Skip to main content
Log in

The unbearable rightness of seeing? Conceptualism, enactivism, and skilled engagement

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Building on the landmark O’Regan and Noë (Behav Brain Sci 24:939–973, 2001) that introduced us to the sensorimotor theory of perception, Alva Noë has continued to develop and defend a highly influential enactivist account of perception. Said account takes perceptual experience to be mediated by sensorimotor knowledge (knowledge of the law-like relations that hold between bodily movements and sensory changes). In recent work, Noë has argued that we should construe sensorimotor knowledge as a kind of conceptual knowledge. One significant theoretical advantage of his account, he contends, is that it allows us to better characterize our embodied coping skills by way of showing how they are manifestations of a conceptual-and-yet-not-representational kind of understanding. He argues that both intellectualist and anti-intellectualist accounts of skill alike assume that conceptual understanding must be wedded to explicit judgement, and therefore have failed to correctly characterize the role of understanding in skilled performance. This paper argues against Noë’s contention that skilled action is always permeated with understanding. It argues additionally that Noë’s of unorthodox notion of conceptual understanding is unstable and, if it were adopted, would over-intellectualize the role of perception in action. The paper concludes by arguing that doing so frees us up to take more seriously the enactivist options for understanding skilled performance without introducing notions of conceptual understanding at all.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Noë sometimes refers to SKE as ‘actionism’ in order to emphasise the importance the position places on the role of sensorimotor action in generating perceptual experience (e.g., 2012, 2015, 2021). In this paper, I will not engage with the thorny theoretical issue of whether sensorimotor knowledge enactivism is plausibly construed as a version of what Varela et al. (2017) termed ‘enactivism’ in their seminal monograph The Embodied Mind (see Ward et al. (2017) for thoroughgoing comparison between SKE and other positions that use the ‘enactivism’ label).

  2. Some philosophers have criticised SKE’s central contention that perception is a species of embodied engagement by way of denying that sensorimotor movement is a necessary condition of seeing (see e.g., Cavedon-Taylor, 2013).

  3. Gallagher (2008) criticises Noë for failing to fully consider the importance of intersubjectivity for perceptual experience. He argues that Noë devotes too much attention to the way that a subject will perceive an object (such as an apple) as accessible in virtue of her knowledge of her own individual sensorimotor contingencies, at the expense of neglecting the way that our perception of objects might also be determined and shaped by the way that we are attuned to how other subjects might interact with them (Gallagher, 2008, p. 175). Gallagher pulls no punches when he suggests that Noë threatens to create a “lonely world” for the enactive perceiver (p. 172)—one that fails to recognise research in contemporary developmental psychology demonstrating the importance of shared attentional processes in explaining how we learn how to interact with objects (see also Di Paolo et al., 2017 pp. 246–249).

  4. Referring to his earliest defences of SKE (cf. O’Regan and Noë, 2001; Noë, 2004), Noë (2021) claim that “knowledge of sensorimotor contingencies was glossed as implicit, practical, and non-propositional, as a matter of know-how” (p. 959).

  5. More specifically, McDowell (1996) requires that agents capable of perceptual experience must have conceptual capacities that can potentially be exploited in self-critical thinking (p. 49). The rationality required for knowledge, for McDowell (following Sellars), involves occupying a point in the space of reasons such that one can recognise reasons that justify one’s own beliefs. McDowell often attempts to assuage the possible concern that his conceptualism, in virtue of disqualifying animals from perceptual experience, somehow demonstrates a “human chauvinism” (2011, p. 11; see also McDowell, 2018). Indeed, in his afterward to Mind and World, he is emphatic that animals are sentient and allows that they are capable of being, “in their ways, clever, resourceful, inquisitive, friendly, and so forth” (McDowell, 1994, p. 182; see also pp. 114–119). As Gaynesford (1996) notes, however, some will deny that McDowell can licence such ascriptions of intelligence to non-human animals while also denying them rational faculties (p. 507). In more recent work, McDowell (2011) has allowed that there might be certain forms of knowledge that non-human animals are capable of possessing (p. 15). Dreyfus (2013) argues that animals do not pose so much of a problem to McDowell’s conceptualism as do young children, since he takes there to be problems with how McDowell addresses the question of how children eventually develop the linguistic and conceptual capacities required for perceptual experience (p. 24).

  6. As Noë (2021) puts it, the knowledge that, on SKE, mediates perception, is “meant to be available to non-linguistic animals” (p. 959).

