Skip to main content
Log in

Phenotype-first hypotheses, spandrels and early metazoan evolution

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Against the neo-Darwinian assumption that genetic factors are the principal source of variation upon which natural selection operates, a phenotype-first hypothesis strikes us as revolutionary because development would seem to constitute an independent source of variability. Richard Watson and his co-authors have argued that developmental memory constitutes one such variety of phenotypic variability. While this version of the phenotype-first hypothesis is especially well-suited for the late metazoan context, where animals have a sufficient history of selection from which to draw, appeals to developmental memory seem less plausible in the evolutionary context of the early metazoans. I provide an interpretation of Stuart Newman’s account of deep metazoan phylogenesis that suggests that spandrels are, in addition to developmental memory, an important reservoir of phenotypic variability. I conclude by arguing that Gerd Müller’s “side-effect hypothesis” is an illuminating generalization of the proposed non-Watsonian version of the phenotype-first hypothesis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Availability of data and material

N/A.

Code Availability

N/A.

Notes

  1. The distinction between the differences actually present among the individuals in a population and potential or propensity to vary, represented by the possible routes the ball could have followed, corresponds to Wagner’s and Altenberg’s distinction between variation and variability (1996).

  2. There is also the distinct, but related notion of evolvability as used in quantitative genetics, which focuses on the evolutionary potential of populations (Hansen & Pélabon, 2021).

  3. But even here, Newman maintains that genetic accommodation may not have been in every case required. “Some [anatomical distinctions among metazoan body plans]—even the clade-defining ones—may not have initially been genetically determined, but relatively arbitrary ‘frozen accidents,’ alternative morphotypes within evolving populations of organisms for which body plans were still plastic” (Newman, 2016, p. 150).

  4. This said, Love and Lugar flag Mark Webster’s argument to the effect that the fossil record does not unequivocally support the claim that greater initial variation is typically followed by less intraspecific variation in Cambrian lineages (Love & Lugar, 2013, p. 454; Webster, 2007).

  5. In this way, just as the morphologies of the primitive metazoans were responsive to environmental stimuli in a relatively unconstrained way, Gould and Lewontin suggest that the “good design” of modern-day sponges and corals is a function of how their relatively contained liquid tissue form is tuned by the aquatic environments in which they find themselves. The fact that such marine organisms “are well adapted to the flow regimes in which they live” need not be explained by natural selection, but “may be purely phenotypic in origin, largely induced by the current itself” (Gould & Lewontin, 1979, p. 592).

  6. I return to this point in Sect. 3.3.

  7. Alasdair Houston documents a narrow and broad use of the term “spandrel” in biology (2009, p. 227). Where Gould and Lewontin characterize a spandrel as the “necessary byproduct” of an adaptation (Gould, 1997, p. 10, p. 754), George Williams adopts the less restricted view that a spandrel is a “structure arising as an incidental consequence of some evolutionary change” (1992, p. 78). This conception of spandrel as “accident” has also been endorsed by Dennett (1995, pp. 279–280). In the present case I employ the broad use of the term. Thus, in characterizing liquid tissue as a “spandrel,” I am not implying that it is a “necessary byproduct” of a certain mechanism of cellular cohesion, but merely an “accident” or “incidental consequence” of that mechanism relative to its selected effects.

  8. To be clear, while this interpretation is compatible with Newman’s plasticity-first account of early metazoan evolution, he makes no appeal to a “spandrel” or “side-effect” to disentangle the adaptive and incidental products of the toolkit genes. Thus, I cannot be sure if this interpretation would ultimately be met with his endorsement.

  9. I’m speaking loosely here. While, as a general rule, spatially and temporally proximal causal relationships tend to be more invariant, as Woodward points out, proximal causal relationships can lack invariance or be “sensitive” to interference and distal relationships can be relatively invariant (Woodward, 2010, pp. 294–295).

  10. Except for the Labridae fish family.

  11. This posit is a simplifying assumption. In fact, the decoupling is likely just another biomechanical side-effect of a different selected effect of a mutation.

