Skip to main content
Log in

Scientific Explanation and Trade-Offs Between Explanatory Virtues

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

“Explanation” refers to a wide range of activities, with a family resemblance between them. Most satisfactory explanations in a discipline for a domain fail to satisfy some general desiderata, while fulfilling others. This can happen in various ways. Why? An idealizing response would be to say that in real science explanations fall short along some dimensions, so that for any explanatory failure there is a conceivable improvement that addresses its shortcomings. The improvement may be more accurate causally or possess more unifying power, or deliver deeper understanding. We formulate a drastically less idealizing response. We argue that there are typically trade-offs in explanation, so that in strengthening one explanatory virtue one will usually weaken another. Scientific explanations, if this is correct, are constrained by such trade-offs. Particular trade-offs are appropriate for particular explanatory vehicles. There are the overarching equations of theoretical physics, which produce unification at the expense of causal detail; there are theoretical models of phenomena that occupy a middle ground between generality and the detailed workings of particular cases and get closer to explaining the workings of specific systems at the expense of unification. Sometimes experiments aim at general causal patterns at the expense of particular detail; and sometimes they are designed to give us information of particular detail at the expense of generality. There are further trade-offs associated with other vehicles of explanation. We provide examples from physics and biology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. Note that this is an altogether different matter from the problem of unification in theoretical physics. There the problem is whether the different forms of physical interaction (“forces”), can be all given a consistent representation in terms of a single symmetry schema. So far, there is no consensus as to which symmetry schema best unifies gravitation with quantum mechanics as a (string) theory of “quantum gravity”. Our point is that, even if an empirically successful theory of quantum gravity was discovered as this special issue goes to press, that wouldn’t count in favour of unity in our explanatory practices. It would be a major achievement within theoretical physics.

  2. In arguing for explanatory trade-offs, we take inspiration from Richard Levins’s “The Strategy of Model Building in Population Biology” (Levins 1966), where he argued about trade-offs in modelling.

  3. For a compact and insightful survey of the philosophy of explanation, see Weber et al. (2013).

  4. De Langhe (2009) discusses explanatory virtues in a way that allows them to be traded off against one another, but is otherwise rather different from the present account.

  5. An instance of this is Salmon’s idea of fitting phenomena in the causal structure of the world (Salmon, op. cit.).

  6. For a recent, interesting approach to unification, and a discussion of where the problem stands, see Weber and Lefevere (2017).

  7. Leuridan (2014) discusses virtues of unification with an emphasis that makes them subsidiary to virtues of causal power. While we are not arguing for any hierarchy or interdependence between the virtues, and indeed think that there are cases for all pairs of them where each can occur without the other, Leuridan's approach does have a general resemblance to what we say speculatively about IBE later in the paper. Morrison (2000, 2013) has explored the role of mathematical structures in cases of phenomena unification in theoretical physics and evolutionary biology. We postpone a discussion of this important topic to a sequel of the present paper.

  8. This paper was brought to our attention by a referee and deserves more attention than we give it. The general approach of Ylikoski and Kuorikoski is similar to ours, with different emphases. They take the contrasts between different aspects of causality as central while for us they are a symptom of a wider indeterminacy. To that extent we are more sceptical about the prospects for a non-piecemeal account of explanation than they are.

  9. In an extreme case (Lipton 2009) one can gain understanding from seeing how something could, or could have, occurred even if it did not occur for the reasons given. There is now a sizable literature on the explanation/understanding contrast, where it is linked to several different ways of making phenomena intelligible. This deserves an independent discussion. See Riggs (2003), de Regt and Parker (2014), de Regt and Diecks (2005) de Regt et al. (2009), and de Regt (2017).

  10. The extreme opposite of this would be quantum field theory, where there is enormous explanatory power yielding very little (sense of) understanding. Understanding is limited in part because the postulated processes do not unfurl in time in a familiar way to help us separate the influences of individual causal factors. So the unification that we get makes a connection with other fairly recondite theories rather than with the intuitive causal analysis of every day cases.

  11. For a recent, and insightful discussion of narratives in explanation, see Morgan (2017).

  12. Lycan (2005) gives a tidy presentation of the case against IBE, which would have to be overcome to establish its respectability. Mackonis (2013) links IBE to explanatory virtues.

  13. Just as an example! Do not take it as a report on the science. We are definitely not composing this as a theory of any autoimmune disease. But if there were really solid evidence in one case it would support the hypothesis of parallel causal detail in the other.

References

  • Dawkis, R. (1976). The selfish gene. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Langhe, R. (2009). Trading off explanatory virtues. In Logic, philosophy and history of science in belgium, proceedings of the young researchers days (pp. 62–67).

  • de Regt, H. W. (2017). Understanding scientific understanding. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W., & Dieks, D. (2005). A contextual approach to scientific understanding. Synthese, 144, 137–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W., Leonelli, S., & Eigner, K. (Eds.). (2009). Scientific understanding: Philosophical Perspectives. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W., & Parker, W. S. (2014). Introduction: Simulation, visualization, and scientific understanding. Perspectives on Science, 22, 311–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galison, P. (1987). Image and logic: A material culture for microphysics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leuridan, B. (2014). The structure of scientific theories, explanation, and unification. A causal-structural account. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 717–771.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins, R. (1966). The strategy of model building in population biology. American Scientist, 54, 421–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2009). Understanding without explanation. In H. W. de Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 43–63). Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (2005). Explanation and epistemology. The oxford handbook of epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackonis, A. (2013). Inference the best explanation, coherence, and other explanatory virtues. Synthese, 190, 975–995.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M. S. (2017). Narrative ordering and explanation. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 62, 86–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M. S., & Morrison, M. (1999). Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural science. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison. (2000). Unifying scientific theories: Physical concepts and mathematical structures. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison. (2013). Unification in Physics. In R. Batterman (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Physics (pp. 381–415). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morton, A. (1993). Mathematical models: Questions of trustworthiness. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 44(4), 659–674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and inference. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J., Glymour, M., & Jewell, N. (2016). Causal inference in statistics: A primer. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reardon, S. (2016). Neanderthal DNA affects differences in immune response (https://www.nature.com/news/neanderthal-dna-affects-ethnic-differences-in-immune-response-1.20854). Accessed 1 Nov 2019.

  • Riggs, W. (2003). Understanding virtue and the virtue of understanding. In M. DePaul & L. Zagzebski (Eds.), Intellectual virtue: Perspectives from ethics and epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosales, A. (2014). The narrative structure of scientific theorizing. PhD Dissertation. University of British Columbia.

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steyn, D. G., & Galmarini, S. (2008). Evaluating the predictive and explanatory value of atmospheric numerical models: Between relativism and objectivism. The Open Atmospheric Science Journal, 2, 38–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suarez, M. (1999). The role of models in the application of scientific theories. In M. S. Morgan & M. Morrison (Eds.), Models and mediators: Perspective on natural science (pp. 168–196). New York: Camrbidge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, E., & Lefevere, M. (2017). Unification, the answer to resemblance questions. Synthese, 17, 3501–3521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, E., Van Bouwel, J., & De Vreese, L. (2013). Scientific explanation. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski, P., & Kuorikoski, J. (2010). Dissecting explanatory power. Philosophical Studies, 148(2), 201–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank two anonymous referees for helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alirio Rosales.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rosales, A., Morton, A. Scientific Explanation and Trade-Offs Between Explanatory Virtues. Found Sci 26, 1075–1087 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-019-09645-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-019-09645-0

Keywords

Navigation