1 Introduction

Following Russell (1912,1913, 1918), philosophers like Moltmann (2003, 2013, Chap. 4), Jubien (2001), Boër (2002), and Newman (2002) analyse (1) as (2a), instead of analysing (1) as (2b).Footnote 1

(1):

John believes that Mary is French.

(2a):

R (John, \(\lambda x\) [x is French], Mary).

(2b):

R (John, that Mary is French).

Thus, for these philosophers, instead of relations holding between agents and truth-bearing entities (propositions), propositional attitude verbs, like ‘belief’, express relations holding between agents and the properties and objects our thoughts and speech acts are about. For example, in (Moltmann 2003), Moltmann treats propositional attitude verbs, like ‘belief’ as syncategorematic expressions which, if, in the simplest case, the that-clause has a propositional content consisting of an n-place relation and n arguments, will specify an (\(n+2\))-place relation \(R_{(bel, n+2)}\) as in (M) (Moltmann 2003, p. 94, pp. 96–97):

(M):

For an n-place relation \(R'\) and entities \(d_{1},\ldots , d_{n}\),

\([\![\)believes, \(\langle R', d_{1},\ldots , d_{n}\rangle ]\!] = \lambda x [R_{(bel, n+2)}(x, R', d_{1},\ldots , d_{n})]\).

The claim that propositional attitude verbs, like ‘belief’, express relations holding between agents and the properties and objects our thoughts and speech acts are about is also known as the Multiple Relation Theory.Footnote 2

There are various reasons why philosophers have advocated or still advocate the Multiple Relation Theory. For example, in (Moltmann 2003), Moltmann reintroduces the Multiple Relation Theory, among others, to explain that inferences like the inferences in (3) aren’t logically valid.

3a.:

John remembers that Mary is French.

John remembers the proposition that Mary is French.

3b.:

John wishes that Mary is French.

John wishes the proposition that Mary is French.

Since, according to the Relational Analysis, the premises in (3) are true if and only if John remembers/wishes the proposition that Mary is French, the Relational Analysis cannot explain this. According to Moltmann, this suggests that the premises in (3) have to be analysed as (2a), instead of analysing them as (2b). First of all, this would explain that the inferences in (3) aren’t logically valid. Moreover, it would also explain that, unlike their conclusion, the premises of (3a) and (3b) specify the content of the attitude in question. Moltmann calls this ‘the Objectivization Effect’: Unlike the that-clause in the premises of (3), the complement in the conclusions of (3) “specifies not the mere content of the attitude, but the object the attitude is about or directed toward” (Moltmann 2003, p. 87).

Against the Multiple Relation Theory, it has been objected that what is judged or believed must be capable of being true or false. Since a collection of things, like the collection of Mary and the property of being happy, is not capable of being true or false, it has been concluded that the relata of the belief relation cannot be the properties and objects our thoughts and speech acts are about (see, for example, Hanks 2007, p. 140). Moltmann (2003, pp. 105–106) responds to this objection that attitude verbs, like ‘belief’, express modes of predication. For example, according to Moltmann, believing that Mary is happy is predicating, in the belief mode, the property of being happy of Mary. Since here predication is understood as an intentional act aiming at truth, according to Moltmann, the primary bearers of truth are not the relata of the belief relation, but the concrete acts of believing.Footnote 3 In this way, an advocate of the Multiple Relation Theory could explain that beliefs are true or false without being committed to the claim that the objects of belief are truth-bearing entities.

In this paper, I won’t go into detail about the different arguments for and against the Multiple Relation Theory that have been discussed in the literature. Instead, I will discuss the Multiple Relation Theory primarily in connection with a problem known as Schiffer’s puzzle. Schiffer (2006) first presented the puzzle to argue against the so called direct-reference theory of belief reports advocated, among others, by Salmon (1986) and Braun (1998). I will argue that, unlike the direct-reference theory of belief reports, the Multiple Relation Theory does not provide a solution to Schiffer’s puzzle. In this connection, I will also discuss a slight modification of the Multiple Relation Theory according to which the ways the properties and objects our thoughts and speech acts are about are presented to us are part of the truth-conditions of sentences like (1). We will see that prima facie such a contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory provides a solution to Schiffer’s puzzle. However, concluding, I will argue with new Schiffer cases that, ultimately, also the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory cannot explain all instances of Schiffer’s puzzle. Together with the result that also the non-contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory, i.e. (M), does not provide a solution to Schiffer’s puzzle, this will undermine the Multiple Relation Theory in general.

The paper is structured as follows: In Sect. 2, I will argue that the Multiple Relation Theory is committed to what Schiffer calls ‘the special-case consequence’ and ‘Frege’s constraint’. Following this, in Sect. 3, I will argue with an example from Schiffer that together with the special-case consequence and Frege’s constraint the non-contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory, i.e. (M), leads to contradictions. This is Schiffer’s puzzle. In Sect. 4, I will argue that, unlike the direct-reference theory of belief reports, the non-contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory does not provide a solution to Schiffer’s puzzle. Following this (Sect. 5), I will discuss a contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory, and I will argue with new Schiffer cases that, ultimately, also a contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory cannot solve Schiffer’s puzzle.

