Skip to main content
Log in

On A Neglected Path to Intuitionism

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to Quine, in any disagreement over basic logical laws the contesting parties must mean different things by the connectives or quantifiers implicated in those laws; when a deviant logician ‘tries to deny the doctrine he only changes the subject’. The standard (Heyting) semantics for intuitionism offers some confirmation for this thesis, for it represents an intuitionist as attaching quite different senses to the connectives than does a classical logician. All the same, I think Quine was wrong, even about the dispute between classicists and intuitionists. I argue for this by presenting an account of consequence, and a cognate semantic theory for the language of the propositional calculus, which (a) respects the meanings of the connectives as embodied in the familiar classical truth-tables, (b) does not presuppose Bivalence, and with respect to which (c) the rules of the intuitionist propositional calculus are sound and complete. Thus the disagreement between classicists and intuitionists, at least, need not stem from their attaching different senses to the connectives; one may deny the doctrine without changing the subject. The basic notion of my semantic theory is truth at a possibility, where a possibility is a way that (some) things might be, but which differs from a possible world in that the way in question need not be fully specific or determinate. I compare my approach with a previous theory of truth at a possibility due to Lloyd Humberstone, and with a previous attempt to refute Quine’s thesis due to John McDowell.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Intuitionists do not deny excluded middle in the sense of holding it to be false; they repudiate the law only in being unwilling to assert arbitrary instances of it.

  2. For justification for these claims, see Rumfitt (2012, sec. 3). On Beth trees, see Beth (1959) and Dummett (2000, secs. 5.4 and 7.4); on Kripke trees, see Kripke (1965).

  3. Note that the sequents directly recoverable from the truth-tables do not by themselves constitute a complete axiomatization of intuitionist propositional logic. Both classicists and intuitionists accept the following elimination rule for ∧: from AB infer A; and from AB infer B. Without the assumption of Bivalence, the sequents (1) to (4) in the text do not ensure the soundness of this rule.

  4. Thus, in a recent paper, Stalnaker writes that a possible world ‘would be more accurately labelled a possible state of the world, or a way that a world might be. It is something like a property that a total universe might have, and it is a maximal property in the sense that saying that a world has a particular property of this kind is enough to determine the truth or falsity of every proposition’ (Stalnaker 2010, 21; last emphasis added).

  5. There are deductive arguments—notably, in set theory itself—for which this assumption does not hold. But I suppress the complications that a more general theory would bring in.

  6. The relation of determination must not be confused with that of relative possibility, familiar from Kripkean possible-worlds semantics. A possibility y determines a possibility x if it is logically necessary that x does obtain if y does. Per contra, a world or possibility v is possible relative to a world or possibility w if, given that w obtains, v (logically) could have obtained. Since I accept the widely held thesis that S5 is the logic of logical necessity, I have suppressed the relation of relative possibility in my analysis.

  7. See for example Davey and Priestley (2002, 145). Following Kuratowksi (1958), topologists demand more of a closure operation, namely, that Cl (∅) = ∅ and that Cl (UV) = Cl (U) ∪ Cl(V). I do not assume that closure satisfies either of these additional conditions.

  8. Proof: Suppose that xU. Then, for any statement A that is true throughout U, A will be true with respect to x. So xCl(U).

  9. Proof: To show that Cl Cl(U) ⊆ Cl(U), suppose that xCl Cl(U). Then x is a truth-ground of any statement that is true throughout Cl(U). Suppose now that statement A is true throughout U. Then A will also be true with respect to any yCl(U), i.e., A will be true throughout Cl(U). Hence A will be true with respect to x. Since this holds for any statement that is true throughout U, we have that xCl(U), showing that Cl Cl(U) ⊆ Cl(U). The converse inclusion follows directly from INCREASING.

  10. Proof: Suppose that U ⊆ V. Then any statement that is true throughout V will be true throughout U. Now suppose further that xCl(U). Then any statement that is true throughout U will be true with respect to x. So any statement that is true throughout V will be true with respect to x. So xCl(V). Thus if U ⊆ V then Cl(U) ⊆ Cl(V), as required.

  11. Proof: We need to show that when U = Cl(U) and V = Cl(V), (UV) = Cl (UV). By INCREASING, we have (UV) ⊆ Cl (UV), so it suffices to show that Cl (UV) ⊆ (UV). Now (UV) ⊆ U, so by MONOTONE, we have Cl (UV) ⊆ Cl (U). Since U = Cl(U), this yields Cl (UV) ⊆ U. Similarly, since V = Cl(V), we have Cl (UV) ⊆ V. Thus Cl (UV) ⊆ (UV), as required.

