Skip to main content
Log in

Process, habit, and flow: a phenomenological approach to material agency

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The artefactual environment is not just the passive, inert background against which the drama of human and non-human animal life plays out; but rather, the built environment plays an active role in the structure of agency. This is an insight that Lambros Malafouris (2013) has articulated in his framework of Material Engagement Theory (MET). I will discuss the enactive-embodied and dynamic approaches to cognition and action, emphasizing the ways that this approach leads to taking MET seriously by force of its own theoretical commitments. That is, material engagement is a natural development of these models of mind, specified to the particularities of the human historical situation. I will then discuss Theiner and Drain’s (2017) critique of HMA, in which they argue that we should replace material agency with materially-scaffolded agency. Scaffolded agency, however, is too weak of a conception of how material culture shapes agency, and is a notion continues to privilege the sense of agency as a mark of what genuinely constitutes agency proper. Drawing on Steward (2016) I propose a definition of material agency that emphasizes the idea that agency is a process, and I suggest that material agency is better captured by the phenomenological experience of flow (Vuorre and Metcalf 2016). This phenomenological understanding of material agency both responds to Theiner & Drain’s critique, and emphasizes the importance of investigating material culture phenomenologically.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I will say, however, that many of their counter-arguments to Malafouris’ use of HEC could probably be defended if MET were to shift its focus from extended cognition to extensive cognition, as articulated by Hutto et al. (2014). This approach regards “minds as naturally extensive—the idea that cognitive activity always already entangles embodiment, action, and world-involving resources and does not restrict itself only to what is inside the individual organism” (10). Accordingly, cognition as a world-involving process is not a rarified or exceptional case. It is the rule, rather than the exception—an approach that I take to be much more in line with the general aims and commitments of MET. But this is an idea that requires much more defense and is outside of the scope of this article. Vaccari (2017), for instance, makes a critique of cognitive artifacts, but maintains that critiques of the traditional notion might not apply to Malafouris’ use of the concept within the framework of MET.

  2. In fact, the German word Augenblick, or the brief passing glance of the eye, is translated as ‘moment’ in English versions of Husserl’s Phenomenology of Internal Time Consciousness (1928/1964). Husserl’s choice of this word, which is interchangeably used alongside the English cognate Moment in everyday German, emphasizes the fact that even these incredibly narrow, seemingly indivisible sequences of time can be broken down into further moments of temporal flux. We might, for instance, be conventionally inclined to treat individual musical notes as the temporal atoms of a melodic sequence. But even these individual notes can be divided further (e.g. a half note could be divided into two sustained quarter notes, or four sustained eighth notes, and so on ad infinitum). A note itself is a diachronic phase situated within the horizons of the broader melodic event.