2 The special-case consequence and Frege’s constraint

The starting point of Schiffer’s puzzle is a problem regarding de re belief which also arises within the Multiple Relation Theory. For example, both (4) and (5) can be true; e.g. if Ralph sincerely and reflectively utters both ‘Karol Wojtyła is Polish’ and ‘It is not the case that John Paul II. is Polish’.

  1. (4)

    Ralph believes that Karol Wojtyła is Polish.

  2. (5)

    Ralph disbelievesFootnote 4that John Paul II. is Polish.

Moreover, it seems that according to the Multiple Relation Theory de re belief is simply a special case of de dicto belief. For example, if (4) is true, then, according to (M), Ralph stands in the three-place belief relation \(R_{(bel, 3)}\) to the property of being Polish and Karol Wojtyła.Footnote 5 Since this seems to be tantamount to saying that Karol Wojtyła is believed by Ralph to be someone such that he is Polish, the Multiple Relation Theory seems to be committed to what Schiffer (2006, p. 362) calls ‘the special-case consequence’:

The Special-Case Consequence (S)::

Necessarily, if \(\alpha \) believes/disbelieves that \(\phi _{\beta }\),

then \(\beta \) is believed/disbelieved by \(\alpha \) to be (something/someone) such that \(\phi _{\beta /it}\).

Here \(\alpha \) is any singular term of English, \(\beta \) is any proper name or other directly referential term of English, \(\phi _{it}\) is any English open sentence in which the pronoun ‘it’ occurs as a free variable – alternatively ‘he’, ‘she’, ‘him’ or ‘her’ – and \(\phi _{\beta }\) is the same as \(\phi _{it}\) except for having occurrences of \(\beta \) wherever \(\phi _{it}\) has free occurrences of the relevant pronoun. If (4) and (5) are true, then, according to (S), so are (6) and (7).

  1. (6)

    Karol Wojtyła is believed by Ralph to be someone such that he is Polish.

  2. (7)

    John Paul II. is disbelieved by Ralph to be someone such that he is Polish.

Since John Paul II. = Karol Wojtyła, and since we can simply assume that Ralph is both a brilliant logician, i.e. that he is in principle in a position to notice and correct contradictory beliefs, and fully rational, i.e. that he would never let contradictory beliefs pass if he recognises them as such, this leads to the question how a brilliant logician like Ralph can rationally both believe and disbelieve an object o to be (something/someone) such that \(\phi _{it}\). I will call this ‘the problem of rationality regarding de re belief’.

The received solution to the problem of rationality regarding de re belief says that Wojtyła is presented to Ralph by two modes of presentation m and \(m'\) without him recognising that m and \(m'\) are modes of presentation of one and the same person. Since Ralph believes Wojtyła to be Polish under m and disbelieves Wojtyła to be Polish under \(m'\), the solution continues, Ralph cannot be convicted of irrationality. Schiffer calls this ‘Frege’s constraint’ (Schiffer 2006, p. 362):Footnote 6

(FC):

If an object o is rationally both believed and disbelieved by an agent k to be (something/someone) such that \(\phi _{it}\), then there are two modes of presentation m and \(m'\) such that

(a):

o is believed by k to be (something/someone) such that \(\phi _{it}\) under m,

(b):

o is disbelieved by k to be (something/someone) such that \(\phi _{it}\) under \(m'\), and

(c):

k does not recognise that m and \(m'\) are modes of presentation of one and the same object.

Taken in its obvious intent, Frege’s constraint appears to be a self-evident truth. If an agent k rationally believes o to be (something/someone) such that \(\phi _{it}\) and disbelieves \(o'\) to be (something/someone) such that \(\phi _{it}\), then, in so doing, k takes o and \(o'\) to be distinct. Insofar as k is rational, he/she thereby takes o and \(o'\) differently, even if, in fact, \(o=o'\). Thus, in addition to the special-case consequence, the Multiple Relation Theory also seems to be committed to Frege’s constraint.

Following Frege’s constraint, advocates of the Multiple Relation Theory have two options. First, they could claim that the modes of presentation implied by Frege’s constraint are part of the truth-conditions of sentences like (4) and (5) and (6) and (7) (respectively). In this case, advocates of the Multiple Relation Theory would have to reject (M), and, instead, hold something along the lines of (\(M'\)) (Moltmann 2003, p. 97).Footnote 7

(\(M'\)):

For an n-place relation \(R'\), entities \(d_{1},\ldots , d_{n}\) and (types of) modes of presentation \(T'\), \(T_{1},\ldots , T_{n}\),

\([\![\)believes/disbelieves, \(\langle \langle R', T'\rangle , \langle d_{1}, T_{1}\rangle ,\ldots , \langle d_{n}, T_{n}\rangle \rangle ]\!]\)

\(= \lambda x [R_{(bel/dis, n+2)}(x, \langle R', T'\rangle , \langle d_{1}, T_{1}\rangle ,\ldots , \langle d_{n}, T_{n}\rangle )].\)Footnote 8

The second option is to stick with (M), and, thus, to claim that the modes of presentation implied by Frege’s constraint are not part of the truth-conditions of sentences like (4) and (5) and (6) and (7) (respectively). Nevertheless, just like (\(M'\)), (M) is consistent with Frege’s constraint. For example, an advocate of (M) could claim that \(R_{(bel, n+2)}\) is the existential generalization of a relation \(R_{(bel, n+2)}'\) involving the modes of presentation implied by Frege’s constraint; i.e. that for all x: \(R_{(bel, n+2)}(x, R', d_{1},\ldots , d_{n})\) if and only if there are (types of) modes of presentation \(T'\), \(T_{1},\ldots , T_{n}\) such that \(R_{(bel, n+2)}'(x, \langle R', T'\rangle , \langle d_{1}, T_{1}\rangle ,\ldots , \langle d_{n}, T_{n}\rangle )\).Footnote 9 In this way, (M) would provide a solution to the problem of rationality regarding de re belief via Frege’s constraint without being committed to the claim that the modes of presentation implied by Frege’s constraint are part of the truth-conditions of sentences like (4) and (5) and (6) and (7) (respectively).

