Skip to main content
Log in

The indexical character of epistemic modality

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Linguistics and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We assume a central thesis about modal auxiliaries due to Angelika Kratzer, the modal base presupposition: natural language expressions that contain a modal component in their meaning, including all English modal auxiliaries and epistemic modal auxiliaries (EMA)s in particular, presuppose a modal base, a function that draws from context a relevant set of propositions which contribute to a premise-semantics for the modal. Accepting this thesis for EMAs leaves open (at least) the following two questions about the meaning of English EMAs like must and might: (i) What constraints, if any, are there on the character of the premise set for an EMA? And (ii) what is the nature of the relationship between premises and conclusion that is required for truth of the EMA statement? I argue for at least a partial answer to (i), with a hypothesis about constraints on the modal base for an EMA: EMAs, unlike some other types of modals, are indexical: They are anchored to an agent-in-a-situation whose doxastic state is currently under discussion in the context of utterance. Realized in a Kratzerian semantics, indexicality sheds new light on a number of outstanding puzzles, including the widely observed variability of anchoring of EMAs, the ways in which EMAs differ from so-called root modals, Yalcin’s (Mind 116:983–1026, 2007) puzzle (a version of Moore’s paradox for epistemic modals embedded under attitudes), how to explain the apparent weakness of necessity EMAs, and problems with second order belief and disagreement.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Kratzer (2012) for an overview of the development of this theory. Cf. also Veltmann’s (1985) premise semantics.

  2. See the mereology of situations in Kratzer (1989), where situations are world-bound.

  3. I adopt Stalnaker’s (2008) constraints on Dox. He modifies Lewis’ (1979) characterization of this relation over centered worlds in ways that do not bear on the current analysis.

  4. I use ‘#’ to indicate that the example (or the marked part of it) is infelicitous in the context in which it is uttered, implicating that the expression is grammatical and might be felicitous in another context.

  5. For locatives, see Fillmore (1975), Hockett (1990) and Oshima’s (2006a, 2006b) “deictic perspective shift”. For shifted indexicals, Deal (2020) summarizes a large body of literature on many languages.

  6. Doron (1991), Sharvit (2008) and Eckardt (2015).

  7. Cipria and Roberts (2000) argue that events are a type of situation. I use event dRefs here because Partee (1984) offers independent motivation for tracking them across discourse and relates them to Reference Time.

  8. Where ⊕ is the join operator of Link (1983).

  9. There is a phenomenon much like FID, occurring in the complements of certain attitude verbs and licensing a shift in perspective, with some indexicals shifting accordingly. Abrusán (2021) calls this protagonist projection, and argues that it differs from FID in important respects. Protagonist projection is captured in (8) by the introduction of ©pred for the relevant verbs. I take it that FID is always and only introduced globally.

  10. Cf. see Potts’ (2007) analysis of the meaning of say in indirect discourse, where the content of the complement is something the speaker is committed to, a purported belief state. Hence, arguably say does denote an attitude, rather like the purported beliefs of ©CS. And it seems that according to has a content like that of say. Like say, according to may report characterizations of a counterfactual situation in which the reporting agent purportedly finds herself.

  11. From episode 8 of Season 1: “Mr. Monk and the Marathon Man”.

  12. Kratzer (2020) explains that the evidential domain of an ema is factual not in that all of the available evidence is true in the world in which the agent actually finds themself, but in that whatever the evidence, its source, and its reliability, this is replicated in all the worlds in the modal’s domain. And she is at pains to make clear that the evidential situation needn’t contain the actual things the agent has information about in that situation—in (12) it needn’t include the actual corpse—so that the available information pertaining to such an object may be limited—the detectives don’t have access to information about whether she was poisoned. But crucially, it includes all the relevant available evidence, noticed or not.

  13. This echoes the findings of Moss (2015), who argues that the QUD in a given context of utterance, a partition over worlds in the interlocutors’ Common Ground, plays an important role in domain restriction of the epistemic vocabulary she considers, and so ultimately in their truth conditional contributions, including explaining apparent non-commutativity of disjunctions containing epistemic vocabulary.

  14. One might further restrict the domain to only consider those propositions that the anchor knows, rather than just those that she believes to be true, as proposed by McCready (2008, 2010). I think this is too strong, as others have argued in the literature.

  15. See Hacking (1967), Egan et al. (2005), MacFarlane (2005), Stephenson (2007), von Fintel and Gillies (2007, 2011), inter alia.

