In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

  • Introduction
  • Robert M. Veatch (bio)

The Kennedy Institute of Ethics regularly sponsors intensive bioethics courses for physicians, nurses, and other health care professionals. While the basic course, held in June of each year, provides a general introduction to bioethics, advanced courses, which are often held in March, focus on more specific topics such as death and dying, justice and the allocation of resources, or theories and methods in bioethics. This year the advanced course addressed one of the most sensitive and complex bioethical issues of our day: managed care. This issue of the Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal includes revised versions of many of the papers from that meeting.

As defined by one of the papers in this issue, managed care involves a system of health care delivery that manages resources, quality, and access associated with the delivery of health care. The key element of managed care is that, for the first time, managers—often from outside the health care professions—are intentionally controlling resources, and therefore controlling health care professional decisions that use those resources. The objective is not merely to eliminate utterly useless interventions—no one could plausibly object to that. Rather the target is also the elimination of inefficient and wasteful resource consumption. Increasingly, we recognize that many diagnostic tests and treatments offer, at best, a very marginal chance of doing the patient good. Some of these come at considerable cost. From the point of view of the rational organization of resources, no rational person would insist on receiving every last procedure that offers only a tiny chance to do a small amount of good at great cost. Managed care is designed to bring to consciousness and rationalize the decisions about which of these marginal, expensive benefits are worth pursuing.

The problem is that any effort to eliminate any of the these expensive marginal services flies directly in the face of the Hippocratic ethic. Physicians and other clinicians traditionally are trained to believe that it is their moral duty to do what is best for the patient. Only now are we realizing that, taken literally, no rational person would want literally the best possible care, assuming that such care would include thousands of long-shot, expensive efforts to get the most modest of benefits at great cost. In a world of finite resources, rational people would certainly want very good medical care; they would want reasonable care. But they would also want some criteria of efficiency and fairness applied. The Hippocratic tradition has never addressed the problem of the difference between the best care and care that is of very high quality, but is chosen with an awareness that the best in medicine will necessarily come at the price of potentially serious [End Page vii] deprivation in other spheres of life. The ethics of managed care is fundamentally an exploration of how health care professionals can reconcile their traditional, if short-sighted and naive, commitment to doing what is best for their patients with increasing realism about the absurdity of pursuing every last possible increment of benefit.

To the clinical health care professional, the issue raised most poignantly by managed care is whether the various health professions can still be practiced with integrity in a setting in which outsiders are charged with the rationalization and systematization of limits placed on excessive use of marginally beneficial resources. Edmund D. Pellegrino, a clinician and former Director of the Kennedy Institute, sets the tone for the course and for this issue of the Journal by making an appeal for the retention of the highest ethical standards of integrity for clinicians practicing in a managed care setting. He is unwilling to let standards be lowered in the process of systematizing the rational use of health care resources. The remaining papers in this issue respond to those pressures to change the nature of the clinical lay-professional relationship. Some of these presentations originated as panels designed to bring out varying points of view. The published form of the presentations, like the original oral remarks, are of different lengths. All have been edited by the presenters, some taking on the form of more finished papers, others still reflecting the less formal conversation of...

Share