Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The Varieties of Moral Vice: An Aristotelian Approach

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This article has been updated

Abstract

On a standard Aristotelian account, the moral virtues and vices stand in an asymmetric relationship to one another. To help explain this asymmetry, I argue that the vices share significantly less common structure than many think. That there are many ways for agents to get it wrong gives us prima facie reason to think that the vices lack a robust common structure. Further, the most promising candidates for a common structure (or important property) of the vices fall short. These are that (a) the vices have the common structure of being excesses and deficiencies (this is not the right kind of common structure), (b) the vices result from agents’ unreflectively taking their inclinations as their ends (not all vicious agents do), and, relatedly, (c) the vices result from rational corruption (this structure does not apply in all cases of vice). Argument (b), which Terence Irwin and others endorse, is the most promising one, so I focus on it. But it, too, faces weighty objections. I conclude that none of these important arguments establishes the existence of a robust common structure of the moral vices. The great variety of moral vices is a puzzling phenomenon that continues to stand in need of explanation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

  • 02 November 2022

    Abstract has been corrected Previously published article.

Notes

  1. I lack scope to discuss other forms of virtue ethics that take inspiration from, say, Stoicism, Thomism, Nietzscheanism, or hybrid accounts.

  2. But see Grönroos (2015) and Müller (2015). As Reeve (2018) says, these authors accept that there is no cause of all evils and no bad in the category of substance itself.

  3. See also Grönroos (2015: 151), citing Plato (1997: Republic I, 351e10-2a9). I follow Grönroos in this paragraph.

  4. I discuss Irwin (2001), Kontos (2018b) and Barney (2020) below.

  5. “Seem to” is not meant here to imply “clearly do,” which would be far too ambitious.

  6. There are also hybrid views (e.g., Barney 2020) on which vices and virtues are in different respects both symmetrical and asymmetrical.

  7. Initial quotation from Roochnik (2007: 211). See also Rorty (1980: 272), Brickhouse (2003: 4), and Nielsen (2017).

  8. Müller (2015: 460–461) names the two views and, focusing on EN IX.4, argues that the second view is correct.

  9. Grönroos (2015: 147–148, 161, et passim) argues that the vicious person faces two sets of desires. Satisfying bad desires both precludes satisfying good ones and leads to a sense of degradation.

  10. “Generally” because, as Aristotle notes (EN I 5, 106b 19–22), some people do seek to imitate powerful leaders (e.g., Sardanapallus) who lead lives of pleasure and gratification fit for grazing animals. Whether people admire the vicious-but-powerful may depend on the particular vices in question. It’s easier to admire a wealthy king who is avaricious than a murderous one.

  11. Barney (2020) provides textual and linguistic analysis of Aristotle that challenges some accounts of a robust common structure. As noted later, I agree in part with her account, including for independent reasons (see §II-V). I also critically address her account of a common structure of the vices (toward the end of §V).

  12. A related account might consider the importance of my thesis for consequentialists and deontologists who argue in the register of virtue and vice.

  13. Some argue that missing the mark is not enough to constitute vice. See, e.g., Drefcinski (1996), Cuzner (2005). I will use “missing the mark” broadly to mean deliberating poorly in choosing an end or ineffectively pursuing a well-chosen end.

  14. One might wish to read the following analysis with regard only to vice in the strict sense soon discussed. Fine by me.

  15. See Kontos (2014) on intellectual failings that cause agents in states of vice, beastliness, incontinence, and continence to miss the mark.

  16. Aristotle also distinguishes incontinence and vice temporally: the former is episodic, the latter continual (Müller, 2015: 470).

  17. See Russell (2018: 242; cf. Kontos 2018: 75 et passim, Müller 2015: 462–463) on controversy over whether Aristotle treats vicious activities as things people pursue who see it as for their good or as activity they (the “incontinent”) know is bad but pursue for temporary pleasure.

  18. Korsgaard (1986: 267) observes:

    The fact that reason itself admits of corruption or a kind of error that is undetectable (vice is unconscious of itself) implies that determining the mean by reason cannot be a straightforward matter. At least we cannot find the mean merely by engaging in some characteristic procedures of reason, for these can be misleading. For instance, we cannot determine the mean by referring to our rational wishes, for if we have vices, these too will be wrong.

  19. On this classificatory scheme, see Irwin (2001) and Curzer (2018). Curzer (2018; see also 2012), for instance, compares virtuous, continent, incontinent, vicious, and brutish (thêriotês) agents. His multifaceted account of vice pursues an intra-group pairwise ranking of agents by their moral status. He notes (2018: 102), for instance, Aristotle’s underappreciated distinction between (a) continent agents who strive to overcome vicious desires for pleasure and (b) agents with “endurance,” who aim to overcome such desires to avoid pain. My argument that the vices have fairly minimal common structure is compatible with this helpful categorization.

  20. But see Aristotle EN VII (2000); Kontos (2014: esp. 224–227; 2018b); and Pearson (2018).

  21. Emotions can be critically virtue-supporting. For instance, anger at being harmed can be good for one’s development (see, e.g., Taylor 2006: 14).