Although both (M) and (\(M'\)) can explain how (4) and (5) can be true of a brilliant and fully rational logician like Ralph, unlike (M), (\(M'\)) could also explain that there can be circumstances in which (4) is true and (8) is false.

  1. (4)

    Ralph believes that Karol Wojtyła is Polish.

  2. (8)

    Ralph believes that John Paul II. is Polish.

For example, if Ralph is disposed to sincerely and reflectively utter ‘Karol Wojtyła is Polish’ without being disposed to sincerely and reflectively utter ‘John Paul II. is Polish’, we have strong intuitions that (4) is true and (8) is false. However, since, according to (M), both (4) and (8) have the logical form in (9), (M) could not explain this.

  1. (9)

    \(R_{(bel, 3)}\) (Ralph, \(\lambda x\) [x is Polish], Karol Wojtyła).

This is also known as Frege’s puzzle.

In (Moltmann 2003, p. 97), Moltmann solves Frege’s puzzle by replacing (M) with (\(M'\)). For example, according to (\(M'\)), (4) has to be analysed as (10), and (8) has to be analysed as (11), where \(T_{KW}\) and \(T_{KW}'\) are two distinct (contextually determined) (types of) modes of presentation of Karol Wojtyła, and \(T_{Pol}\) is a (contextually determined) (type of) mode of presentation of the property of being Polish.

  1. (10)

    \(R_{(bel, 3)}\) (Ralph, \(\langle \lambda x\) [x is Polish], \(T_{Pol}\rangle , \langle \)Karol Wojtyła, \(T_{KW}\rangle \)).

  2. (11)

    \(R_{(bel, 3)}\) (Ralph, \(\langle \lambda x\) [x is Polish], \(T_{Pol}\rangle , \langle \)Karol Wojtyła, \(T_{KW}'\rangle \)).

Since there can be circumstances in which (10) is true and (11) is false, in this way, an advocate of the Multiple Relation Theory could explain how there can be circumstances in which (4) is true and (8) is false. Such a solution to Frege’s puzzle is also called a ‘contextualist solution to Frege’s puzzle’. Therefore, I will call (\(M'\)) ‘the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory’.Footnote 10

The alternative to a contextualist solution to Frege’s puzzle is a naive solution to Frege’s puzzle. According to a naive solution to Frege’s puzzle, (4) is true if and only if (8) is true; i.e. according to a naive solution to Frege’s puzzle, our intuitions regarding the truth-values of sentences like (4) and (8) can be misleading (see, for example, Salmon 1986; Braun 1998). Following this, a naive solution to Frege’s puzzle has to provide an explanation of how our intuitions regarding the truth-values of sentences like (4) and (8) can be misleading. Here an advocate of (M) could build on Salmon’s (1986) or Braun’s (1998) naive solution to Frege’s puzzle in connection with the direct-reference theory of belief reports. Therefore, I will call (M) also ‘the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory’.

The discussion between the naive and the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory can be compared with the discussion between the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports advocated by Salmon (1986) and Braun (1998) and the contextualist version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports advocated by Crimmins and Perry (1989) and Crimmins (1992). A contextualist theory has the advantage that it can take our intuitions regarding the truth-values of sentences like (4) and (8) seriously, whereas a naive theory has the advantage that it does not have to introduce modes of presentation as unarticulated constituents; i.e. contents for which no word or morpheme in the sentence stands for. Therefore, just like in connection with the direct-reference theory of belief reports, prima facie, also in connection with the Multiple Relation Theory both a naive and a contextualist version of the theory seem to be serious options. However, in the next section, I will argue with an example from Schiffer that together with the special-case consequence and Frege’s constraint the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory leads to contradictions. Since, as we have seen above, the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory seems to be committed to both the special-case consequence and Frege’s constraint, this will undermine the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory. We will see that, prima facie, the same problem does not arise in connection with the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory.

3 Schiffer’s puzzle

Take the above example of Ralph. From Ralph’s sincere and reflective utterance of ‘Karol Wojtyła is Polish’ and ‘It is not the case that John Paul II. is Polish’ we infer that both (4) and (5) are true. This means that we presuppose the following disquotational principles connecting sincere assertion and belief, where ‘p’ can be replaced, inside and outside quotation marks, by any standard English sentence lacking indexical or pronominal devices or ambiguities (Kripke 1979, pp. 248–249)Footnote 11:

(DP):

If a normal English speaker sincerely and reflectively utters ‘p’, then he/she believes that p.

(\(DP'\)):

If a normal English speaker sincerely and reflectively utters ‘It is not the case that p’, then he/she disbelieves that p.Footnote 12

Analogous principles can be formulated for French, German etc.