References

  • Abedin, M., & Nicole King (2010). Diverse evolutionary paths to cell adhesion. Trends in Cell Biology, 20(12), 734–742. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tcb.2010.08.002

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alegado, R. A., Laura, W., Brown, S., Cao, R. K., Dermenjian, R., Zuzow, S. R., Fairclough, J., Clardy, & King, N. (2012). A bacterial sulfonolipid triggers multicellular development in the closest living relatives of animals. ELife 1 (October): e00013. https://doi.org/10.7554/eLife.00013

  • Altenberg, L. (1995). Genome growth and the evolution of the genotype-phenotype map. In W. Banzhaf & F. H. Eeckman (Eds.), Evolution and Biocomputation, (pp. 205–259). Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/3-540-59046-3_11

  • Arthur, W. (1997). The origin of animal body plans: A study in evolutionary developmental biology. Cambridge University Press

  • Badyaev, A. V. (2010). The beak of the other finch: Coevolution of genetic covariance structure and developmental modularity during adaptive evolution. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 365(1543), 1111–1126. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2009.0285

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boraas, M., Seale, D., & Boxhorn, J. (1998). Phagotrophy by a flagellate selects for colonial prey: A possible origin of multicellularity. Evolutionary Ecology, 12(2), 153–164. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1006527528063

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2007). Typology now: Homology and developmental constraints explain evolvability. Biology & Philosophy, 22(5), 709–725. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9089-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, R. L. (2014). What evolvability really is. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65(3), 549–572. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axt014

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brunet, T., Larson, B. T., Linden, T. A., Vermeij, M. J. A., McDonald K., & King, N. E. (2019). Light-regulated collective contractility in a multicellular choanoflagellate. Science, 366(6463), 326–334. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aay2346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cuénot, L. (1914). Théorie de préadaptation. Scientia, 16, 60–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1995). Darwin’s dangerous idea: Evolution and the meanings of life. Allen Lane

  • Eldredge, N., & Gould S. J. (1972). Punctuated equilibria: An alternative to phyletic gradualism. In Thomas J. M. Schopf (Ed.), Models in paleobiology, (pp. 82–115). Freeman, Cooper and Company

  • Eshel, I. & Matessi, C. (1998). Canalization, genetic assimilation and preadaptation: A quantitative genetic model. Genetics, 149(4), 2119–2133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fagan, M. B. (2012). Waddington redux: Models and explanation in stem cell and systems biology. Biology & Philosophy, 27(2), 179–213. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9294-y

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fernández, R., & Gabaldón, T. (2020). Gene gain and loss across the metazoan tree of life. Nature Ecology & Evolution, 4(4), 524–533. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41559-019-1069-x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma, D. J. (2013). Evolution. 3rd edition. Sinauer Associates (Oxford University Press)

  • Gibson, G., & Dworkin, I. (2004). Uncovering cryptic genetic variation. Nature Reviews Genetics, 5(9), 681–690. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrg1426

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1997). The exaptive excellence of spandrels as a term and prototype. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 94 (20), 10750–55. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.94.20.10750

  • Gould, S. J., & Lewontin, R. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B. Biological Sciences 205 (1161), 581–598. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.1979.0086

  • Griffiths, P. E., & Gray, R. D. (1994). Developmental systems and evolutionary explanation. The Journal of Philosophy, 91(6), 277–304. https://doi.org/10.2307/2940982

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guijarro-Clarke, C., Holland, P. W. H., & Jordi, P. (2020). Widespread patterns of gene loss in the evolution of the animal kingdom. Nature Ecology & Evolution, 4(4), 519–523. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41559-020-1129-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, T. F., & Pélabon, C. (2021). Evolvability: A quantitative-genetics perspective. Annual Review of Ecology Evolution and Systematics, 52(1), 153–175. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-ecolsys-011121-021241

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayden, E. J., Ferrada, E., & Wagner, A. (2011). Cryptic genetic variation promotes rapid evolutionary adaptation in an RNA enzyme. Nature, 474(7349), 92–95. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature10083

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herron, M. D., Borin, J. M., Boswell, J. C., Walker, J., Chen, I.-C. K., Knox, C. A., Boyd, M., Rosenzweig, F., & Ratcliff, W. C. (2019). De novo origins of multicellularity in response to predation. Scientific Reports, 9(1), 2328. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-019-39558-8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houston, A. I. (2009). San Marco and evolutionary biology. Biology & Philosophy, 24(2), 215. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-008-9141-y

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner, M., & Gerhart, J. (2006). The plausibility of life: Resolving Darwin’s dilemma. Cincias Biol-Gicas e edition. Yale University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumler, W. E., Jorge, J., Kim, P. M., Iftekhar, N., & Koehl, M. R. (2020). Does formation of multicellular colonies by choanoflagellates affect their susceptibility to capture by passive protozoan predators? Journal of Eukaryotic Microbiology, 67(5), 555–565. https://doi.org/10.1111/jeu.12808