  12. Because the truth-grounds of any statement form a closed set, we still have ∧-introduction in the form: if A is a logical consequence of some premisses X, and B is a logical consequence of X, then AB is a logical consequence of X. See the proof of soundness for the rule &R in Theorem 4 of Sambin (ibid., 868).

  13. For further defence of the claim, see Hale (1999) and Rumfitt (2010).

  14. But how are we to interpret ‘xy’ when x and y are not compossible? See the beginning of the next section.

  15. For proof, see Sambin (1995), especially the remarks on distribution (864), lemma 2 (865) and theorem 4 (868).

  16. Proof: We need to show that Cl (U  V) ⊆ U  V when U and V are closed. Suppose then that xCl (U  V) and take an arbitrary u U. By Stability, xuCl (U  Vu). By definition of  , xuCl (V). Since V is closed, this means that xuV. That is, for any uU, xuV, i.e. xU  V, as required.

  17. If xx =  then ∀w (x ≤ w  w = ). But x ≤ x, so x = .

  18. Note that if f is a statement that is true only at the impossible state of affairs , then ¬A is equivalent to A →f and the closure of |¬A| follows from the result about conditionals proved in note 16.

  19. Relevant and dialetheist logicians, who reject explosion, will reject this way of ensuring that negated statements conform to (R). There are other ways of ensuring this, and thereby of developing the nascent logico-semantic theory of truth at a possibility in directions that they too could accept, but I cannot explore these alternatives here.

  20. As Sambin points out: ‘the result now is a simple and fully constructive completeness proof for first-order BL [basic linear logic] and virtually all its extensions, including the usual, or structured, intuitionistic and classical logic. Such a proof clearly illustrates the fact that stronger set-theoretic principles and classical metalogic are necessary only when completeness is sought with respect to a special class of models, such as the usual two-valued models’ (ibid., 861).

References

  • Beth EW (1959) The foundations of mathematics. North Holland, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright RL (ed) (1987) Implications and entailments. In: Cartright RL Philosophical essays, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass, pp 237–256

  • Davey BA, Priestley HA (2002) Introduction to lattices and order, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett MAE (1991) The logical basis of metaphysics. Duckworth, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett MAE (2000) Elements of intuitionism, 2nd edn. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn JM (1993) Star and perp: two treatments of negation. Philosophical Perspectives 7:331–357

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Etchemendy J (1990) The concept of logical consequence. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldblatt RI (1974) Semantic analysis of orthologic. J Phil Log 3:19–35

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hale RLV (1999) On some arguments for the necessity of necessity. Mind 108:23–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hale RLV, Hoffmann A (eds) (2010) Modality: metaphysics, logic, and epistemology. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyting A (1934) Mathematische Grundlagenforschung, Intuitionismus, Beweistheorie. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Humberstone IL (1981) From worlds to possibilities. J Phil Log 10:313–339

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke SA (1965) Semantical analysis of intuitionistic logic I. In: Crossley JN, Dummett MAE (eds) Formal systems and recursive functions. North Holland, Amsterdam, pp 92–129

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke SA (1980) Naming and necessity. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuratowksi C (1958) Topologie I, 2nd edn. PWN (Polish Scientific Publishers), Warsaw

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell JH (1976) Meaning, bivalence, and verificationism. In: Evans MGJ, McDowell JH (eds) Truth and meaning: essays in semantics. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 42–66

    Google Scholar 

  • McFetridge IG (ed) (1990) Logical necessity: some issues. In: McFetridge IG Logical necessity and other essays. Aristotelian Society, London, pp 135–154

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WV (1986) Philosophy of logic, 2nd edn. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumfitt I (2010) Logical necessity. In: Hale and Hoffmann (eds) pp 35–64

  • Rumfitt I (2012) Prospects for justificationism Forthcoming. In: Frauchiger M, Essler WK (eds) The Lauener library of analytic philosophy: themes from Dummett. Ontos, Frankfurt

    Google Scholar 

  • Sambin G (1995) Pretopologies and completeness proofs. J Symb Log 60:861–878

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker RC (1976) Possible worlds. Noûs 10:65–75

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker RC (2010) Merely possible propositions. In: Hale and Hoffmann (eds) pp 21–32

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to David Charles and Timothy Williamson for comments that improved a draft.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ian Rumfitt.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Rumfitt, I. On A Neglected Path to Intuitionism. Topoi 31, 101–109 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-011-9108-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-011-9108-5

Keywords

Navigation