Taken in their obvious intent, also (DP) and (\(DP'\)) seem to be self-evident truths. In particular, (DP) and (\(DP'\)) seem to be true of belief ascriptions of the form ‘A believes that S’. For example, if a normal English speaker sincerely and reflectively utters ‘Ralph believes that snow is white’, we usually infer that the speaker believes that Ralph believes that snow is white. Similarly, if a normal English speaker sincerely and reflectively utters ‘It is not the case that Ralph believes that snow is white’, we usually infer that the speaker disbelieves that Ralph believes that snow is white.Footnote 13

Now, Schiffer (2006, p. 363) notes that in the example of Ralph even a rational, normal English speaker who knows that ‘Karol Wojtyła = John Paul II.’ is true could sincerely and reflectively utter both (4) and (12); e.g. if the speaker has Fregean intuitions regarding the truth-values of sentences like (4) and (12).

(4):

Ralph believes that Karol Wojtyła is Polish.

(12):

It is not the case that Ralph believes that John Paul II. is Polish.

Assume that Peter is such a speaker. Together with (DP) and (\(DP'\)), it would follow that both (13) and (14) are true.

(13):

Peter believes that Ralph believes that Karol Wojtyła is Polish.

(14):

Peter disbelieves that Ralph believes that John Paul II. is Polish.

If (13) and (14) are true, then, according to (S), so are (15) and (16).

(15):

Karol Wojtyła is believed by Peter to be someone such that Ralph believes that he is Polish.

(16):

John Paul II. is disbelieved by Peter to be someone such that Ralph believes that he is Polish.

According to (M), (15) then has the logical form in (17), and (16) has the logical form in (18), where BEL stands for the three-place predicate ‘x is believed by y to be someone/something such that \(\phi _{it}\)’ and DIS stands for the three-place predicate ‘x is disbelieved by y to be someone/something such that \(\phi _{it}\)’:Footnote 14

(17):

BEL (Karol Wojtyła, Peter, \(\lambda z [R_{(bel, 3)}\)(Ralph, \(\lambda x [x\) is Polish], z)]).

(18):

DIS (Karol Wojtyła, Peter, \(\lambda z [R_{(bel, 3)}\)(Ralph, \(\lambda x [x\) is Polish], z)]).

From this, in turn, it would follow together with Frege’s constraint that Karol Wojtyła is presented to Peter by two modes of presentation without him recognising that these are modes of presentation of one and the same person. However, since Peter believes ‘Karol Wojtyła = John Paul II.’ to be true, we can simply assume that Wojtyła is not presented to Peter by two modes of presentation without him recognising that these are modes of presentation of one and the same person. This is Schiffer’s puzzle.

Schiffer’s puzzle shows that together with the special-case consequence the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory, i.e. (M), leads to instances of the problem of rationality regarding de re belief that violate Frege’s constraint. Together with the claim that the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory is committed to both the special-case consequence and Frege’s constraint, this would refute the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory.

Prima facie, the same problem does not arise in connection with the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory. Even if Peter does not have two modes of presentation of Karol Wojtyła, he could still attribute two such modes of presentation to Ralph. In this case, according to (\(M'\)), (15) would have the logical form in (19), and (16) would have the logical form in (20), where \(T_{KW}\) and \(T_{KW}'\) are the modes of presentation of Karol Wojtyła that Peter attributes to Ralph.

(19):

BEL (Karol Wojtyła, Peter, \(\lambda z [R_{(bel, 3)}\)(Ralph, \(\langle \lambda x [x\) is Polish], \(T_{Pol}\rangle , \langle z, T_{KW}\rangle \))]).

(20):

DIS (Karol Wojtyła, Peter, \(\lambda z [R_{(bel, 3)}\)(Ralph, \(\langle \lambda x [x\) is Polish], \(T_{Pol}\rangle , \langle z, T_{KW}'\rangle \))]).

Now, according to (19) and (20), Karol Wojtyła is not both believed and disbelieved by Peter to be someone Ralph believes to be Polish, but rather he is believed by Peter to be someone Ralph believes under \(T_{KW}\) to be Polish, and disbelieved by Peter to be someone Ralph believes under \(T_{KW}'\) to be Polish. Since from this it does not follow together with Frege’s constraint that Karol Wojtyła is presented to Peter by two modes of presentation without him recognising that these are modes of presentation of one and the same person, prima facie, the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory provides a solution to Schiffer’s puzzle.

In Sect. 5, I will discuss such a contextualist solution to Schiffer’s puzzle in more detail. But first I will briefly discuss the possibility to reject the special-case consequence or Frege’s constraint within the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory. For example, in (Salmon 2006), Salmon replies to Schiffer’s objection that the direct-reference theory of belief reports is not committed to (S), but to counter-instances of (S). Therefore, next, I will briefly present Schiffer’s puzzle in connection with the direct-reference theory of belief reports. Following this, I will argue that, unlike the direct-reference theory of belief reports, the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory cannot solve Schiffer’s puzzle by rejecting the special-case consequence or Frege’s constraint.

4 Rejecting the special-case consequence or Frege’s constraint

As said above, Schiffer first presented his puzzle as an objection to the so called direct-reference theory of belief reports. For example, following the work of Marcus (1961), Donnellan (1970), Perry (1977), Kripke (1980) and Kaplan (1989), so called Neo-Russellians, like Salmon (1986) and Braun (1998), hold that:

(\(NR_{1}\)):

The propositions we say and believe are Russellian propositions; i.e. structured propositions whose basic components are the objects and properties our thoughts and speech acts are about.