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K., Odling-Smee, J., & Endler, J. (2017). Niche construction, sources of selection and trait coevolution. Interface Focus, 7(5), 20160147. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsfs.2016.0147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levis, N. A., & Pfennig, D. W. (2016). Evaluating ‘plasticity-first’ evolution in nature: Key criteria and empirical approaches. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 31(7), 563–574. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tree.2016.03.012

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewin, R. (1980). “Evolutionary Theory Under Fire.” Science, November. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.6107993

  • Lewis, D. (1986). Postscript C to ‘Causation’: (Insensitive Causation) Philosophical Papers, II vol., (pp. 184–188). Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Loison, L. (2019). Canalization and genetic assimilation: Reassessing the radicality of the waddingtonian concept of inheritance of acquired characters. Special issue ‘Canalization, a central concept in biology’, Seminars in Cell & Developmental Biology, 88, 4–13. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.semcdb.2018.05.009

  • Love, A. C. (2008). Explaining evolutionary innovations and novelties: Criteria of explanatory adequacy and epistemological prerequisites. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 874–886. https://doi.org/10.1086/594531

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A. C., & Lugar, G. L. (2013). Dimensions of integration in interdisciplinary explanations of the origin of evolutionary novelty. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 44 (4, Part A), 537–550. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2013.09.008

  • Masel, J. (2006). Cryptic genetic variation is enriched for potential adaptations. Genetics, 172(3), 1985–1991. https://doi.org/10.1534/genetics.105.051649

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moss, L., & Newman, S. (2016). The grassblade beyond Newton: The pragmatizing of Kant for evolutionary-developmental biology. https://doi.org/10.13130/2240-9599/6686

  • Müller, G. B. (1990). Developmental mechanisms at the origin of morphological novelty: A side-effect hypothesis. In M. H. Nitecki (Ed.), Evolutionary innovations , 1st edition, (pp. 99–130). University Of Chicago Press

  • Newman, S. (1995). Carnal boundaries: The commingling of flesh in theory and practice. In L. Birke, & R. Hubbard (Eds.), Reinventing biology: Respect for life and the creation of knowledge, (pp .191–227). Indiana University Press

  • Newman, S. (2004). In conversation: Four critics of biotech. Irish Pages, 2(2), 155–168

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman, S. (2016). Origination, variation, and conservation of animal body plan development. In Reviews in cell biology and molecular medicine, (pp. 130–162). American Cancer Society. https://doi.org/10.1002/3527600906.mcb.200400164.pub2

  • Newman, S. (2019a). Inherency of form and function in animal development and evolution. Frontiers in Physiology, 10, https://doi.org/10.3389/fphys.2019.00702

  • Newman, S. (2019b). Inherent forms and the evolution of evolution. Journal of Experimental Zoology Part B: Molecular and Developmental Evolution, 332(8), 331–338. https://doi.org/10.1002/jez.b.22895

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, S. (2020). The origins and evolution of animal identity. In A. S. Meincke, & J. Dupré Biological identity: Perspectives from metaphysics and the philosophy of biology, (pp. 128–148). Routledge

  • Newman, S., & Bhat, R. (2009). Dynamical patterning modules: A ‘Pattern Language’ for development and evolution of multicellular form. The International Journal of Developmental Biology, 53(5–6), 693–705. https://doi.org/10.1387/ijdb.072481sn

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, S., Forgacs, G., & Müller, G. (2003). Before programs: The physical origination of multicellular forms. International Journal of Developmental Biology, 50(2–3), 289–299. https://doi.org/10.1387/ijdb.052049sn

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S. (2000). Causal democracy and causal contributions in developmental systems theory. Philosophy of Science, 67, S332–S347

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paps, J., & Holland, P. W. H. (2018). Reconstruction of the ancestral metazoan genome reveals an increase in genomic novelty. Nature Communications, 9(1), 1730. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-018-04136-5

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, T., & Müller, G. B. (2016). Phenotypic novelty in EvoDevo: The distinction between continuous and discontinuous variation and its importance in evolutionary theory. Evolutionary Biology, 43(3), 314–335. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11692-016-9372-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, T., & Müller, G. B. (2018). Developmental finite element analysis of cichlid pharyngeal jaws: Quantifying the generation of a key innovation. Plos One, 13(1), e0189985. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0189985

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pfennig, D. W. (Ed.). (2021). Phenotypic plasticity & evolution: Causes, consequences, controversies. CRC Press

  • Pfennig, D. W., & Peter, J. M. (2000). Character displacement in polyphenic tadpoles. Evolution; International Journal of Organic Evolution, 54(5), 1738–1749. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0014-3820.2000.tb00717.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ros-Rocher, N., Pérez-Posada, A., Leger, M. M., & Iñaki, R. T. (2021). The origin of animals: An ancestral reconstruction of the unicellular-to-multicellular transition. Open Biology, 11(2), 1–21. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsob.200359