  7. Dreyfus and Dreyfus’s (1980) stages of skill development are novice, competence, proficiency, expertise, and mastery. In their famous Mind Over Machine, however, they present an updated five-stage model, having added an “advanced beginner” stage into the mix and apparently collapsed the category of mastery into that of expertise. In the advanced beginner stage, beginners will increasingly use more sophisticated rules to guide their development (Dreyfus and Dreyfus, 1988, p. 22; see also Rousse and Dreyfus, 2021, p. 18). Dreyfus and Dreyfus (2008; Rousse and Dreyfus, 2021) reintroduce mastery into their model, expanding it to six stages. They claim that only a small quantity of experts will ever become masters in their respective fields of endeavour (and that non-human animals cannot become masters). A thoroughgoing analysis of the distinct stages of the Dreyfus and Dreyfus model need not concern us here, since, as will become clear, Noë’s objections to Dreyfus do not rest on such details.

  8. Often, Hebbian learning is paraphrased in Carla Shatz’s (1992) memorable rhyme “what fires together, wires together” (1992, p. 60). But since Hebbian theory dictates that a neuron must repeatedly causally participate in the firing of another neuron in order to increase the synaptic strength between them, Hebbian learning does not concern neurons that fire simultaneously (Keysers and Gazzola, 2014).

  9. Clark (2002) argues that we should conceive of such attractor states as internal, “action-oriented” representations (see also Clark, 2015; Wheeler, 2005). He notes that several of the arguments that Dreyfus offers against construing such states to be representational seem to depend on the idea that propositionally-formatted representations are not fine-grained enough to guide context-sensitive action (Clark, 2002, p. 386; see also Dreyfus, 2002, p. 381). Clark argues that action-oriented representations do not face such objections, since their content is determined by the sensorimotor capacities of the agent in such a way as cannot be captured by a general context-insensitive structure (2002, p. 387). As such, argues Clark, action-oriented representations “serve not to passively encode information but to control and structure our active engagements” (2002, p. 386). Elsewhere, however, Dreyfus appeals to the frame problem in criticising the notion of appealing to action-oriented representations in explaining skilled action. In sum, he claims that such an appeal mandates explanation as to how the cognitive system has the capacity to produce just the right representation at just the correct time so as to respond to the intricate situational demands the agent absorbed in skilled coping faces (Dreyfus, 2006, 2007b; see also Wheeler, 2005). The frame problem also forms the basis of the criticisms he famously levelled against AI research in the 1980s (Dreyfus, 1992; see also Wilks, 1972). Hutto and Myin, 2013 (see also Hutto, 2013) criticise action-orientated representations on the basis that it is hard see how—on the action-oriented account—content qua content could make an explanatory contribution (p. 59; et passim).

  10. More recently, philosophers working from within the enactivist tradition of cognitive science have argued that contemporary models of neural function derived from Karl Friston’s (2005) free energy principle provide a plausible basis for the contention that intelligent human action can be geared around obtaining an optimum grip in such a way as does not implicate representations (Bruineberg et al., 2018; Downey, 2018; Kirchhoff, 2015; see also Kirchhoff and Robertson, 2018; Robertson and Kirchhoff, 2019).

  11. Noë (2015) summarises the SC account as follows: “Reasons, principles, and explicit knowledge guide perception and activity, according to Dreyfus, but only in the case of the novice. The expert, in contrast, is one who is engaged, in the flow. The expert, having mastered the rules and the concepts, has no further use for them” (p. 9). It is worth noting, though, that Dreyfus claims that even experts and masters will occupy flow states very infrequently. An expert, for Dreyfus, will—as Noë notes—usually be engaged in skilled coping such that she will not need to consciously reflect on the environmental solicitations by which she acts (nor consult any rules), but she is only in a state of flow—of fully absorbed coping—when she entirely stops monitoring her performance. She will even, for Dreyfus, lack an “awareness that things are going well” (2007, n. 5), although presumably the flow will soon cease if her performance—for whatever reason—begins to deteriorate. Dreyfus and Dreyfus (1986) thus write as follows: “There are rare moments, however, when all monitoring ceases. We are referring to those brief periods of what is sometimes called “flow,” when performance, accompanied by a feeling of euphoria, reaches its peak” (p. 40; emphasis added; see also Dreyfus, 2013, p. 28; Rousse and Dreyfus, 2021, p. 18). Dreyfus does not deny that “conceptual activity is required for some kinds of perceiving and acting” (2013, p. 15). In fact, he takes said claim to be “obviously true” (Dreyfus, 2013, p. 15). For Dreyfus, when experts are engaged in the flow, the ego—and, along with it, any sense of “I”—disappears (e.g. 2007, p. 373; see also Sartre, 1957, pp. 48–49). Consult Kreing and Ilundáin-Agurruza (2014) for comparison between Dreyfus's notion of flow and the concept of mushin found often in traditional martial arts works (see also Miyahara, 2021).