  16. See Sharvit (2008), Eckardt (2015) for overviews and extensive illustrations.

  17. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer, who brought this contrast to my attention.

  18. Though see Dowell (2011) for discussion of a variety of other examples.

  19. An anonymous reviewer points out that similar examples involving telescoping also appear acceptable:

    1. (i)

      Every contestant worried about the future. He might be kicked off the show and sent home empty-handed. It would be intolerable.

    One might understand telescoping as a kind of zooming in on the arbitrary instance of the quantificational domain, in this case licensing the arbitrary ©worry to serve as anchor for might. But since I know of no fully satisfactory account of telescoping at this time, this is just an intuition.

  20. I suspect that epistemic modals generally do not take semantic tense, but always get their temporal interpretation indexically. But that does not preclude their “wearing” tense. Fǎlǎuş and Laca (2021) discuss cases where Romance epistemic modals bear past morphology, but there ‘past’ seems to only apply to the interpretation of the modal’s prejacent. They say, “Whatever the right analysis for these cases turns out to be, it seems clear that an appropriate context for the. . .Romance examples involving modals bearing imparfait morphology requires licensing by an implicit past attitude. If this is the case, the label “past temporal perspective” is misleading as applied to them: the temporal perspective is actually simultaneous (“present”), but it is simultaneous to a past attitude, as it is the case in overt sequence of tense contexts.” That is, the past-ness of the epistemic modal comes from the anchoring perspective, not from the tense it bears. Thanks to Paula Menéndez-Benito (p.c.) for pointing out their relevant work. Of course, many more languages need to be considered before one can generalize the claim about epistemic modals being tenseless. But insofar as epistemic modals are indexical in the sense defined here, that is what we would expect.

  21. It is clear that root modals do often bear a special relationship to the subject of the clause in which they occur. Whether this is direct (via control) or indirect (via raising) is controversial, though the latter view currently seems dominant. See the literature summarized in Portner (2009, section 4.3.2: 187ff).

  22. About which I have serious reservations; see Roberts (2018).

  23. (43) is Yalcin’s (8) with but substituted for his and, and the final raining elided. I take it that this is more natural sounding, and the change makes no difference to the logic of the examples.

  24. Rich Thomason (p.c. to Bill Harper, brought to my attention by Nate Charlow) noticed around 1975 that “conditionally entertaining that P is not conditionally entertaining that KP” (Rich’s characterization, p.c.), offering as an example If my wife were cheating on me, I wouldn’t know it, subsequently much cited in the literature.

  25. The problem has, of course, been discussed by others. For example, see Anand and Hacquard (2013). Space precludes comparing all the approaches that have been considered.

  26. Merriam-Webster (http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/entertain) offers this definition for entertain (definition 3a): “to keep, hold, or maintain in the mind”. And a direction to suppose is often followed by Then…

  27. So-called counterfactual conditionals in English themselves are only possibly counterfactual, as recognized at least since Karttunen and Peters (1979). This will be the case with suppose as well.

  28. In actual implementation, the agent is an individual concept, type <s,e>. I simplify for ease of exposition.

  29. See Portner (2007), Roberts (2018, 2022a, 2022b) for details, simplified here.

  30. Nate Charlow and Phil Kremer (p.c.) pointed out the importance of the reversed order examples, for which I am grateful.

  31. Note that the Diversity Condition of Condoravdi (2002)/the Disparity Principle of Werner (2003, 2006), requiring that the modal domain contains both worlds where the prejacent is true and those where it is false, also fail to hold in cases like (63): This condition only holds when the QUD is ‘whether ’ or some super-question thereof. But in such cases, Disparity/Diversity follows from the QUD, for these are the alternatives in the partition.

  32. Compare the present proposal with that of Mandelkern (2019c) on this point: His “guiding observation” is that “a claim of \( \left\lceil {{\hbox{Might p}}} \right\rceil \) is a proposal to make p compatible with the common ground, and to make this fact itself common ground.” This is what is typically asserted in uttering a declarative might p in a context where the QUD is ‘whether p’. But in Mandelkern’s formulation, the generalization is too broad: If the student in (63) had replied instead There might be three reds, Mordecai would have responded That’s right!, and neither he nor the student would have intended to suggest that the prejacent should be compatible with the common ground, with which it is in fact incompatible.

