Skip to main content
Log in

Objective List Theories and Ill-Being

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What, if anything, directly detracts from well-being? Objective list theorists affirm basic goods such as knowledge, friendship, and achievement, but it is less clear what they should say about opposing bads. In this paper, I argue that false beliefs, unhealthy relationships, and failed projects are not basic bads and do not directly detract from well-being. They can have bad effects or elements, or block the realization of basic goods, but do not themselves carry negative weight with respect to well-being. This is shown by comparing cases where these bads are present and absent, examining their relation to negative overall well-being, and considering the role of these bads in the pursuit of positive goods.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Kagan (2014).

  2. Objective list theories or similar views are defended in Finnis (1980); Griffin (1986); Griffin (2000); Chappell (1998); Scanlon (1998); Arneson (1999); Nussbaum (2000); Murphy (2001); Kazez (2007); Oderberg (2008); Hurka (2011); Fletcher (2013); Rice (2013); Couto (2014); Hooker (2015). See also the discussions of objective list theories in Parfit (1984), Appendix I, “What Makes Someone’s Life Go Best”; and Moore (2000).

  3. See Heathwood (2015), p. 140; Lin (2016).

  4. Moore (2000), p. 77.

  5. Kagan (2014), p. 263.

  6. Kagan (2014), p. 275.

  7. Kagan (2014), p. 263.

  8. Pain may seem obvious as a basic bad, but for an alternative view, see Murphy (2001), pp. 96–100, 118–126.

  9. Parfit (1984), p. 499. Kagan considers Parfit’s list of bads in Kagan (2014), pp. 272–276.

  10. Hooker (2015), “Separate-Element vs. Combined-Element Theories,” para. 17.

  11. Murphy (2001), pp. 40–43.

  12. Murphy (2001), pp. 43–44. Similarly, outside the well-being debate, Thomas Hurka makes a similar point, stating that “narrow perfectionism… does not permit talk of intrinsic evils. Because an essentialist property cannot be realized to negative degrees, the theory’s scale of quality must have zero as its lowest point.” Hurka (1993).

  13. See, for example, Hooker (2015).

  14. See Clifford (1999).

  15. See Hooker (1998).

  16. Kagan (2014), p. 280.

  17. Thanks to an anonymous referee for encouraging me to stress this point.

  18. This is in part due to my tentativeness on these issues, but also to maintain a perspective that is inclusive of the different theorists surveyed in section 4.

  19. David Benatar is perhaps the thinker most associated with negative well-being, yet even he does not posit false beliefs as a basic bad. In discussing objective list theories and the good of knowledge, he notes how even the brightest humans possess only a very small fraction of all possible knowledge. In this way, he minimizes the value of knowledge, but does not suggest that false beliefs are a basic bad. See Benatar (2017).

  20. Nozick (1974), pp. 42.

  21. Nozick (1974), pp. 43–44.

  22. Thanks to an anonymous referee for suggesting that I clarify this.

  23. Parfit (1984), p. 499.

  24. Nagel (1979); Kagan (1994).

  25. Bradford (2015).

  26. Thanks to an anonymous referee for recommending that I address this issue.

  27. Thanks to Stephen Campbell and William Lauinger for very helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

References

  • Arneson RJ (1999) Human Flourishing Versus Desire Satisfaction. Soc Philos Policy 16:113–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benatar D (2017) The Human Predicament: A Candid Guide to Life’s Biggest Questions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bradford G (2015) Achievement. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chappell TDJ (1998) Understanding Human Goods: A Theory of Ethics. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Clifford WK (1999) The Ethics of Belief [1877]. In: Clifford WK (ed) The Ethics of Belief and Other Essays, Amherst, Prometheus Books, pp 70–96

  • Couto A (2014) Liberal Perfectionism: The Reasons that Goodness Gives. De Gruyter, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Finnis J (1980) Natural Law and Natural Rights. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher G (2013) A Fresh Start for the Objective List Theory of Well-Being. Utilitas 25:206–220

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffin J (2000) Replies. In: Crisp R, Hooker B (eds) Well-Being and Morality: Essays in Honour of James Griffin. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 281–313

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin J (1986) Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Moral Importance. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Heathwood C (2015) Monism and Pluralism about Value. In: Hirose I, Olson J (eds) The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 136–157

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker B (1998) Does Moral Virtue Constitute a Benefit to the Agent? In: Crisp R (ed) How Should One Live?: Essays on the Virtues. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 141–155

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker B (2015) The Elements of Well-Being. J Practical Ethics 3:15–35 Available at: http://www.jpe.ox.ac.uk/papers/the-elements-of-well-being/

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurka T (2011) The Best Things in Life: A Guide to What Really Matters. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurka T (1993) Perfectionism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan S (2014) An Introduction to Ill-Being. Oxford Stud Normative Ethics 4:261–288

  • Kagan S (1994) Me and My Life. Proc Aristot Soc 94:309–324

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kazez J (2007) The Weight of Things: Philosophy and the Good Life. Blackwell Publishing, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Lin E (2016) Monism and Pluralism. In: Fletcher G (ed) The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-Being. Routledge, London, pp 331–341

  • Moore A (2000) Objective Human Goods. In: Crisp R, Hooker B (eds) Well-Being and Morality: Essays in Honour of James Griffin. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 75–89

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy MC (2001) Natural Law and Practical Rationality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel T (1979) Mortal Questions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Nozick R (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum MC (2000) Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg DS (2008) The Structure and Content of the Good. In: Oderberg IDS, Chappell T (eds) Human Values: New Essays on Ethics and Natural Law. Palgrave Macmillan, Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire, pp 127–165

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (1984) Reasons and Persons. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Rice CM (2013) Defending the Objective List Theory of Well-Being. Ratio 26:196–211

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon T (1998) What We Owe to Each Other. Belknap Press of Harvard University, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christopher M. Rice.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rice, C.M. Objective List Theories and Ill-Being. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 22, 1073–1085 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-019-10035-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-019-10035-5

Keywords

Navigation