  12. As Dreyfus (2005) puts it, phronesis is “a kind of understanding that makes possible an immediate response to the full concrete situation” (2005, p. 51). Gallagher (2020) argues that Dreyfus confuses Aristotle’s notion of phronesis with what he (Aristotle) referred to as a capacity for “cleverness” (2020, p. 257). Some Aristotelians, however, argue that Aristotle understood cleverness to be a constituent of phronesis (Athanassoulis, 2018). Finnigan (2015) too expresses doubt as to whether Dreyfus’s characterisation of phronesis as a perceptual capacity is plausibly consistent with Aristotle’s view.

  13. Rousse and Dreyfus (2021) claim that the SC account is often caricatured. They note that some—such as Montero (2016)—have criticised the idea that experts tend to perform unreflectively. In response, they point out that the SC has always allowed that even experts will often, faced with unforeseen circumstances, need to break coping and engage in reflective thought (thereby oscillating back and forth through the various stages of skill development). The idea is that the expert will not need to reflect on their doings “when things are proceeding normally” (Dreyfus and Dreyfus, 1988, p. 31; Rousse and Dreyfus, 2021, p. 30). That said, Montero criticises the notion that in paradigmatically expert domains such as elite sports performance we can speak of things proceeding normally, since such experts are always faced with situational novelty. In this way, Montero criticises the idea that SC characterises high-level, professional expert endeavours as unfolding through the same kind of absorbed coping processes as do highly habituative, everyday doings, such as walking down a city street (2016, Chapter 2; see also Toner et al. 2022). Rousse and Dreyfus (2021), on the other hand, are emphatic that they take there to be a “fundamental continuity between everyday skills and specialized (or “elite”) skills” that “lies in the tendency for experienced performers to develop an intuitive familiarity that guides them in coping with typical situations” (Rousse and Dreyfus, 2021, p. 3).

  14. In this way, Dreyfus’s view on expert rule-following bares striking similarity to that of Gilbert Ryle. Ryle (1949/2009) describes a skilled performer gaining competence while simultaneously becoming less able to explicitly follow rules in the following terms: “But very soon he comes to observe the rules without thinking of them. He makes the permitted moves and avoids the forbidden ones; he notices and protests when his opponent breaks the rules. But he no longer cites to himself or to the room the formulae in which the bans and permissions are declared. It has become second nature to him to do what is allowed and to avoid what is forbidden. At this stage he might even have lost his former ability to cite the rules” (p. 29; see Waights-Hickman, 2019 for discussion of Ryle’s views on the relationship between rules and know-how).

  15. Noë (2015, n. 9) likens this appeal to demonstratives to the way McDowell uses to demonstratives in supporting his contention that perceptual content is exclusively conceptual against the possible objection that we often seem to experience things that one cannot linguistically describe and therefore seem to “transcend our conceptual powers” (McDowell 1994, p. 56). McDowell appeals to the idea that we can linguistically describe even highly intricate facets of our experience—such as a rich and unfamiliar shade of colour—by invoking demonstratives. Some have objected to McDowell’s line here on the basis that it presumably rests on the idea that the demonstrative concept, say, of a colour, is fixed by the subject perceptually experiencing that colour, but that it is unclear that McDowell can licence such a move, since the concept of the colour cannot then be part of the perceptual experience (Heck, 2000).