(\(NR_{2}\)):

Names and other singular terms (pronouns, simple demonstratives, indexicals) function as directly referential terms; i.e. the semantic content of ‘n is F’ in a context c is the singular proposition \(\langle o, \varPhi \rangle \), where o is the referent of the name n in c and \(\varPhi \) is the property expressed by the predicate F in c.

This is also known as the direct-reference theory.Footnote 15 Moreover, Salmon and Braun advocate the following theory of belief reports:

(\(NR_{3}\)):

A sentence of the form ‘n believes/disbelieves that S’ is true in a context c iff the referent of the name n in c believes/disbelieves the proposition expressed by the sentence S in c.Footnote 16

Since the theory consisting of (\(NR_{1}\)), (\(NR_{2}\)), and (\(NR_{3}\)) is committed to a naive solution to Frege’s puzzle according to which our intuitions regarding the truth-values of sentences like (4) and (8) can be misleading, it is sometimes referred to as ‘the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports’.Footnote 17

In (Schiffer 2006), Schiffer argues that the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports is committed to both the special-case consequence and Frege’s constraint. For example, according to the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports, to believe of an object x, de re, that it is F simply seems to be to believe de dicto the singular proposition about x that it is F. Therefore, according to Schiffer, also within the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports the inferences from (13) and (14) to (15) and (16) are valid. Moreover, according to the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports, (15) has the logical form in (21), and (16) has the logical form in (22), where B stands for the two-place belief relation holding between agents and Russellian propositions.

(21):

BEL (Karol Wojtyła, Peter, \(\lambda z [B\)(Ralph, that z is Polish)]).

(22):

DIS (Karol Wojtyła, Peter, \(\lambda z [B\)(Ralph, that z is Polish)]).

Since from this it would follow together with Frege’s constraint that Karol Wojtyła is presented to Peter by two modes of presentation without him recognising that these are modes of presentation of one and the same person, we see that together with the special-case consequence also the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports leads to instances of the problem of rationality regarding de re belief that violate Frege’s constraint. Thus, if the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports were committed to both the special-case consequence and Frege’s constraint, this would refute the naive version of the direct reference theory of belief reports.Footnote 18

In (Salmon 2006, pp. 271–272), Salmon replies to Schiffer’s objection that the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports is not committed to (S), but to counter-instances of (S). Braun (2006, p. 376) agrees with Salmon on this point. As Salmon (2006, pp. 271–272) rightly points out, within the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports, one example of a counter-instance of (S) is provided by Schiffer’s puzzle itself. If (13) and (14) are true, then, according to the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports, Peter both believes and disbelieves the singular proposition \(\langle \langle \)Ralph, \(\langle \)Karol Wojtyła, being Polish\(\rangle \rangle \), believing\(\rangle \). However, Peter does not thereby both believe and disbelieve the singular proposition \(\langle \)Karol Wojtyła, being (someone) such that Ralph believes that he is Polish\(\rangle \). For example, if Peter believes ‘Karol Wojtyła = John Paul II.’ to be true, then, as a rational, normal English speaker, he is not disposed to sincerely and reflectively utter both (25) and (26).

(25):

Karol Wojtyła is (someone) such that Ralph believes that he is Polish.

(26):

It is not the case that John Paul II. is (someone) such that Ralph believes that he is Polish.

Since, according to the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports, (15) is true if and only if Peter believes the singular proposition \(\langle \)Karol Wojtyła, being (someone) such that Ralph believes that he is Polish\(\rangle \), and (16) is true if and only if Peter disbelieves \(\langle \)Karol Wojtyła, being (someone) such that Ralph believes that he is Polish\(\rangle \), it follows that although, in the above example, both (13) and (14) are true, according to the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports, (15) or (16) is not.

This leads to the question whether a similar solution to Schiffer’s puzzle is also available within the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory. I will argue that it is not. According to (M), both the propositional content of (4) and the propositional content of (8) consist of the three-place belief relation \(R_{(bel, 3)}\), Ralph, the property of being Polish, and Karol Wojtyła. From this, in turn, it follows within the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory that (13) has the logical form in (27), and that (14) has the logical form in (28).

(27):

\(R_{(bel, 5)}\) (Peter, \(\lambda x\lambda y\lambda z [R_{(bel, 3)}(x, y, z)]\), Ralph, \(\lambda x\) [x is Polish], Karol Wojtyła).

(28):

\(R_{(dis, 5)}\) (Peter, \(\lambda x\lambda y\lambda z [R_{(bel, 3)}(x, y, z)]\), Ralph, \(\lambda x\) [x is Polish], Karol Wojtyła).

Since this seems to be tantamount to saying that Karol Wojtyła is both believed and disbelieved by Peter to be believed by Ralph to be Polish, it is very likely that within the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory Schiffer’s puzzle does not provide a counter-instance of the special-case consequence. This suggests that, unlike the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports, the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory leads to instances of the problem of rationality regarding de re belief that violate Frege’s constraint.

