Skip to main content
Log in

Individual Differences in the Interpretation of Commitment in Argumentation

  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The present study explored several dispositional factors associated with individual differences in lay adult’s interpretation of when an arguer is, or is not, committed to a statement. College students were presented with several two-person arguments in which the proponent of a thesis conceded a key point in the last turn. Participants were then asked to indicate the extent to which that concession implied a change in the proponent’s attitude toward any of the previous statements in the argument. Participants designated as ‘liberal’ used the concession to infer substantial change in commitment to earlier statements in the argument. A group designated as ‘conservative’ were reluctant to make any such inferences. A discriminant analysis indicated that variables assessing participants’ attitudes toward argument as well as their cognitive and communication styles jointly predicted their liberal or conservative status. The discriminant function and follow-up group comparisons indicated that liberals were more likely than conservatives to engage in argument. This included a greater tendency to use argument as a source of knowledge. Liberals also employed a more sophisticated message design logic than conservatives on a communication task. The groups did not clearly differ with respect to participants’ implicit theory of argument, though trends were present that merit attention in future research. Implications of these findings for future research on lay interpretations of commitment are discussed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bailenson, J. 2001. Contrast ratio: Shifting burden of proof in informal arguments. Discourse Processes 32(1): 29–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bailenson, J.N., and L.J. Rips. 1996. Informal reasoning and burden of proof. Applied Cognitive Psychology 10: S3–S16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Belenky, M.F., B.M. Clinchy, N.R. Goldberger, and J.M. Tarule. 1997. Women’s ways of knowing: The development of self, voice, and mind, 2nd ed. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benjamini, Y., and Y. Hochberg. 1995. Controlling the false discovery rate: A practical and powerful approach to multiple testing. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society B 57(1): 289–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chapman, M. 1993. Everyday reasoning and the revision of belief. In Mechanisms of everyday cognition, ed. J.M. Puckett, and H.W. Reese. Hillsdale, NJ: LEA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummings, L. 2005. Pragmatics: A multidisciplinary perspective. Mahwah, NJ: LEA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J.St.B.T. 2007. Hypothetical thinking: Dual processes in reasoning and judgement. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felton, M.K. 2004. The development of discourse strategies in adolescent argumentation. Cognitive Development 19: 35–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felton, M., and D. Kuhn. 2001. The development of argumentive discourse skill. Discourse Processes 32(2&3): 135–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank, D.A. 2004. Argumentation studies in the wake of The New Rhetoric. Argumentation and Advocacy 40: 267–283.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galotti, K.M., B. McVicker-Clinchy, K.H. Ainsworth, B. Lavin, and A.F. Mansfield. 1999. A new way of assessing ways of knowing: The attitudes towards thinking and learning survey (ATTLS). Sex Roles 40(9/10): 745–766.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M.A. 1997. Coalescent argumentation. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gratton, C. 2000. Counterexamples and tacit premises. Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 20(1): 9–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, Ch.L. 1970. Fallacies. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, M.A., and P.J. Mineo. 2002. Argumentativeness and its effect on verbal aggressiveness: A meta-analytic review. In Interpersonal communication research: Advances through meta-analysis, ed. M. Allen, R.W. Preiss, B.M. Gayle, and N. Burrell, 281–314. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hample, D. 2005. Arguing: Exchanging reasons face to face. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hample, D., B. Warner, and D. Young. 2009. Framing and editing interpersonal arguments. Argumentation 23: 21–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. 1992. The interrogative model of inquiry as a general theory of communication and cognition. Communication and Cognition 25(2 and 3): 221–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Infante, D.A. 1981. Trait argumentativeness as a predictor of communicative behavior in situations requiring argument. Central States Speech Journal 32: 265–272.

    Google Scholar 

  • Infante, D.A., and A.S. Rancer. 1982. A conceptualization and measure of argumentation. Journal of Personality Assessment 46: 72–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Infante, D.A., M.M. Step, and C.I. Horvath. 1997. Counterattitudinal advocacy: When high argumentatives are more persuasible. Communication Research Reports 14: 79–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, S. 1989. Speech acts and arguments. Argumentation 3: 345–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kazoleas, D. 1993. The impact of argumentativeness on resistance to persuasion. Human Communication Research 20: 118–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klaczynski, P.A., and K.L. Lavallee. 2005. Domain-specific identity, epistemic regulation, and intellectual ability as predictors of belief-biased reasoning: A dual-process perspective. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 92(1): 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krabbe, E.C.W. 1985. Formal systems of dialogue rules. Synthese 63: 295–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, D. 2005. Education for thinking. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leitao, S. 2000. The potential of argument in knowledge building. Human Development 43: 332–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, J.D. 1985. No logic before Friday. Synthese 79: 99–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, J.D. 1990. Four dialogue systems. Studia Logica 49: 567–583.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M.M., C.M. Anderson, and K.S. Thweatt. 1998. Aggressive communication traits and their relationship with the cognitive flexibility scale and the communication flexibility scale. Journal of Social Behavior and Personality 13: 531–540.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Keefe, B.J. 1988. The logic of message design: Individual differences in reasoning about communication. Communication Monographs 55: 80–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Keefe, B.J. 1990. The logic of regulative communication: Understanding the rationality of message designs. In Seeking compliance: The production of interpersonal influence messages, ed. J. Dillard, 87–106. Scottsdale, AZ: Gorusuch-Scarisbrick.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Keefe, D.J. 2003. Against familywise alpha adjustment. Human Communication Research 29: 431–447.