  22. For example, exercising charity will often require sympathy, but one can fail to sympathize, be insufficiently sympathetic, or sympathize for the wrong reasons or with the wrong people.

  23. Korsgaard (1986: 266) observes that the vicious might yet have harmonious souls due to their “corrupted reason.” A vicious person can reason in unconflicted ways to achieve defective ends, such that “the bad person’s rational wishes and rational judgments are harmonious with her evil passions” (266).

  24. Neo-Aristotelian views of excess and deficiency address reason and non-rational desire as well as their roles and weights in deliberation and action. It is unsurprising, then, that UET and the excess-and-deficiency account are not wholly distinct (see Irwin 1988: 374–376; 2007: 155–157).

  25. On the nature and development of practical skill, see Fridland (2014).

  26. For example, the suburbanite teenager with no income does not incorporate the virtue of generosity by giving great sums to charity. Instead she becomes generous by, say, helping her friends with their homework or volunteering at a local soup kitchen. I believe I first heard this example from Julia Annas.

  27. Annas’s account is not intended to suggest a perfect analogy between virtue and skill. Human action differs from skillful production in notable ways, and virtue requires certain motivations, unlike skill. See Aristotle (2000: EN VI).

  28. Irwin too discusses the excess and deficiency view (2001: 74).

  29. On the doctrine of the mean, see Gottlieb (2009: Chap.1, esp. 32–35). Gottlieb argues (22–32), inter alia, that it is a doctrine of equilibrium or correct balancing rather than moderation, and that virtue is a mean relative to persons and their particular contexts. By implication, when it comes to determining the mean, “the relevant factors in one situation may not be the relevant factors in another” (Meilaender, 2010). I accordingly suggest that the degree of common structure of the vices will depend on how the vices link to their particular corresponding virtues and how and how far particular vices are agent- and context-relative.

  30. Here “very vicious” allows that viciousness is scalar rather than binary.

  31. The vicious person may well pursue the fine (kalon) but does so to meet his ends and not because it is fine (see Irwin 2001: 86).

  32. On miscalibration as a vicious extreme, see Gottlieb (2009: 23).

  33. Social environments may also be full of temptations to, or accommodations for, vice, which can even make the virtuous maladapted to succeed within them.

  34. People who act upon their inclinations will not necessarily become worse off. In certain settings, relying on inclinations that are caused or guided by one’s emotional instincts can be adaptively valuable (see, e.g., Railton 2014).

  35. Irwin does say that “[p]erhaps all that the different vices have in common is their failure to be virtues” (Irwin, 2001: 74). He does not develop this idea, however, but proceeds to argue in detail that the vices have one key common structure: viz., the vicious uncritically accept their inclinations as ends.

  36. See also Gaus (2008: 56–65) on framing effects, prospect theory, and other sources of psychological bias. For instance, if Jane falsely believes that charitably helping others precludes them from eventually helping themselves, this can push her toward extreme selfishness.

  37. This theory arose as a challenge to the traditional rational actor model in economics.

  38. Repeatedly facing such situations could give one a vicious disposition to steal that is not due to an unjustified lack of reflection.

  39. This seems true insofar as reflecting seriously requires doing so in a way that is sensitive to resource trade-offs one faces qua deliberator.

  40. This allows that rationality is scalar rather than binary.

  41. Irwin’s account has also been criticized for underappreciating the conflict between wish and appetite in the vicious person. On this line of argument, the rational part of the soul, which “harbours wish,” fails to control the non-rational part, which “harbours appetite” (Grönroos, 2015: 150, 154, et passim). Korsgaard (1986: 261) notes that wish (boulesis) “is a rational desire, a desire for something conceived as a good.” Such a fact pattern is sufficient, but not necessary, however, to establish the presence of vice. Vicious agents can also, for instance, conceive (Reeve, 2018: 22–23) or pursue (Brickhouse, 2003: 12–19) the good in rationally inadequate ways.

  42. Other possible structures of the vices seem true of either some but not all vices (e.g., steady weakness in the face of temptation) or many things beyond the vices (e.g., a disposition to support value-undermining processes or outcomes). See Barney (2020: 293 − 94).

References

  • Annas, J. (2011). Intelligent Virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1963). Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1978). The Life of the Mind. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (1935). Aristotle: Athenian Constitution. Eudemian Ethics. Virtues and Vices. (transl Rackham, H.). Cambridge, MA:Harvard University Press.

  • Aristotle (2000). Nicomachean Ethics (transl. Crisp, R.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Aristotle (1998). Politics (transl. Reeve, C. D. C.). Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barney, R. (2020). “Becoming Bad: Aristotle on Vice and Moral Habituation. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy.

  • Brickhouse, T. C. (2003). “Does Aristotle Have a Consistent Account of Vice?,” Review of Metaphysics, 57:3–23.

  • Curzer, H. (2012). Aristotle and the Virtues. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Curzer, H. (2018). “Aristotelian Demons,” In Evil in Aristotle (ed. P. Kontos). Cambridge Cambridge University Press, 98–121.