If the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory leads to instances of the problem of rationality regarding de re belief that violate Frege’s constraint, then we have to reject the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory or Frege’s constraint. In (Schiffer 2006, pp. 364–365), Schiffer notes that, prima facie, an advocate of the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports could solve his puzzle by rejecting Frege’s constraint. For example, in order to explain that a brilliant logician like Ralph can rationally both believe and disbelieve the singular proposition \(\langle \)Karol Wojtyła, being Polish\(\rangle \), advocates of the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports already accept a version of Frege’s constraint for propositional modes of presentation; i.e. Salmon’s constraint (see, for example, Salmon 1986).

(SC):

If a proposition p is rationally both believed and disbelieved by an agent k, then there are modes of presentation m and \(m'\) such that

(a):

p is believed by k under m,

(b):

p is disbelieved by k under \(m'\), and

(c):

k does not take m and \(m'\) to be modes of presentation of one and the same proposition.

Following this, Schiffer notes that an advocate of the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports could respond to his objection that although Karol Wojtyła is not presented to Peter by two modes of presentation without him recognising that these are modes of presentation of one and the same person, the singular proposition \(\langle \langle \)Ralph, \(\langle \)Karol Wojtyła, being Polish\(\rangle \rangle \), believing\(\rangle \) is nevertheless presented to him by two modes of presentation without him recognising that these are modes of presentation of one and the same proposition. Since Peter believes the proposition under one mode of presentation and disbelieves it under the other, the solution goes, Peter cannot be convicted of irrationality. However, Schiffer (2006, p. 365) also notes that it is very unclear how to construe the propositional modes of presentation implied by Salmon’s constraint such that Salmon’s constraint does not commit the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports to Frege’s constraint. Moreover, such a solution to Schiffer’s puzzle is not even available within the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory. According to the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory, the belief relation holding between agents, properties/relations, and objects is not reducible to a belief relation holding between agents and Russellian propositions. Therefore, an advocate of the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory cannot simply reject Frege’s constraint, and, instead, accept a version of Frege’s constraint for propositional modes of presentation.

We see that it is very likely that within the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory the solution to Schiffer’s puzzle can neither be to reject the special-case consequence nor to reject Frege’s constraint. In other words, the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory has to provide an explanation of how both (27) and (28) can be true, although Peter is both a brilliant logician and fully rational. Since neither \(R_{(bel, 3)}\), nor Ralph, nor the property of being Polish, nor Karol Wojtyła is presented to Peter by two modes of presentation without him recognising that these are modes of presentation of one and the same object/property/relation, it is very unclear whether the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory can explain this. An advocate of the Multiple Relation could respond that this only shows that we have to reject the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory, and, instead, accept the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory. However, next, I will argue with new Schiffer cases that even the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory leads to instances of the problem of rationality regarding de re belief that violate Frege’s constraint. This will undermine the Multiple Relation Theory in general.

5 Schiffer’s puzzle again

According to the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory, the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) are simply the modes of presentation implied by Frege’s constraint. Otherwise, the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory could not explain that both (4) and (5) can be true of a rational logician like Ralph.

(4):

Ralph believes that Karol Wojtyła is Polish.

(5):

Ralph disbelieves that John Paul II. is Polish.

According to (\(M'\)), (4) has the logical form in (10), and (5) has the logical form in (29), where \(T_{KW}\) and \(T_{KW}'\) are two distinct (contextually determined) (types of) modes of presentation of Karol Wojtyła.

(10):

\(R_{(bel, 3)}\) (Ralph, \(\langle \lambda x\) [x is Polish], \(T_{Pol}\rangle , \langle \)Karol Wojtyła, \(T_{KW}\rangle \)).

(29):

\(R_{(dis, 3)}\) (Ralph, \(\langle \lambda x\) [x is Polish], \(T_{Pol}\rangle , \langle \)Karol Wojtyła, \(T_{KW}'\rangle \)).

Now, in order to explain that both (10) and (29) can be true of a rational logician like Ralph, an advocate of the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory is committed to the claim that Ralph does not recognise that \(T_{KW}\) and \(T_{KW}'\) are modes of presentation of one and the same person. Since this is tantamount to saying that the modes of presentation implied by (10) and (29) play the role defined by Frege’s constraint, it follows that according to the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) are simply the modes of presentation implied by Frege’s constraint.

Both (\(M'\)) and Frege’s constraint leave open what modes of presentation are. In this section, I will discuss the three main conceptions of the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) (and Frege’s constraint), and I will argue that, ultimately, on all three conceptions (\(M'\)) leads to instances of the problem of rationality that violate Frege’s constraint. This will suggest that also the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory does not provide a solution to Schiffer’s puzzle.

A first construal of the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) and Frege’s constraint could be that the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) and Frege’s constraint are expressions of a public language. According to such a construal of the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) and Frege’s constraint, (4) has to be analysed as (30), and (5) has to be analysed as (31), where the two public language names ‘Karol Wojtyła’ and ‘John Paul II.’ are the ways Karol Wojtyła is presented to Ralph.

(30):

\(R_{(bel, 3)}\) (Ralph, \(\langle \lambda x\) [x is Polish], ‘x is Polish’\(\rangle , \langle \)Karol Wojtyła, ‘Karol Wojtyła’\(\rangle \)).

(31):

\(R_{(dis, 3)}\) (Ralph, \(\langle \lambda x\) [x is Polish], ‘x is Polish’\(\rangle , \langle \)Karol Wojtyła, ‘John Paul II.’\(\rangle \)).

