Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The Re-contextualization of the Patient: What Home Health Care Can Teach Us About Medical Decision-Making

  • Published:
HEC Forum Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article examines the role of context in the development and deployment of standards of medical decision-making. First, it demonstrates that bioethics, and our dominant standards of medical decision-making, developed out of a specific historical and philosophical environment that prioritized technology over the person, standardization over particularity, individuality over relationship and rationality over other forms of knowing. These forces de-contextualize the patient and encourage decision-making that conforms to the unnatural and contrived environment of the hospital. The article then explores several important differences between the home health care and acute care settings. Finally, it argues that the personalized, embedded, relational and idiosyncratic nature of the home is actually a much more accurate reflection of the context in which real people make real decisions. Thus, we should work to “re-contextualize” patients, in order that they might be better equipped to make decisions that harmonize with their real lives.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Research shows that sometimes it is, and, surprisingly, sometimes it isn’t. In fact, there is a growing ethnographic literature demonstrating that despite the best intentions of developers, home-based medical services and technologies can actually be quite disruptive to the “intimate, co-constitutive relationship between self and home” and the care recipients’ “embodied subjectivity” (Angus et al. 2005, p. 182; Dyck et al 2005, p. 176). An article by Bowden and Bliss (2008) reveals that the use of highly medicalized hospital beds in the homes of terminal cancer patients is far from “entirely benign and beneficial” (p. 561) and often represents the beginning of an unanticipated transformation in the patient’s experience of home.

  2. While in general the data demonstrate that remaining in one’s home while receiving healthcare has significant emotional and physical benefits (see Gilleard et al. 2007; Wiles et al. 2011; Chapin and Dobbs-Kepper 2001), this is sometimes not the case. See Jennifer Parks’ text No Place Like Home? (2003) for a discussion of how many home health care practices can be highly exploitative of both workers and patients.

  3. Of course, Kant and Rawls have a very specific understanding of what constitutes “rationality” (very simply, rationality is that which conforms to means-ends reasoning), one that neglects other versions of practical reason. MacIntyre claims (1988) that all conceptions of rationality are relative to a certain tradition, and to identify or use a particular conception independent of its tradition, as Rawls has, only confuses the conversation.

  4. I use the term radical individualism not necessarily to distinguish it significantly from individualism as the term is usually used (i.e., that the freedoms, goals and values of the individual are prioritized over and above those of collections of individuals or communities) but instead to emphasize that, according to this particular anthropology, this priority is fundamental and inherent.

  5. While this section focuses on standards of general medical decision-making, the influence of modern liberalism (specifically its emphasis on individualism) in standards of pediatric decision-making has been discussed in Salter (2014).

  6. Berger et al. critique the traditional hierarchy of standards (known wishes, substituted judgment, and best interests) saying that “many patients do not necessarily want their surrogates to follow their specific treatment preferences or to follow the standards sequentially but wish them to respond dynamically to actual clinical situations and to integrate both medical and nonmedical concerns” (p. 49) including concerns like minimizing emotional or financial burdens on family members. As an example of a situation that would likely defy the traditional hierarchy by giving preference to substituted judgment over known wishes, the authors imagine a surrogate decision maker stating that “I know that my wife wrote in her living will that under no circumstances would she want to be on a ventilator, but our son is returning from Iraq next week and I believe she would want to be kept alive to say goodbye” (p. 50).

  7. While it is not my goal in this article to actually engage in and deliberate about actual home health care ethics dilemmas, the interested reader might turn to the following resources: Parks (2003); Preto and Mitchell (2004); Ruddick (1994); Schaefer (2008).

  8. The American Cancer Society offers this question among several others on a list of things to consider when making a treatment decision. http://www.cancer.org/cancer/prostatecancer/detailedguide/prostate-cancer-treating-considering-options.

References

  • Aging in Place. Aging in place: Key ingredients. http://aginginplace.com/mini-2/key-ingredients/. Accessed 15 October 2014.