  • Drefcinski, S. (1996). Aristotle’s Fallible Phronimos. Ancient Philosophy, 16(1), 139–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Driver, J. (2001). Uneasy Virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1978). Virtues and Vices. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fridland, E. (2014). They’ve Lost Control: Reflections on Skill. Synthese, 191, 2729–2750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2008). On Philosophy, Politics, and Economics. Belmont, CA: Thomson Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2016). The Tyranny of the Ideal: Justice in a Diverse Society. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Geuss, R. (2008). Philosophy and Real Politics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb, P. (2009). The Virtue of Aristotle’s Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grönroos, G. (2015). “Why is Aristotle’s Vicious Person Miserable?” In The Quest for the Good Life: Ancient Philosophers on Happiness (Rabbås, Ø., Emilsson, E. K., Fossheim, H., & Tuominen, M. (Eds.).), Oxford:Oxford University Press,146–163.

  • Hampson, Margaret. “The Learner’s Motivation and the Structure of Habituation in Aristotle” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, vol. 104, no. 3, 2022, pp. 415-447. https://doi.org/10.1515/agph-2019-0053

  • Hume, D. (1738). A Treatise of Human Nature (eds.: David Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton). Oxford University Press, 2000.

  • Hutcheson, F. (1728). Illustrations upon the Moral Sense. Selections reprinted in British moralists (ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge). 1964. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 403–418.

  • Irwin, T. (1988). Aristotle’s First Principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irwin, T. (2001). Vice and Reason. The Journal of Ethics, 5, 73–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Irwin, T. (2007). The Development of Ethics (I vol.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, J. and J. Zeis (1990). The Unity of the Vices. The Thomist, 54(4), 641–653.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kontos, P. (2014). “Non-Virtuous Intellectual States in Aristotle’s Ethics. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 47:205–243.

  • Kontos, P. (Ed.). (2018a). Evil in Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kontos, P. (2018b). “Radical Evil in Aristotle’s Ethics and Politics.” In Evil in Aristotle (ed. P. Kontos). Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,75–97.

  • Korsgaard, C. M. (1986). “Aristotle on Function and Virtue.”History of Philosophy Quarterly 3, 3,259–279.

  • Kraut, R. (2018). “Aristotle’s Ethics.”Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

  • Meilaender, P. (2010). Review of Paula Gottlieb’s The Virtue of Aristotle’s Ethics. Bryn Mawr Classical Review.

  • Müller, A. W. (2004). “Aristotle’s Conception of Ethical and Natural Virtue. How the Unity Thesis Sheds Light on the Doctrine of the Mean.” In What Is Good for a Human Being? Human Nature and Values (eds. M. Lutz-Bachmann and J. Szaif). Berlin: de Gruyter, 18–53.

  • Müller, J. (2015). Aristotle on Vice. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 23, 3: 459–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, K. (2017). Vice in the Nicomachean Ethics. Phronesis, 62, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearson, G. (2018). “Aristotle on Psychopathology.” In Evil in Aristotle (ed. P. Kontos) Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 122–149.

  • Plato (1987). Gorgias (transl., Zeyl D. J). Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato (1997). In J. M. Cooper (Ed.), Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. J. (2014). The Affective Dog and its Rational Tale. Ethics, 124, 813–859.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reeve, C. D. C. (2018). “Good and Bad in Aristotle.” In Evil in Aristotle (ed. P. Kontos) Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 17–31.

  • Robson, G. (2020). “Review of Political Utopias. Contemporary Debates” (Michael Weber and Kevin Vallier (Ed.).), Journal of Moral Philosophy 17: 367–370.

  • Roochnik, D. (2007). “Aristotle’s Account of the Vicious: A Forgivable Inconsistency.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 24: 207 – 20.

  • Rorty, A. O. (1980). “Akrasia and Pleasure.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics (ed. by A. Rorty) Berkeley : University of California Press, 267–284.

  • Russell, D. (2009). Practical Intelligence and the Virtues. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, D. (2018). “Practical Unintelligence and the Vices.” In Evil in Aristotle (ed. P. Kontos) Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 240–259.

  • Schmidtz, D. (2011). “Nonideal Theory: What It Is and What It Needs To Be,” Ethics 121: 772–96.

  • Schmidtz, D. (2016). A Realistic Political Ideal. Social Philosophy and Policy, 33, 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, G. (2006). Deadly Vices. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tolstoy, L. (1987). Anna Karenina. Wordsworth Classics.

  • Wittgenstein, L. (2009). Philosophical Investigations (4th ed.). P.M.S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte (eds. and trans.). Oxford:Wiley-Blackwell.

Download references

Acknowledgements

For generous feedback and discussion, I thank Neera Badhwar, Ben Bryan, Jason Byas, Mark LeBar, Christian Miller, James Otteson, Karina Robson, Tristan Rogers, Daniel Russell, and Wes Siscoe. I especially thank Julia Annas, a mentor who never ceases to inspire a desire for virtue.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gregory Robson.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Robson, G. The Varieties of Moral Vice: An Aristotelian Approach. Erkenn (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-022-00614-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-022-00614-x

Navigation