Since, in the above example, Ralph does not recognise that ‘Karol Wojtyła’ and ‘John Paul II.’ are names of one and the same person, prima facie, expressions of a public language seem to be good candidates for the role defined by Frege’s constraint. However, in connection with Kripke’s Paderewski example (Kripke 1979, pp. 265–266), such a conception of the modes of presentation implied by Frege’s constraint reaches its limits; i.e. it leads to an instance of the problem of rationality regarding de re belief that violates Frege’s constraint.

In Kripke’s Paderewski example, Kripke’s Peter gets introduced twice to one and the same name ‘Paderewski’ without him recognising it. Therefore, even as a brilliant and fully rational logician Peter could sincerely and reflectively utter both (32) and (33).

(32):

Paderewski has musical talent.

(33):

It is not the case that Paderewski has musical talent.

However, according to the public language conception of the modes of presentation implied by Frege’s constraint, there would be a mode of presentation m such that Paderewski is both believed and disbelieved by Peter to have musical talent under m; i.e. the public language name ‘Paderewski’. Thus, on the public language conception of the modes of presentation implied by Frege’s constraint, Kripke’s example would lead to an instance of the problem of rationality that violates Frege’s constraint.

Following Kripke’s Paderewski example, an advocate of the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory could claim that, instead of expressions of a public language, the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) and Frege’s constraint are bundles of properties or files of information.Footnote 19 For example, it is very likely that in Kripke’s example Peter has two distinct files of information of Paderewski; one file containing, among others, the information being a politician, and one file containing, among others, the information being a musician. Following this, an advocate of the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory could claim that since Paderewski is believed by Peter to have musical talent under one file, and disbelieved by Peter to have musical talent under the other file, without him recognising that these are files of one and the same person, Peter cannot be convicted of irrationality. However, even on the files of information conception of the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory leads to instances of the problem of rationality that violate Frege’s constraint.

Assume that although Harry has two names for Cicero in his public language, he has only one file of information of Cicero; i.e. the file containing the information being a Roman orator, being named ‘Cicero’, and being named ‘Tully’.Footnote 20 Thus, although Harry has two names for Cicero, he associates one and the same information with ‘Cicero’ and ‘Tully’. Nevertheless, Harry could accept ‘Cicero was a Roman’ without being disposed to accept ‘Tully was a Roman’; i.e. if Harry is irrational or not very reflective. Moreover, following this, a rational, normal English speaker like Sally could be disposed to sincerely and reflectively utter (34) and (35) even if she knows both that ‘Cicero = Tully’ is true and that Harry associates one and the same file of information with ‘Cicero’ and ‘Tully’; e.g. if Sally has strong sententialist intuitions.Footnote 21

(34):

Harry believes that Cicero was a Roman.

(35):

Harry does not believe that Tully was a Roman.

Together with (DP) and (\(DP'\)), it would follow that both (36) and (37) are true.

(36):

Sally believes that Harry believes that Cicero was a Roman.

(37):

Sally disbelieves that Harry believes that Tully was a Roman.

If (36) and (37) are true, then, according to the special-case consequence, so are (38) and (39).

(38):

Cicero is believed by Sally to be someone such that Harry believes that he was a Roman.

(39):

Tully is disbelieved by Sally to be someone such that Harry believes that he was a Roman.

However, since Sally knows that Harry associates one and the same file of information with ‘Cicero’ and ‘Tully’, according to the file of information conception of the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)), (38) has the logical form in (40), and (39) has the logical form in (41), where \(F_{Cicero}\) is the Cicero file that Sally attributes to Harry.Footnote 22

(40):

BEL (Cicero, Sally, \(\lambda z [R_{(bel, 3)}\)(Harry, \(\langle \lambda x [x\) was a Roman], \(T_{Rom}\rangle , \langle z, F_{Cicero}\rangle \))]).

(41):

DIS (Cicero, Sally, \(\lambda z [R_{(bel, 3)}\)(Harry, \(\langle \lambda x [x\) was a Roman], \(T_{Rom}\rangle , \langle z, F_{Cicero}\rangle \))]).

From this, in turn, it would follow together with Frege’s constraint that Cicero is presented to Sally by two modes of presentation without her recognising that these are modes of presentation of one and the same person.Footnote 23 However, since Sally knows that ‘Cicero = Tully’ is true, we can simply assume that Cicero is not presented to Sally by two modes of presentation without her recognising that these are modes of presentation of one and the same person. It follows that on the files of information conception of the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory leads to instances of the problem of rationality regarding de re belief that violate Frege’s constraint.

An advocate of the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory could respond that this only shows that in the above example the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) are expressions of a public language; i.e. that (38) has to be analysed as (42), and that (39) has to be analysed as (43), where the two names ‘Cicero’ and ‘Tully’ play the role of the modes of presentation that Sally attributes tos Harry.

(42):

BEL (Cicero, Sally, \(\lambda z [R_{(bel, 3)}\)(Harry, \(\langle \lambda x [x\) was a Roman], \(T_{Rom}\rangle , \langle z\), ‘Cicero’\(\rangle \))]).

(43):

DIS (Cicero, Sally, \(\lambda z [R_{(bel, 3)}\)(Harry, \(\langle \lambda x [x\) was a Roman], \(T_{Rom}\rangle , \langle z\), ‘Tully’\(\rangle \))]).