  16. As Noë (2015) notes, Dreyfus (e.g., 2006) often offers lightning chess players as an example of experts who perform without conscious deliberation or reflection. For Dreyfus, lightning chess masters lack the time required (at least when they are performing optimally) to engage in calculations about what move to make (or to consult rules), but instead are able to rely on their perceptual capacities in order to see what move would be appropriate (2006, p. 47). The master’s perceptual capacities in this regard (honed through many hours of practice) allows her “to respond to subtle differences in the appearance of perhaps hundreds of thousands of situations” (2006, p. 48). Montero (2019) has argued against Dreyfus’s claims about lightning chess masters, contending that even lightning chess players engage in conscious deliberation about their moves. She conducted a series of trials in which four accomplished chess players were instructed to verbalize the thoughts they had while playing 1-min chess games online. On the basis that there was no significant loss in ability amongst participants, Montero took her experiment to suggest that even accomplished lightning chess players can consciously deliberate about their moves as they make them (2019, p. 381). Notice, however, that even if we accept that conscious deliberation and reflection is more involved in skills such as lightning chess than Dreyfus is willing to accept, this does not show that he has gone wrong in holding the Intellectualist Assumption. One could readily accept the Intellectualist Assumption that judgement is the only mode of conceptual understanding and yet take Dreyfus underestimating how important judgement is even in highly immersive action.

  17. Dreyfus and Taylor (2015) refer to skilled coping as “a preconceptual engagement […] which involves understanding” (p. 72). While McDowell adopts the Kantian term “spontaneity” to refer to processes that involve conceptual capacities, Dreyfus contrastingly argues that spontaneity is involved in the nonconceptual engagement with the world that he takes to be characteristic of expert coping. The absorbed expert, Dreyfus contends, can be said to “make sense” of his surroundings and exercise spontaneity in virtue of actively engaging with them in such a way as to make the affordances that are most relevant to his performance salient to him. He offers Merleau-Ponty’s example of a football player engaging with “the field before him, articulating it into vectors of vulnerability where the other can break through” (Dreyfus and Taylor, 2015, p. 88). As such, Dreyfus and Taylor allow that “spontaneity is “rational” because it is not just arbitrary, but is directed to make sense of our world, to getting it right” (p. 77).

  18. See McCauley and Henrich (2006) for discussion of how susceptibility to the illusion changes across cultures.

  19. In fact, Stanley (2011) claims that “genuinely skilled action requires being directly guided by one’s propositional knowledge—being guided automatically and without reflection” (2011 p. 24 emphasis added).

  20. One might, for example, take having propositional knowledge that w is a way to φ to involve understanding that w is a way to φ. They might, in turn, take understanding that w is a way to φ to necessarily involve—for example—knowing how to explain why w is a way to φ. In such a case, the intellectualist will argue that this know-how is propositional.

  21. As Michaelian and Sant’Anna (2021) have recently put it, RE is " an increasingly influential approach to cognition in general” (p. S307). It has in recent years been deployed as a theoretical framework for investigating basic emotions (Hutto et al., 2018), predictive and probabilistic views of cognition (Kirchhoff and Robertson, 2018; Robertson and Kirchhoff, 2019), perceptual illusions (Gallagher et al., 2022), habits (Hutto and Robertson 2020; Miyahara and Robertson, 2021), autism (Hipólito et al., 2020), skilled action (Merritt, 2015; Ilundain-Agurruza, 2015; Krein and Ilundain-Agurruza, 2017; Carmona, 2021), and a range of other cognitive phenomena.

  22. Others have criticised RE on the basis that it supposedly does not warrant its “radical” label. Gärtner and Clowes (2017), for example, deny that RE is radical because anti-representational views have a venerable lineage (one that goes through the likes of Stich, the Churchlands, and others) in contemporary philosophy of mind (p. 78). Although I am not here concerned with how radical RE is, these sorts of objections seem to conflate a position being radical with its being original. RE seems to possess radical credentials within analytic philosophy to the extent that mainstream cognitivist conceptions of cognition as always and everywhere involving the manipulation of representational content remain the status quo.

  23. In fact, in criticising Hutto and Myin for “conceding to the establishment” that certain kinds of language-involving thought can be representational Noë writes as follows: “Representationalism is wrongheaded, I would say, no less when it comes to language than when it comes to perceiving or other more “elementary” modes of thought and awareness” (2021, p. 962). Perhaps Noë is happy for representationalism to be criticised but takes Hutto and Myin to lack any affirmative argument against construing experience as representational beyond “mere insistence”. Since their work is positively replete with such affirmative arguments, however, this would not be a fair criticism.

  24. Bengson (2020) defends the view that the practical understanding required for skilled action involves “grasp of method—in particular, conceptual grasp of ways of acting” (p. 216).