  33. An anonymous reviewer and Paula Menéndez-Benito (p.c.) point out that on the present account, “must can be expected to give rise to weakness implicatures relative to a shifted perspective” (PMB). I think that’s the right prediction: If the QUD is ‘what does Pascal know about p’ and the answer is ‘(according to Pascal) there must be two reds’, there is an inference that Pascal is not in a position to assert that p.

  34. A related reason one might hedge about the truth of the prejacent of an ema has to do with what’s at stake, a point emphasized by Stanley (2005) about knowledge generally. The formal Character of emas in Sect. 3 does not reflect the subtleties about credence that would be required to capture this distinction, but it should be kept in mind.

  35. See earlier arguments along similar lines due to Stone (1994), Murray (2014), Swanson (2015), Lassiter (2016), and Silk (2016). Though the data are rather delicate, I think these authors give good evidence for something like Support as a general constraint on the felicitous use of emas; and Mandelkern also offers convincing experimental results. Support can be taken to be a corollary of Palmer’s characterization of must above: a reflection of the anaphoric presupposition that there is a salient modal base f which yields the domain of the operator in the modal’s proffered content. This is a different account than that proposed by Mandelkern (2019b); unfortunately there isn’t space here to discuss his proposal in detail.

  36. The following elaborations on the scenario are not considered by von Fintel and Gillies (2021).

  37. Lassiter (2016, section 4.4) makes related arguments about examples like (67), though without assuming the character of must that supports this discussion here.

  38. An anonymous reviewer finds that another factor in the felicity of must claims is whether the truth of the prejacent is particularly contentious. Perhaps. It might be that in a contentious discussion it behaves the interlocutors to exercise greater precision or caution in drawing conclusions.

References

  • Abrusán, M. (2021). The spectrum of perspective shift: Protagonist projection versus free indirect discourse. Linguistics and Philosophy, 44, 839–873. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-020-09300-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aikhenvald, A. Y. (2006). Evidentiality. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amaral, P. M., Roberts, C., & Smith, E. A. (2007). Review of The logic of conventional implicatures by Christopher Potts. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30, 707–749.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anand, P., & Hacquard, V. (2013). Epistemics and attitudes. Semantics and Pragmatics, 6(8), 1–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barlew, J. (2017).The semantics and pragmatics of perspectival expressions in English and Bulu: The case of deictic motion verbs. Ph.D. dissertation, The Ohio State University.

  • Cinque, G. (1999). Adverbs and functional heads: A crosslinguistic perspective (Oxford Studies in Comparative Syntax). Oxford University Press.

  • Cipria, A., & Roberts, C. (2000). Spanish imperfecto and preterito: Truth conditions and aktionsart effects in a situation semantics. Natural Language Semantics, 8(4), 297–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Condoravdi, C. (2002). Temporal interpretation of modals. Modals for the present and for the past. In D. Beaver, S. Kaufmann, B. Clark, & L. Casillas (Eds.), The construction of meaning (pp. 59–88). CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deal, A. R. (2020). A theory of indexical shift. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Degen, J., Trotzke, A., Scontras, G., Wittenberg, E., & Goodman, N. D. (2019). Definitely, maybe: A new experimental paradigm for investigating the pragmatics of evidential devices across languages. Journal of Pragmatics, 140, 33–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Del Pinel, G., & Waldon, B. (2018). Experimenting with epistemic tensions: Must might be weak, might must be strong. Ms., University of Michigan and Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1991). Epistemic possibilities. The Philosophical Review, 100(4), 581–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Djärv, K. (2019). Factive and assertive attitude reports. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Pennsylvania.

  • Doron, E. (1991) Point of view as a factor of content. In S. Moore & A. Z. Wyner (Eds.), Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 1 (pp. 51–64). Cornell University, CLC.