However, we have seen that such a public language conception of the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) does not provide a solution to Kripke’s Paderewski example. Therefore, such a solution to the Cicero/Tully example would commit an advocate of (\(M'\)) to a mixed view regarding the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)); i.e. that the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) are sometimes files of information, like in Kripke’s Paderewski example, and sometimes expressions of a public language, like in the Cicero/Tully example, however, as we have seen above, according to the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory, the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) are simply the modes of presentation implied by Frege’s constraint. Since it is very unlikely that the functional role defined by Frege’s constraint is sometimes played by public language expressions, and sometimes played by files of information, also a mixed view of the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) is not very plausible. This suggests that within the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory the solution to the Cicero/Tully example cannot simply be to analyse (38) as (42) and (39) as (43).

In light of this, an advocate of the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory could claim that, instead of public language expressions or files of information, the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) are expressions of a language of thought LOT. For example, an advocate of the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory could claim that although Kripke’s Peter does not have two names for Paderewski in his public language, he has two names for Paderewski in his language of thought. Prima facie, the same could be said of Harry; i.e. that although Harry has only one file of information of Cicero, just like he has two names for Cicero in his public language, he also has two names for Cicero in his language of thought. However, as Braun (1998, fn 39) points out, in connection with Kripke’s Paderewski example such a solution presupposes that the language of thought is not the public language; i.e. English. Otherwise, Peter would also have only one name for Paderewski in his language of thought. But then from the fact that Harry has two names for Cicero in his public language it does not automatically follow that he also has two names for Cicero in his language of thought. On the contrary, if Harry’s language of thought is not English, then, since Harry never distinguished two mental files of Cicero, it is very likely that he also never distinguished two mental names of Cicero. This suggests that in connection with the Harry/Sally example the LOT conception of the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) leads to a similar problem as the file of information conception of the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)).

We see that on the three main conceptions of the modes of presentation implied by (\(M'\)) and Frege’s constraint also the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory leads to instances of the problem of rationality regarding de re belief that violate Frege’s constraint. This suggests that, just like the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory, ultimately, also the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory does not provide a solution to Schiffer’s puzzle. This undermines the Multiple Relation Theory in general.

6 Conclusions

Unlike the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports, the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory, i.e. (M), seems to be committed to both the special-case consequence and Frege’s constraint. Since, together with the special-case consequence and Frege’s constraint, the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory leads to contradictions, this undermines the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory. This was Schiffer’s puzzle. Moreover, even if the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory is not committed to both the special-case consequence and Frege’s constraint, it has to provide an explanation of how both (27) and (28) can be true, although Peter is both a brilliant logician and fully rational. Since neither \(R_{(bel, 3)}\), nor Ralph, nor the property of being Polish, nor Karol Wojtyła is presented to Peter by two modes of presentation without him recognising that these are modes of presentation of one and the same object/property/relation, it is very unclear how the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory could explain this.

In order to solve Schiffer’s puzzle, an advocate of the Multiple Relation Theory could reject the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory, and, instead, accept the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation Theory; i.e. (\(M'\)). However, as we have seen in Sect. 5, just like the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory, also the contextualist version of the Multiple Relation theory leads to instances of the problem of rationality regarding de re belief that violate Frege’s constraint. Therefore, Schiffer’s puzzle not only undermines the naive version of the Multiple Relation Theory, but the Multiple Relation Theory in general.

For advocates of the Multiple Relation Theory, a possible way out of the problem is to claim with Jubien (2001) that the relata of the belief relation are always properties and relations; i.e. that there is nothing like de re belief, and, therefore, that there is nothing like the problem of rationality regarding de re belief or Schiffer’s puzzle. However, most advocates of the Multiple Relation Theory hold that, in addition to properties and relations, also individuals can be the relata of the belief relation.

Another possibility would be to distinguish between the assertoric content of a sentence (what we say with an utterance of the sentence) and its semantic content (the meaning of the sentence). Following this, an advocate of the Multiple Relation Theory could claim that (M) and (\(M'\)) are theories of assertoric content, and not theories of semantic content. Therefore, the solution to Schiffer’s puzzle goes, although a speaker who accepts (4) and (12) both believes and disbelieves one and the same assertoric objects, he cannot be convicted of irrationality, since the sentences he thereby uses do not have the same semantic content. However, in order to offer a complete solution to Schiffer’s puzzle, such a theory would have to say what the semantic content of sentences like (4) and (8) is, and how sentences like (4) and (8) can have different semantic contents.

Another possible way out of Schiffer’s puzzle would be to claim with Neo-Russellians, like Salmon (1986, 2006) and Braun (1998, 2006), that a sentence like (1) does not have the logical form in (2a), but rather the logical form in (2b). Following this, one could argue with Salmon that Schiffer’s puzzle provides a counter-instance of (S), and, therefore, does not lead to instances of the problem of rationality regarding de re belief that violate Frege’s constraint. However, in (Rinner 2020), I argue that although the naive version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports advocated by Salmon and Braun is not committed to (S), it nevertheless leads to instances of the problem of rationality regarding de re belief that violate Frege’s constraint. Since the same problem does not arise for the contextualist version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports advocated, among others, by Crimmins and Perry (1989) and Crimmins (1992), unlike the naive version, the contextualist version of the direct-reference theory of belief reports would still provide a solution to Schiffer’s puzzle.