References

  • Athanassoulis, N. (2018). Acquiring Aristotelian virtue. In N. E. Snow (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of virtue (pp. 415–431). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barkasi, M. (2021). Does what we dream feel present? Two varieties of presence and implications for measuring presence in VR. Synthese, 199(1–2), 2525–2551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J. (2020). Practical understanding: Skill as grasp of method. Concepts in thought, action, and emotion (pp. 215–235). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47(1–3), 139–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brownstein, M., & Michaelson, E. (2016). Doing without believing: Intellectualism, knowledge-how, and belief-attribution. Synthese, 193(9), 2815–2836.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Bruineberg, J., Kiverstein, J., & Rietveld, E. (2018). The anticipating brain is not a scientist: The free-energy principle from an ecological-enactive perspective. Synthese, 195(6), 2417–2444.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Carmona, C. (2018). Dance and embodied cognition: Motivations for the enactivist program. Rivista Italiana Di Filosofia Del Linguaggio. https://doi.org/10.4396/20180208

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carmona, C. (2021). Practices of remembering a movement in the dance studio: Evidence for (a radicalized version of) the REC framework in the domain of memory. Synthese, 199(1–2), 3611–3643.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cavedon-Taylor, D. (2013). Seeing and retinal stability: On a sensorimotor argument for the necessity of eye movement for sight. Philosophical Psychology, 26(2), 263–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2002). Skills, spills and the nature of mindful action. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(4), 384–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2015). Predicting peace: The end of the representation. In Open mind. MIND Group

    Google Scholar 

  • Clavel Vázquez, M. J. (2020). A match made in heaven: Predictive approaches to (an unorthodox) sensorimotor enactivism. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 19(4), 653–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Jesus, P. (2016a). Autopoietic enactivism, phenomenology and the deep continuity between life and mind. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 15(2), 265–289. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-015-9414-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Jesus, P. (2016b). From enactive phenomenology to biosemiotic enactivism. Adaptive Behavior, 24(2), 130–146. https://doi.org/10.1177/1059712316636437

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E., Buhrmann, T., & Barandiaran, X. (2017). Sensorimotor life: An enactive proposal. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Downey, A. (2018). Predictive processing and the representation wars: A victory for the eliminativist (via fictionalism). Synthese, 195, 5115–5139.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (1992). What computers still can’t do: A critique of artificial reason. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2002). Intelligence without representation–Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation. The relevance of phenomenology to scientific explanation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(4), 367–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2005). Overcoming the myth of the mental: How philosophers can profit from the phenomenology of everyday expertise. In Proceedings and addresses of the American Philosophical Association (Vol. 79, No. 2, pp. 47–65). American Philosophical Association.

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2006). Overcoming the myth of the mental. Topoi, 25, 43–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2007a). Why Heideggerian AI failed and how fixing it would require making it more Heideggerian. Philosophical Psychology, 20(2), 247–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2007b). Response to McDowell. Inquiry, 50(4), 371–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2013). The myth of the pervasiveness of the mental. Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world (pp. 25–50). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H., & Dreyfus, S. E. (1986). Mind over machine. Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H., & Dreyfus, S. (1988). Mind over machine: The power of human intuition and expertise in the era of the computer (2nd ed.). Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L., & Dreyfus, S. E. (2008). Beyond expertise: Some preliminary thoughts on mastery. A qualitative stance: Essays in honor of Steinar Kvale, 113–124.

  • Dreyfus, H., & Taylor, C. (2015). Retrieving realism. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, S. E., & Dreyfus, H. L. (1980). A five-stage model of the mental activities involved in directed skill acquisition. California University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ennen, E. (2003). Phenomenological coping skills and the striatal memory system. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 2, 299–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnigan, B. (2015). Phronēsis in Aristotle: Reconciling deliberation with spontaneity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91(3), 674–697.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, W. J. (1991). The physiology of perception. Scientific American, 264(2), 78–87.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Fridland, E. (2013). Problems with intellectualism. Philosophical Studies, 165, 879–891.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fridland, E. (2014). They’ve lost control: Reflections on skill. Synthese, 191(12), 2729–2750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2007). Moral agency, self-consciousness, and practical wisdom. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14(5–6), 199–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2020). Action and interaction. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008). Intersubjectivity in perception. Continental Philosophy Review, 41, 163–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., Hutto, D., & Hipólito, I. (2022). Predictive processing and some disillusions about illusions. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 13(4), 999–1017.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Marcel, A. J. (1999). The self in contextualized action. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6(4), 4–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärtner, K., & Clowes, R. W. (2017). Enactivism, radical enactivism and predictive processing: What is radical in cognitive science? Kairos. Journal of Philosophy & Science, 18(1), 54–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaynesford, M. D. (1996). Mind and world. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 495–509.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979).The people, place, and space reader (pp. 56–60). Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315816852

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, C. (1975). Knowledge, perception, and memory (Boston: Dordrecht Reidel). Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04385-y

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heck, R. G., Jr. (2000). Nonconceptual content and the “space of reasons.” The Philosophical Review, 109(4), 483–523.