  • Dorr, C., & Hawthorne, J. (2013). Embedding epistemic modals. Mind, 122(488), 868–913.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowell, J. (2011). A flexibly contextualist account of epistemic modals. Philosopher’s Imprint, 11(14), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, D. R. (1986). The effects of aspectual class on the temporal structure of discourse: Semantics or pragmatics? Linguistics and Philosophy, 9, 37–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eckardt, R. (2015). The semantics of free indirect discourse. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, A. (2007). Epistemic modals, relativism, and assertion. Philosophical Studies, 133, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan, A., Hawthorne, J., & Weatherson, B. (2005). Epistemic modals in context. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy: Knowledge (pp. 131–170). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fǎlǎuş, A., & Laca, B. (2021). Modal-temporal interactions. In D. Gutzmann, L. Matthewson, C. Meier, H. Rullmann, & T. E. Zimmermann (Eds.), The Wiley Blackwell companion to semantics. Wiley. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118788516.sem073.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fillmore, C. J. (1975). Santa Cruz lectures on deixis. Indiana University Linguistics Club.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K. (1994). Restrictions on quantifier domains. University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A. S. (2007). An opinionated guide to epistemic modality. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 2, pp. 32–62). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A. S. (2008). CIA leaks. The Philosophical Review, 117(1), 77–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A. S. (2010). Must. . .stay. . .strong! Natural Language Semantics, 18, 351–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A. S. (2011). Might made right. In A. Egan & B. Weatherson (Eds.), Epistemic modality (pp. 108–130). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A. S. (2021). Still going strong. Natural Language Semantics, 29, 91–113. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-020-09171-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K., & Iatridou, S. (2003). Epistemic containment. Linguistic Inquiry, 34(2), 173–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodhue, D. (2018). Must φ is felicitous only if φ is not known. Semantics and Pragmatics, 10, 14. https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.10.14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1967). Possibility. Philosophical Review, 76(2), 143–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacquard, V. (2010). On the event relativity of modal auxiliaries. Natural Language Semantics, 18, 79–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacquard, V. (2013). On the grammatical category of modality. In M. Aloni, M. Franke, & F. Roelofsen (Eds.), Proceedings of the 19th Amsterdam Colloquium (pp. 19–26). ILLC.

  • Harris, J. A., & Potts, C. (2009). Perspective-shifting with appositives and expressive. Linguistics and Philosophy, 32(6), 523–552.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J., Rothschild, D., & Spectre, L. (2015). Belief is weak. Philosophical Studies, 173, 1393–1404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (1982). The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

  • Heim, I. (1992). Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs. Journal of Semantics, 9, 183–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinrichs, E. (1986). Temporal anaphora in discourses of English. Linguistics and Philosophy, 9, 63–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hockett, C. F. (1990). Bring, take, come, and go. Journal of English Linguistics, 23, 239–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ippolito, M. (2017). Constraints on the embeddability of epistemic modals. In R. Truswell, C. Cummins, C. Heycock, B. Rabern, & H. Rohde (Eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 21(1) (pp. 605–622). Elsevier. https://ojs.ub.uni-konstanz.de/sub/index.php/sub/article/view/157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H., & Reyle, U. (1993). From discourse to logic. Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1977). Demonstratives, draft #2. Ms., UCLA Philosophy Department. Revised and published as “Demonstratives: An essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics, and epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals.” In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford University Press, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karttunen, L. (1972). Possible and must. In J. Kimball (Ed.), Syntax and Semantics, 1 (pp. 1–20). Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karttunen, L. (1976). Discourse referents. In J. McCawley (Ed.), Syntax and Semantics, 7 (pp. 363–386). Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karttunen, L., & Peters, S. (1979). Conventional implicatures. In C.-Y. Oh & D. Dineen (Eds.), Syntax and Semantics, 11: Presupposition (pp. 1–56). Academic Press.

  • Kratzer, A. (1981/2012). The notional category of modality. In H. J. Eikmeyer, & H. Rieser (Eds.), Words, worlds and contexts (pp. 38–74). de Gruyter. Significantly revised and published as Chapter 2 of Kratzer (2012).

  • Kratzer, A. (1989). An investigation of the lumps of thought. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12, 608–653.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (2002). Facts: Particulars or information Units? Linguistics and Philosophy, 25, 655–670.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (2009). Modals and context-dependency. Ms. of a lecture given at Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (2012). Modals and conditionals. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (2020). What’s an epistemic modal anyway? Ms., UMass, Amherst.

  • Lassiter, D. (2016). Must, knowledge and indirectness. Natural Language Semantics, 24, 117–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Attitudes de dicto and de se. The Philosophical Review, 88(4), 513–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74(4), 549–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Link, G. (1983). The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms: A lattice theoretical approach. In R. Bäuerle, C. Schwarze, & A. von Stechow (Eds.), Meaning, use, and interpretation of language (pp. 302–323). de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, J. (1977). Semantics (Vol. 2). Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2005). The assessment sensitivity of knowledge attributions. Oxford Studies in Epistemology, 1, 197–233. Reprinted in Sosa, E., Kim, J., Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (Eds.), Epistemology: An anthology. Blackwell, 2008.