References

  • Bateson, G. (1973). Steps to an ecology of mind. London: Granada.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. (2010). Agency, time, and sociality. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 84, 7–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Denver: Bradford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (2004). A thousand plateaus. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1896). The reflex arc concept in psychology. Psychological Review, 3, 357–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. (2009). Extended life. Topoi, 28, 9–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2007). The natural philosophy of agency. Philosophy Compass, 2(2), 347–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2011). Multiple aspects in the sense of agency. New Ideas in Psychology, 30(1), 15–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2015). Doing the math: calculating the role of evolution and enculturation in the origins of mathematical reasoning. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, 119, 341–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gell, A. (1998). Art and agency: An anthropological theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The theory of affordances. In R. Shaw & J. Bransford (Eds.), Perceiving, acting, and knowing (pp. 67–82). Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gosden, C., & Malafouris, L. (2015). Process archaeology (P-Arch). World Archaeology, 47(5), 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenfield, P. M. (1984). A theory of the teacher in the learning activities of everyday life. In B. Rogoff & J. Lave (Eds.), Everyday cognition: Its development in social context (pp. 117–138). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1927). Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodder, I. (2011). Human-thing entanglement: towards an integrated archeological perspective. Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute, 17(1), 154–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1928/1964). The Phenomenology of Internal Time-Consciousness, (tr. J. Churchill.). The Hague: Marinus Hijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (2004). Material anchors for conceptual blends. Journal of Pragmatics, 37, 1555–1577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., Kirchhoff, M., & Myin, E. (2014). Extensive enactivism: why keep it all in? Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 706. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, J., & Scott, A. (2016). On the self-organizing origins of agency. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 20(7), 490–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. D. (2015). Extended cognition & the causal-constitutive fallacy: in search for a diachronic and dynamical conception of constitution. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(2), 320–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knappett, C. (2008). The neglected networks of material agency: Artefacts, pictures and text. In C. Knappett & L. Malafouris (Eds.), Material agency: Towards a non- anthropocentric perspective (pp. 139–156). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1991). Technology is society made durable. In J. Law (Ed.), A sociology of monsters: Essays on power, technology, and domination. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2010). Metaplasticity and the human becoming: principles of neuroarchaeology. Journal of Anthropological Sciences, 88, 49–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2013). How things shape the mind: A theory of material engagement. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2015). Metaplasticity and the primacy of material engagement. Time and Mind, 8(4), 351–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2016a). Material engagement and the embodied mind. In T. Wynn & F. L. Coolidge (Eds.), Cognitive models in palaeolithic archaeology (pp. 69–82). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2016b). On human becoming and incompleteness: A material engagement approach to the study of embodiment in evolution and culture. In G. Etzelmüller & C. Tewes (Eds.), Embodiment in evolution and culture (pp. 289–305). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L., & Renfrew, C. (2008). Steps to a ‘neuroarchaeology’ of mind: an introduction. Cambridge Archaeological Journal, 18(3), 381–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L., & Renfrew, C. (2010). An introduction to the cognitive life of things: Archaeology, material engagement and the extended mind. In L. Malafouris & C. Renfrew (Eds.), The cognitive life of things: Recasting the boundaries of the mind (pp. 1–12). Cambridge: McDonald Institute for Archaeological Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). The visible and the invisible. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012/1945). Phenomenology of perception. New York: Routledge.

  • Renfrew, C. (1994). Towards a cognitive archaeology. In C. Renfrew & E. Zubrow (Eds.), The ancient mind: Elements of cognitive archaeology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Renfrew, C. (2001). Symbol before concept: Material engagement and the early development of society. In I. Hodder (Ed.), Archaeological theory today (pp. 122–140). Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renfrew, C., Frith, C., & Malafouris, L. (2008). Introduction. The sapient mind. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London Series B, 363, 1935–1938.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E. (2008). Situated normativity: the normative aspect of embodied cognition in unreflective action. Mind, 117, 973–1001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E., & Kiverstein, J. (2014). A rich landscape of affordances. Ecological Psychology, 26, 325–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rogoff, B., Mistry, J., Göncü, A., & Mosier, C. (1993). Guided participation in cultural activity by toddler and caregivers. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 58(8), 1–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2012). The evolved apprentice. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Steward, H. (2016). Making the agent reappear: How processes might help. In R. Altshuler & M. Sigrist (Eds.), Time and the philosophy of action. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Theiner, G., & Drain, C. (2017). What’s the matter with cognition? a ‘Vygotskian’ perspective on material engagement theory. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 16(5), 837–862.

  • Vaccari, A. P. (2017). Against cognitive artifacts: extended cognition and the problem of defining ‘artifact’. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 16(5), 879–892.

  • Vuorre, M., & Metcalfe, J. (2016). The relation between sense of agency and experience of flow. Consciousness and Cognition, 43, 133–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in society. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work has benefitted tremendously from the feedback of Mike Butler, Nicolle Brancazio, Marta Caravà, and Morgan Elbot. I would also like to thank two anonymous reviewers for their careful and insightful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tailer G. Ransom.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ransom, T.G. Process, habit, and flow: a phenomenological approach to material agency. Phenom Cogn Sci 18, 19–37 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9541-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9541-z

Keywords

Navigation