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Hipolito, I., Hutto, D. D., & Chown, N. (2020). Understanding autistic individuals: Cognitive diversity not theoretical deficit. Neurodiversity studies (pp. 193–209). London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. L. (1998). Consciousness in action. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S., & Noë, A. (2003). Neural plasticity and consciousness. Biology & Philosophy, 18(1), 131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2005). Knowing what? Radical versus conservative enactivism. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 389–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. (2013). Exorcising action oriented representations: Ridding cognitive science of its Nazgul. Adaptive Behavior, 21(3), 142–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2017). Evolving enactivism: Basic minds meet content. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2022). Re-affirming experience, presence, and the world: Setting the RECord straight in reply to Noë. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 20, 971–989.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Robertson, I. (2020). Clarifying the character of habits: Understanding what and how they explain. Habits: Pragmatist approaches from cognitive science, neuroscience, and social theory, 204–222.

  • Hutto, D. D., Robertson, I., & Kirchhoff, M. D. (2018). A new, better BET: Rescuing and revising basic emotion theory. Frontiers in Psychology, 9, 1217.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Satne, G. (2015). The natural origins of content. Philosophia, 43, 521–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ilundáin-Agurruza, J. (2015). From clumsy failure to skillful fluency: A phenomenological analysis of and Eastern solution to sport’s choking effect. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14, 397–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keysers, C., & Gazzola, V. (2014). Hebbian learning and predictive mirror neurons for actions, sensations and emotions. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 369(1644), 20130175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. D. (2015). Experiential fantasies, prediction, and enactive minds. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 22(3–4), 68–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. D., & Robertson, I. (2018). Enactivism and predictive processing: A non-representational view. Philosophical Explorations, 21(2), 264–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krein, K., & Ilundáin-Agurruza, J. (2014). An East-west comparative analysis of Mushin and flow. Philosophy and the Martial Arts, 139–164.

  • Krein, K., & Ilundáin-Agurruza, J. (2017). High-level enactive and embodied cognition in expert sport performance. Sport, Ethics and Philosophy, 11(3), 370–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCauley, R. N., & Henrich, J. (2006). Susceptibility to the Müller-Lyer illusion, theory-neutral observation, and the diachronic penetrability of the visual input system. Philosophical Psychology, 19(1), 79–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell. (1996). Mind and world. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2011a). Perception as a capacity for knowledge. Marquette University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2011b). Some remarks on intention in action. The Amherst Lecture in Philosophy, 6, 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2013). Perceptual experience: Both relational and contentful. European Journal of Philosophy, 21(1), 144–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2018). Perceptual experience and empirical rationality. In New issues in epistemological disjunctivism (pp. 31–40). Routledge.

  • McDowell, J. (2019). Perceptual experience and empirical rationality. New issues in epistemological disjunctivism (pp. 31–40). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012). Phenomenology of Perception. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merritt, M. (2015). Thinking-is-moving: Dance, agency, and a radically enactive mind. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14, 95–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miyahara, K. (2022). Dreyfus and Zeami on embodied expertise. Knowers and Knowledge in East-West Philosophy: Epistemology Extended, 345–366.

  • Montero, B. G. (2013). A dancer reflects. In J. K. Schear (Ed.), Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world. The McDowell-Dreyfus debate (pp. 303–319). Routledge.

  • Montero, B. G. (2015). Thinking in the zone: The expert mind in action. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53, 126–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. G. (2016). Thought in action: Expertise and the conscious mind. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. G. (2019). Chess and the conscious mind: Why Dreyfus and McDowell got it wrong. Mind & Language, 34(3), 376–392.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Myin, E. (2021). On the importance of correctly locating content: Why and how REC can afford affordance perception. Synthese, 198(Suppl 1), 25–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2012). Varieties of presence. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2015). Concept pluralism, direct perception, and the fragility of presence. In Open mind. MIND Group.