  • MacFarlane, J. (2011). Epistemic modals are assessment-sensitive. In B. Weatherson & A. Egan (Eds.), Epistemic modality (pp. 144–178). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelkern, M. (2019a). Bounded modality. Philosophical Review, 128(1), 1–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelkern, M. (2019b). What ‘must’ adds. Linguistics and Philosophy, 42(3), 225–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelkern, M. (2019c). How to do things with modals. Mind and Language, 35, 115–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthewson, L. (2015). Evidential restrictions on epistemic modals. In L. Alonso-Ovalle & P. Menéndez-Benito (Eds.), Epistemic indefinites (pp. 141–160). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, F. (2012). Two kinds of first-person-oriented content. Synthese, 184, 157–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCready, E. (2008). Evidentials, knowledge and belief. Proceedings of LENLS, 5, 156–167.

  • McCready, E. (2010). Evidential universals. In T. Peterson & U. Sauerland (Eds.), Evidence from evidentials (UBC Working Papers in Linguistics Vol. 28) (pp. 105–127). University of British Columbia.

  • Moore, G. E. (1993). Moore’s paradox. In T. Baldwin (Ed.), G. E. Moore: Selected writings (pp. 207–212). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, J. (1970). On the criterion of identity for noun phrase deletion. CLS, 6, 380–381.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moss, S. (2015). On the semantics and pragmatics of epistemic vocabulary. Semantics and Pragmatics, 8(5), 1–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray, S. (2014). Varieties of update. Semantics and Pragmatics, 7(2), 1–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ninan, D. (2010). De se attitudes: Ascription and communication. Philosophy Compass, 5(7), 551–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oshima, D. Y. (2006a). Motion deixis, indexicality, and presupposition. In M. Gibson & J. Howell (Eds.), Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 16 (pp. 172–189). Cornell University, CLC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oshima, D. Y. (2006b). Perspectives in reported discourse. Ph.D. dissertation, Stanford University.

  • Palmer, F. R. (1979). Modality and the English modals. Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. H. (1984). Nominal and temporal anaphora. Linguistics and Philosophy, 7, 243–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Portner, P. (2007). Imperatives and modals. Natural Language Semantics, 15, 351–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Portner, P. (2009). Modality (Oxford Surveys in Semantics and Pragmatics). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potts, C. (2007). The dimensions of quotation. In C. Barker & P. Jacobson (Eds.), Direct compositionality (pp. 405–431). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rett, J. (2016). On a shared property of deontic and epistemic modals. In N. Charlow & M. Chrisman (Eds.), Deontic modality (pp. 200–229). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, C. (1989). Modal subordination and pronominal anaphora in discourse. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12(6), 683–721. Reprinted in J. Gutierrez-Rexach (Ed.), Semantics: Critical concepts in linguistics, Routledge, 2003.

  • Roberts, C. (1996/2012). Information structure in discourse: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. In J. H. Yoon & A. Kathol (Eds.), Ohio State University Working Papers in Linguistics, vol. 49 (pp. 91–136). Reprinted in the 1998 version with a new Afterword in Semantics and Pragmatics, vol. 5, 2012.

  • Roberts, C. (2015). Indexicality: De se semantics and pragmatics. Ms., OSU.

  • Roberts, C. (2017). Agreeing and assessing: Epistemic modals and the question under discussion. Ms., NYU and OSU.

  • Roberts, C. (2018). Speech acts in discourse context. In D. Fogal, D. Harris, & M. Moss (Eds.), New work on speech acts (pp. 317–359). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, C. (2021). Modal subordination: “It would eat you first!” In D. Gutzmann, L. Matthewson, C. Meier, H. Rullmann, & T. E. Zimmermann (Eds.), The Wiley Blackwell companion to semantics. Wiley. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118788516.sem102.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, C. (2022a). Imperatives in a dynamic pragmatics. Ms., submitted for publication.

  • Roberts, C. (2022b). The architecture of interpretation: Auxiliary content and pragmatic competence. Beth Lecture, 23th Amsterdam Colloquium.

  • Rothschild, D. (2020). What it takes to believe. Philosophical Studies, 177, 1345–1362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rullmann, H., & Matthewson, L. (2018). Towards a theory of modal-temporal interaction. Language, 94(2), 281–331. https://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2018.0018.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Santorio, P. (2010). Modals are monsters: On indexical shift in English. In N. Li & D. Lutz(Eds.), Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 20 (pp. 289–308). CLC and LSA.

