & Wimsatt, W. C. (1987). Generative entrenchment and evolution. In Fine, A. & Machamer, P. (Eds.), Proceedings of the 1986 biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association (Vol. 2, pp. 33–60). East Lansing: PSA.

  • Scholander, P. F. (1955). Evolution of climatic adaptation in homeotherms. Evolution, 9, 15–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. A. (2000). Multiple realizations. Journal of Philosophy, 97, 635–654.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slobodkin, L. (1964). Experimental populations of hydrida. Journal of Animal Ecology, 33(Suppl), 131–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1997). Two outbreaks of lawlessness in recent philosophy of science. Philosophy of Science, 64(Proceedings), S458–S467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tilman, D. (1986). A consumer–resource approach to community structure. American Zoologist, 26, 5–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, D. (2010). Gould’s replay revisited. Biology and Philosophy, 26, 65–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Utida, S. (1953). Interspecific competition between two species of bean weevil. Ecology, 34, 301–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C. K. (1998). Causal regularities in the biological world of contingent distributions. Biology and Philosophy, 13, 5–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1999). Generativity, entrenchment, evolution, and innateness: Philosophy, evolutionary biology, and conceptual foundations of science. In V. Grey (Ed.), Where biology meets psychology (pp. 139–179). Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (2001). Generative entrenchment and the developmental approach to evolutionary processes. In S. Oyama, P. E. Griffiths, & R. D. Gray (Eds.), Cycles of contingency (pp. 219–237). Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C., & Schank, J. C. (1988). Two constraints on the evolution of complex adaptations and the means for their avoidance. In M. H. Nitecki (Ed.), Evolutionary progress (pp. 231–273). Chicago: University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The work was supported financially by the Academy of Finland as a part of the project “Causal and Mechanistic Explanations in the Environmental Sciences” (Project No. 1258020). I am grateful to the anonymous referees and to the editor of this journal, Helmut Pulte, who provided helpful comments and suggestions. N. Emrah Aydinonat, Markus Eronen, Till Grüne-Yanoff, Andrew Hamilton, Tomi Kokkonen, Jaakko Kuorikoski, Aki Lehtinen, Caterina Marchionni, Uskali Mäki, Anna-Mari Rusanen, Petri Ylikoski, Tero Ijäs, Petri Turunen, Rami Koskinen, Miles MacLeod, and Ilkka Pättiniemi all provided helpful comments, discussions, and suggestions on previous drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jani Raerinne.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Raerinne, J. Evolutionary Contingency, Stability, and Biological Laws. J Gen Philos Sci 46, 45–62 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-014-9271-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-014-9271-7

Keywords

Navigation