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Trillo, I., & Mendoza, A. (2020). Towards understanding the origin of animal development. Development, 147(23), dev192575. https://doi.org/10.1242/dev.192575

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rust, J. (2021). Von Baer, the intensification of uniqueness, and historical explanation. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 43(4), 122. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-021-00473-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, P. (1993). The organism and a dynamical system. In W. Stein, & F. J. Varela (Eds.), Thinking About Biology. CRC Press

  • Schmalhausen, I. (1949). Factors of evolution: The theory of stabilizing selection. (Translated by Theodosius Dobzhansky). Blakiston Co

  • Sebé-Pedrós, A., Degnan, B. M., & Iñaki, R. T. (2017). The origin of metazoa: A unicellular perspective. Nature Reviews Genetics, 18(8), 498–512. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrg.2017.21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sharov, A. A. (2014). Evolutionary constraints or opportunities? Biosystems, 123: 9–18. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biosystems.2014.06.004

  • Smith, J., Maynard, R., Burian, S., Kauffman, P., Alberch, J., Campbell, B., Goodwin, R., Lande, D., Raup, & Wolpert, L. (1985). Developmental constraints and evolution: A perspective from the mountain lake conference on development and evolution. The Quarterly Review of Biology 60 (3), 265–87. https://doi.org/10.1086/414425

  • Sober, E. (2014). The nature of selection: Evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. University of Chicago Press

  • Stanley, S. M. (1973). An ecological theory for the sudden origin of multicellular life in the late precambrian. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 70(5), 1486–1489

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2007). What is evolvability? In M. Matthen, & C. Stephens (Eds.), Philosophy of biology, (pp. 163–178). Handbook of the philosophy of science. North-Holland. https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-044451543-8/50011-3

  • Waddington, C. H. (1942). Canalization of development and the inheritance of acquired characters. Nature, 150(3811), 563–565. https://doi.org/10.1038/150563a0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waddington, C. H. (1956). Principles of embryology. MacMillan

    Google Scholar 

  • Waddington, C. H. (1957). The strategy of the genes. George Allen and Unwin

    Google Scholar 

  • Waddington, C. H. (1958). Theories of evolution. In S. A. Barnett (Ed.), A century of Darwin, (pp. 1–18). William Heinemann Ltd. http://archive.org/details/centuryofdarwin0000barn

  • Wagner, A. (2011). The origins of evolutionary innovations: A theory of transformative change in living systems. Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, G., & Altenberg, L. (1996). Perspective: Complex adaptations and the evolution of evolvability. Evolution, 50(3), 967–976. https://doi.org/10.2307/2410639

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, R. A., & Szathmáry, E. (2016). How can evolution learn? Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 31(2), 147–157. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tree.2015.11.009

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, R. A., Wagner, G. P., Pavlicev, M., Weinreich, D. M., & Mills, R. (2014). The evolution of phenotypic correlations and ‘developmental memory.’ Evolution, 68(4), 1124–1138. https://doi.org/10.1111/evo.12337

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M. J. (1989). Phenotypic plasticity and the origins of diversity. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 20(1), 249–278

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M. J. (2003). Developmental plasticity and evolution. 1st edition. Oxford University Press

  • West-Eberhard, M. J. (2021). Forward: A perspective on ‘plasticity.’ In D. W. Pfennig (Ed.), Phenotypic plasticity & evolution: Causes, consequences, controversies, (pp .ix–xxi). CRC Press

  • Wilkins, A. S. (2008). Waddington’s unfinished critique of neo-Darwinian genetics: Then and now. Biological Theory, 3(3), 224–232. https://doi.org/10.1162/biot.2008.3.3.224

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G. C. (1966). Adaptation and natural selection: A critique of some current evolutionary thought. Princeton University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G. C. (1992). Natural selection: Domains, levels, and challenges. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2010). Causation in biology: Stability, specificity, and the choice of levels of explanation. Biology & Philosophy, 25(3), 287–318. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-010-9200-z

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2021). Causation with a human face: Normative theory and descriptive psychology. Oxford University Press

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful for the especially insightful feedback I received from the two reviewers of this journal.

Funding

The author is grateful to Stetson University for providing financial support for this project in the form of a sabbatical leave.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

N/A.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joshua Rust.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest/Competing interests

N/A.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rust, J. Phenotype-first hypotheses, spandrels and early metazoan evolution. HPLS 44, 48 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-022-00531-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-022-00531-w

Keywords

Navigation