  • Shaer, M. (2016). The false promise of DNA testing. The Atlantic, June, 2016. https://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2016/06/a-reasonable-doubt/480747/.

  • Sharvit, Y. (2008). The puzzle of free indirect discourse. Linguistics and Philosophy, 31, 353–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sherman, B. (2018). Open questions and epistemic necessity. The Philosophical Quarterly, 68(273), 819–840. https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqy025.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silk, A. (2016). Discourse contextualism: A framework for contextualist semantics and pragmatics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Speas, M., & Tenny, C. (2003). Configurational properties of point of view roles. In A.-M. Di Sciullo (Ed.), Asymmetry in grammar (pp. 315–344). John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. C. (2008). Locating ourselves in the world. In Our knowledge of the internal world (pp. 47–74). Oxford University Press.

  • Stalnaker, R. C. (2014). Context. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford University Press.

  • Stephenson, T. (2007). Towards a theory of subjective meaning. Ph.D. dissertation, MIT.

  • Stone, M. (1994). The reference argument of epistemic must. Proceedings of IWCS, 1, 181–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swanson, E. (2015). The application of constraint semantics to the language of subjective uncertainty. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 45(121), 121–146.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veltman, F. (1985). Logics for conditionals. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Amsterdam.

  • Werner, T. (2003). Deducing the future and distinguishing the past: Temporal interpretation in modal sentences in English. Ph.D. dissertation, Rutgers University.

  • Werner, T. (2006). Future and non-future modal sentences. Natural Language Semantics, 14, 235–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Willer, M. (2015). An update on epistemic modals. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 44(6), 835–849.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Willett, T. (1988). A cross-linguistic survey of the grammaticalization of evidentiality. Studies in Language, 12, 51–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yalcin, S. (2007). Epistemic modals. Mind, 116, 983–1026.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yalcin, S. (2011). Nonfactualism about epistemic modality. In A. Egan & B. Weatherson (Eds.), Epistemic modality (pp. 295–332). Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199591596.003.0011.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am indebted to Jefferson Barlew, Greg Kierstead, and Eric Snyder for discussions of this material over many months and their own stimulating exploration of related ideas; to Nate Charlow, Guillermo Del Pinal, Janice Dowell, Kai von Fintel, Hans-Martin Gärtner, Thony Gillies, Lelia Glass, Jack Hoeksma, Marcus Kneer, Phil Kremer, Dan Lassiter, Ernie LePore, Emar Maier, Friederike Moltmann, Carl Pollard, Jennifer Spenader, Rich Thomason, Judith Tonhauser, and Brandon Waldon for stimulating discussions and comments, and especially to anonymous reviewers for the journal Semantics and Pragmatics for tough and extremely useful comments on a much earlier draft, as well as to my reviewers and Paula Menéndez-Benito at L&P, whose help led to very substantial improvements. I am also grateful to audiences at the Rutgers University ErnieFest in 2014, the MASZAT group at the Research Institute for Linguistics of the Hungarian Institute of Sciences, ReDRAW’15 at the University of Groningen, the 2018 meeting of the Society for Exact Philosophy at the University of Connecticut, a University of Toronto Philosophy Colloquium, the NY Philosophy of Language Workshop, the Philosophy of Language and Mind meeting in St. Andrews in August, 2019, and Cleo Condoravdi’s fall 2020 Stanford seminar. An earlier version of this paper was completed while I was a Senior Fellow in 2014–2015 at the Institute for Advanced Studies at Central European University, Budapest, Hungary, sponsored by Budapesti Közép-Európai Egyetem Alaptvány, and I am deeply grateful for their support, and for the assistance of OSU, without which I could not have accepted the fellowship. The theses promoted herein are the author’s own, and do not necessarily reflect the opinion of any of the other sponsoring organizations or individuals cited here. To my dismay, as this paper was being proofread I discovered Santorio (2010), which is relevant to the proposal herein. I will have to save for another occasion discussion of Santorio’s proposal for treating epistemic and doxastic modals as Kaplanian monsters.

Funding

Partial funding was received from a Targeted Investment in Excellence grant from The Ohio State University, from a Research Enhancement Grant from the OSU Colleges of the Arts and Sciences, and from NSF Grants #0952571 and #1452674, 2015–2018 to Beaver, Roberts, Simons and Tonhauser.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Craige Roberts.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Roberts, C. The indexical character of epistemic modality. Linguist and Philos 46, 1219–1267 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-023-09384-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-023-09384-3

Keywords

Navigation