Skip to main content
Log in

Expressing One’s Mind

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Remarks such as ‘I am in pain’ and ‘I think that it’s raining’ are puzzling, since they seem to literally describe oneself as being in pain or having a particular thought, but their conditions of use tend to coincide with unequivocal expressions of pain or of that thought. This led Wittgenstein, among others, to treat such remarks as expressing, rather than as reporting, one’s mental states. Though such expressivism is widely recognized as untenable, Bar-On has recently advanced a neo-expressivist view, on which such remarks exhibit characteristics of both expressions of mental states and reports of those states. I argue against any attempt to see such remarks as both reporting and expressing the same mental states, and that a correct account rests on distinguishing the truth conditions of such remarks from their conditions of use.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bar-On, D. (2004). Speaking my mind: expression and self-knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-On, D. (2007). Reply to Matthew Boyle and David Rosenthal. Presented at Author-Meets-Critics session, American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division, December 2007.

  • Frege, G. (1977). Thoughts. In P. T. Geach & R. H. Stoothoff (Eds.), Logical investigations (pp. 1–30). New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gasking, D. (1962). Avowals. In R. J. Butler (Ed.), Analytical philosophy I (pp. 154–169). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (2004). The superiority of hop to hot. In R. J. Gennaro (Ed.), Higher-order theories of consciousness (pp. 93–113). Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1942). A reply to my critics. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of G. E. Moore (pp. 533–677). New York: Tudor Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1944). Russell’s theory of descriptions. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Bertrand Russell (pp. 175–226). New York: Tudor Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J., Leekam, S. R., & Wimmer, H. (1987). Three-year olds difficulty with false belief: the case for a conceptual deficit. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 5(2), 125–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1968). Brains and behaviour. In R. J. Butler (Ed.), Analytical philosophy, vol. II (pp. 1–19). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (1995). Self-knowledge and Moore’s paradox. Philosophical Studies, 77, 2–3. 1994 Pacific Division APA Special Issue (March): 195–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (2002). Moore’s paradox and Crimmins’s case. Analysis, 62(2), 167–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (2004). Varieties of higher-order theory. In R. J. Gennaro (Ed.), Higher-order theories of consciousness (pp. 17–44). Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (2005). Consciousness and mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (2008). Consciousness and its function. Neuropsychologia, 46(3), 829–840.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In W. Sellars (Ed.), Science, perception and reality. London: Routledge & Regan Paul Ltd., 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1969). Language as thought and as communication. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 29(4), 506–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1964). Notes on intentionality. The Journal of Philosophy, LXI(21), 655–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1968). Science and metaphysics. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, and Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing Co., 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1975). The structure of knowledge, lecture II: minds. In H.-N. Castañeda (Ed.), Action, knowledge, and reality: critical studies in honor of Wilfrid Sellars (pp. 316–331). Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soon, C. S., Brass, M., Heinze, H.-J., & Haynes, J.-D. (2008). Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain. Nature Neuroscience, 11(5), 543–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals: an essay in descriptive metaphysics. London: Methuen & Co., Ltd., ch. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition, 13(1), 103–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations, ed. G. E. M. Anscombe and R. Rhees, tr. G. E. M. Anscombe. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David M. Rosenthal.

Additional information

What follows derives, slightly revised, from ‘The Mind and Its Expression,’ to appear in a volume in honor of Jay Rosenberg, edited by Eric M. Rubenstein and James R. O’Shea. I am grateful to the editors for permission to use this material. My discussion here also expands on comments on Bar-On’s (2004) at an Author-Meets-Critics session, American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division, December 2007.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Rosenthal, D.M. Expressing One’s Mind. Acta Anal 25, 21–34 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-009-0078-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-009-0078-9

Keywords

Navigation