  • Angus, J., Knotos, P. C., Dyck, I., McKeever, P., & Poland, B. (2005). The personal significance of home: Habitus and the experience of receiving long-term home care. Sociology of Health & Illness, 27(2), 161–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arras, J., & Dubler, N. N. (1994). Bringing the hospital home: Ethical and social implications of high-tech home care. Hastings Center Report, 24(5), 19–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg, J., Applebaum, P., Lidz, C., & Parker, L. (2001). Informed consent: Legal theory and clinical practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berger, J., DeRenzo, E., & Schwartz, J. (2008). Surrogate decision making: Reconciling ethical theory and clinical practice. Annals of Internal Medicine, 149(1), 48–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowden, G., & Bliss, J. (2008). Does using a hospital bed have an impact on the meaning of home? British Journal Of Community Nursing, 13(12), 556–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chapin, R., & Dobbs-Kepper, D. (2001). Aging in place in assisted living: Philosophy vs. policy. The Gerontologist, 41(1), 43–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collopy, B., Dubler, N. N., Zuckerman, C., Crigger, B. J., & Campbell, C. (1990). The ethics of home care: Autonomy and accommodation. Hastings Center Report, 20(2), 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dyck, I., Kontos, P., Angus, J., & McKeever, P. (2005). The home as a site for long-term care: Meanings and management of bodies and spaces. Health & Place, 11(2), 173–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilleard, C., Hyde, M., & Higgs, P. (2007). The impact of age, place, aging in place and attachment to place on the well-being of the over-50s in England. Research on Aging, 29(6), 590–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Illich, I. (1976). Limits to medicine—medical nemesis: The expropriation of health. London: Boyars.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1993). Grounding for the metaphysics of morals, 3rd ed. J.W. Ellington (Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  • Kapp, M. (1995). Legal and ethical issues in home-based care. Journal of Gerontological Social Work, 24(3–4), 31–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaufman, S. R. (2005). And a time to die: How American hospitals shape the end of life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuczewski, M. (1996). Reconceiving the family: The process of consent in medical decision-making. Hastings Center Report, 26(2), 30–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lo, B. (2013). Resolving ethical dilemmas (5th ed.). Philadelphia: Lippincott, Williams and Wilkins.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1988). Whose justice? Which rationality?. South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, J. W., & Feingold, M. G. (1993). Using standard treatment protocols to manage costs and quality of hospital services. Hospital Technology Services, 12(7), 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1906). Utilitarianism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (1994). The therapy of desire: Theory and practice in Hellenistic ethics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. (2002). Autonomy and trust in bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parks, J. (2003). No place like home? Feminist ethics and home health care. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preto, N., & Mitchell, I. (2004). Ethical issues in home care: Summary and overview of presentations and discussions at the annual meeting of the Canadian Bioethics Society October 28–31, 2004. Resource document. Health Canada. http://www.hc-sc.gc.ca/hcs-sss/alt_formats/hpb-dgps/pdf/pubs/2004-ethi-homedomicile/2004-ethi-homedomicile-eng.pdf. Accessed 16 October 2014.

  • Quill, T., & Brody, H. (1996). Physician recommendation and patient autonomy: Finding a balance between physician power and patient choice. Annals of Internal Medicine, 125(9), 763–769.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999). Theory of justice (revised ed.). Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruddick, W. (1994). Transforming homes and hospitals. Hastings Center Report, 24(5), S11–S14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salter, E. K. (2014). Resisting the siren call of individualism in pediatric decision-making and the role of relational interests. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 39(1), 26–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. (1982). Liberalism and the limits of justice. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaefer, N. (2008). Ethical issues in home health. Featured article. ADVANCE Healthcare Network for Nurses. http://nursing.advanceweb.com/Article/Ethical-Issues-in-Home-Health-2.aspx. Accessed 16 October 2014.

  • Starr, P. (1982). The social transformation of American medicine: The rise of a sovereign profession in the making of a vast industry. New York: Basic Books Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tamm, M. (1999). What does a home mean and when does it cease to be a home? Disability and Rehabilitation, 21(2), 49–55.

  • Weisz, G. (2003). The emergence of medical specialization in the nineteenth century. Bulletin on the History of Medicine, 77(3), 536–575.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiles, J. L., Leibing, A., Guberman, N., Reeve, J., & Allen, R. (2011). The meaning of “ageing in place” to older people. The Gerontologist, 52(3), 357–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Erica K. Salter.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Salter, E.K. The Re-contextualization of the Patient: What Home Health Care Can Teach Us About Medical Decision-Making. HEC Forum 27, 143–156 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-015-9268-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-015-9268-6

Keywords

Navigation