    Google Scholar 

  • Onyekwere, E.O., R.B. Rubin, and D.A. Infante. 1991. Interpersonal perception and communication satisfaction as a function of argumentativeness and ego-involvement. Communication Quarterly 39: 35–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pacini, R., and S. Epstein. 1999. The relation of rational and experiential information processing styles to personality, basic beliefs, and the ratio-bias phenomenon. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 76(6): 972–987.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rancer, A.S., and T.A. Avtgis. 2006. Argumentative and aggressive communication: Theory, research, and application. Thousand Oaks CA: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rancer, A.S., and D.A. Infante. 1985. Relations between motivation to argue and the argumentativeness of adversaries. Communication Quarterly 33: 209–218.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rancer, A.S., R.L. Kosberg, and R.A. Baukus. 1992. Beliefs about arguing as predictors of trait argumentativeness: Implications for training in argument and conflict management. Communication Education 41: 375–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. 1977. Dialectics: A controversy-oriented approach to the theory of knowledge. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricco, R.B. 2002. Analyzing the roles of challenge and defense in argumentation. Argumentation and Advocacy 39(1): 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rips, L.J. 1998. Reasoning and conversation. Psychological Review 105(3): 411–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rips, L.J., S.K. Brem, and J.N. Bailenson. 1999. Reasoning dialogues. Current Directions in Psychological Science 8(6): 172–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrodt, P., and L. Wheeless. 2001. Aggressive communication and informational reception apprehension: The influence of listening anxiety and intellectual inflexibility on trait argumentativeness and verbal aggressiveness. Communication Quarterly 49: 53–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. 1969. Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich, K.E., and R.F. West. 1997. Reasoning independently of prior belief and individual differences in actively open-minded thinking. Journal of Educational Psychology 89(2): 342–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tabachnick, B.G., and L.S. Fidell. 2001. Using multivariate statistics, 4th ed. Boston: Allyn and Bacon.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 2004. A systematic theory of argumentation: The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H., and P. Houtlosser. 2007. The study of argument as normative pragmatics. Pragmatics and Cognition 15(1): 161–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H., R. Grootendorst, F. Snoeck Henkemans, J.A. Blair, R.H. Johnson, E.C. Krabbe, et al. 1996. Fundamentals of argumentation theory. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H., R. Grootendorst, and F. Snoeck Henkemans. 2002. Argumentation: Analysis, evaluation, presentation. Mahwah, NJ: LEA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. 1987. Informal fallacies: Towards a theory of argument criticisms. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. 1989. Dialogue theory for critical thinking. Argumentation 3: 169–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. 1996. Argumentation schemes for presumptive reasoning. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. 2000. The place of dialogue theory in logic, computer science, and communication studies. Synthese 123: 327–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N., and E.C. Krabbe. 1995. Commitment in dialogue. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, V.S.L., L.V. Jones, and J.W. Tukey. 1999. Controlling error in multiple comparisons, with examples from state-to-state differences in educational achievement. Journal of Educational and Behavioral Statistics 24(1): 42–69.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert B. Ricco.

Appendix

Appendix

 

Turn

Arguer

Statement

Pro-death-penalty argument

 1.

Bob

The death penalty should be adopted by all states

 2.

Ed

Why do you say that?

 3.

Bob

It’s punishment that fits the crime—a life for a life

 4.

Ed

No. It’s punishment that is no better than the crime. Killing is wrong whether its by a criminal or the State

 5.

Bob

You can’t compare execution of a violent criminal in the name of justice with the murder of innocent life

 6.

Ed

Yes, you can. If its wrong to kill, then it doesn’t matter what the circumstance is

 7.

Bob

Okay, you’re right about that

Con-death-penalty argument

 1.

Bob

The death penalty should be banned in California and other states

 2.

Ed

Why do you say that?

 3.

Bob

It’s a cruel and unusual form of punishment

 4.

Ed

It’s not cruel. It’s punishment that fits the crime—a life for a life

 5.

Bob

No. It’s punishment that is no better than the crime. Killing is wrong whether its by a criminal or the State

 6.

Ed

You can’t compare execution of a violent criminal in the name of justice with the murder of innocent life

 7.

Bob

Okay, you’re right about that

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Ricco, R.B., Sierra, A.N. Individual Differences in the Interpretation of Commitment in Argumentation. Argumentation 25, 37–61 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-010-9191-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-010-9191-6

Keywords

Navigation