  • Noë, A. (2021). The enactive approach: A briefer statement, with some remarks on “radical enactivism.” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 20(5), 957–970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A., & Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 939–973.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Orlandi, N. (2016). Bayesian perception is ecological perception. Philosophical Topics, 44(2), 327–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2015). Knowing a rule. Philosophical Issues, 25, 165–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2019). The psychological reality of practical representation. Philosophical Psychology, 32(5), 784–821.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2020). Probabilistic knowledge in action. Analysis, 80(2), 342–356.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E. (2010). McDowell and Dreyfus on unreflective action. Inquiry, 53(2), 183–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E., & Kiverstein, J. (2014). A rich landscape of affordances. Ecological Psychology, 26(4), 325–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, I. (2021). High time for a change? A response to callender on rationality and time preferences. Australasian Philosophical Review, 5(3), 296–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, I. (2023). Skills and savoir-faire: Might anti-intellectualism suffice? Inquiry, 1–27.

  • Robertson, I., & Hutto, D. D. (2023). Against intellectualism about skill. Synthese, 201(4), 143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, I., & Kirchhoff, M. D. (2019). Anticipatory action: Active inference in embodied cognitive activity. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 27(3–4), 38–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolla, G. (2021). Reconceiving rationality: Situating rationality into radically enactive cognition. Synthese, 198(Suppl 1), 571–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rousse, B., & Dreyfus, S. (2021). Revisiting the six stages of skill acquisition. Teaching and Learning for Adult Skill Acquisition: Applying the Dreyfus & Dreyfus Model in Different Fields, 3–28.

  • Ryle, G. (1945) Knowing how and knowing that. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 46

  • Ryle, G. (1949 [2009]). The concept of mind. Routledge.

  • Sartre, J. P. (1957). The transcendence of the ego: An existentialist theory of consciousness (Vol. 114). Macmillan.

  • Sartre, J. P. (2003). Being and nothingness. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schear, J. K. (2013). Are we essentially rational animals? In Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world (pp. 295–312). Routledge.

  • Shatz, C. J. (1992). The developing brain. Scientific American., 267, 60–67.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Silverman, D. (2018). Bodily skill and internal representation in sensorimotor perception. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 17(1), 157–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skarda, C. A., & Freeman, W. J. (1987). How brains make chaos in order to make sense of the world. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10(2), 161–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skora, L. I., Seth, A. K., & Scott, R. B. (2021). Sensorimotor predictions shape reported conscious visual experience in a breaking continuous flash suppression task. Neuroscience of Consciousness, 2021(1), niab003.

  • Stanley, J. (2011). Know how. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2015). Knowledge, habit, practice, skill. Journal of Philosophical Research, 40(Supplement), 315–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy., 98(8), 411–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2017). Skill. Noûs, 51(4).

  • Thompson, E. (2018). Daniel D. Hutto and Erik Myin Evolving Enactivism: Basic Minds Meet Content. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/evolving-enactivism-basic-minds-meet-content/

  • Tsai, C. H. (2022). Beyond intuitive know-how. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1–14.

  • Varela, F. J. (1994). Ethical know-how: Action, wisdom, and cognition. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (2017). The embodied mind (Revised). MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waights-Hickman, N. (2019). Knowing in the “executive way”: Knowing how, rules, methods, principles and criteria. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 99(2), 311–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, D. (2023). Sensorimotor relationalism and conscious vision. The Philosophical Quarterly, 73(1), 258–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, D., Silverman, D., & Villalobos, M. (2017). Introduction: The varieties of enactivism. Topoi, 36, 365–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive world: The next step. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilks, Y. (1972). Review: Dreyfus’s disproofs. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 27(2), 177–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2013). Mindedness, mindlessness and first-person authority. Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world: The McDowell-Dreyfus debate, 320–340.

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Daniel Hutto, Michael Kirchhoff and Deb Marber. The research for this paper was supported by the Australian Discovery Project “Minds in Skilled Performance” (DP170102987).

Funding

Funding was provided by Australian Research Council (Grant Number DP170102987).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ian Robertson.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Robertson, I. The unbearable rightness of seeing? Conceptualism, enactivism, and skilled engagement. Synthese 202, 173 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04385-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04385-y

Keywords

Navigation