Skip to main content
Log in

Ceteris Paribus and Ceteris Rectis Laws: Content and Causal Role

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper has three goals. The first goal is to work out the difference between literal ceteris paribus (cp) laws in the sense of “all others being equal” and ceteris rectis (cr) “laws” in the sense of “all others being right” (Sects. 2, 4). While cp laws involve a universal quantification, cr generalizations involve an existential quantification over the values of the remainder variables Z. As a result, the two differ crucially in their confirmability and lawlikeness. The second goal is to provide a classification of different kinds of cr generalizations (indefinite, definite and normic), including certain transition cases between cr generalizations and cp laws (Sect. 3). The third goal is to work out what cp laws and all kinds of cr assertions have in common: they figure as an information source for assertions of causal influence between variables (Sect. 5).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Barrow (1979, ch. 1.9 and fig. 1–8).

  2. The equivalence of a definite cr law with an ordinary law cannot be read off from its semantic content, but follows from the background knowledge to which the cr clause refers. So it is still appropriate to distinguish between a definite cr law and an ordinary law.

  3. That the gravitational force between two masses has the same spatial direction as their position difference holds in Newton’s law of gravitation and may fail in relativistic mechanics (s. French 2007, ch. 7.4); but Newton’s 2nd law and hence the monotonic cp relationship still holds.

  4. Roberts (2014) and Unterhuber (2014) defend the normic-statistical account. For objections see Nickel (2014) and Reutlinger (2014).

  5. More precisely, D is the set of possible outcomes of a random experiment, and P(Xa = x) is the limiting frequency of result x in an infinite random sequence of D-elements. As usual in statistical probability theory we define P over an algebra over D, P:Al(D)→[0,1]. In the literature on Bayes nets, P is usually defined over an algebra over the combined value space of given random variables, P: Al(⊗ Val) → [0,1], where ⊗ Val = def Val(X1) × ⋯ ×Val(Xn). The latter distribution function is recoverable from the former by the definition P(V1 ×⋯× Vn) = def P({d ∈ D: Xi(d) ∈ Vi, 1 ≤ i ≤ n}) (with Vi ⊆ Val(Xi)), provided the variables are measurable in the sense that for all V1 × ⋯ ×Vn ∈ Al(⊗ Val), {d ∈ D: Xi(d) ∈ Vi, 1 ≤ i ≤ n} ∈ Al(D). This is what we assume; so our definition coheres with the usual Bayes nets formalism.

  6. The distinction between laws i.b.s. and physical necessities is not consistently kept up in the literature. Most authors would agree that "all ravens are black" is lawlike (cf. Nagel 1977, 273) but not a physical necessity (cf. Armstrong 1983, 18).

  7. “X has a causal influence on Y conditional on Z = z” means that in the underlying causal model Y is a cause of X and DEP(X,Y|z) holds.

References

  • Albert, H., Arnold, D., & Maier-Rigaud, F. (2012). Model platonism: Neoclassical economic thought in critical light. Journal of Institutional Economics, 8(3), 293–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1983). What is a law of nature? Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barrow, G. M. (1979). Physical chemistry. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J., & Roberts, J. (1999). Ceteris paribus, there is no problem of provisos. Synthese, 118, 439–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1991). You can fool some of the people all of the time. Mind, 100, 19–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, A. P. (2007). Special relativity. New York: Taylor and Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1955). Fact, fiction and forecast. Cambridge/MA: Harvard Univ Press. 2005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joseph, G. (1980). The many sciences and the one world. Journal of Philosophy, 77(12), 773–790.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machlup, F. (1957). Professor Hick’s revision of demand theory. The American Economic Review, 47(1), 135–199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, A. (1890). Principles of economics (8th ed.). Macmillan: London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1977). Teleology revisited. Journal of Philosophy, 74(5), 261–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickel, B. (2014). The role of kinds in the semantics of Ceteris Paribus Laws, Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9638-5.

  • Pearl, J. (2009). Causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1956). The direction of time. Berkeley: Univ. of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reutlinger, A., Schurz, G., & Hüttemann, A. (2011). “Ceteris Paribus laws”, The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ceteris-paribus.

  • Reutlinger, A. (2014). “Do Statistical Laws Solve the ‘Problem of Provisos’?”, Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9640-y.

  • Roberts, J. (2014). CP-law statements as vague, self-referential, self-locating, statistical, and perfectly in order. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9641-x.

  • Schurz, G. (2001). What is ‘normal’? An evolution-theoretic foundation of normic laws. Philosophy of Science, 28, 476–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2002). Ceteris paribus laws: Classification and deconstruction. Erkenntnis, 57(3), 351–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2014). Philosophy of science: A unified view. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., & Scheines, R. (2000). Causation, prediction, and search. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth. An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge: Harvard Univ Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unterhuber, M. (2014). Do ceteris paribus laws exist? A regularity-based best system analysis, Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9645-6.

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. New York: Oxford Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For valuable discussion I am grateful to Nancy Cartwright, Alexander Gebharter, Andreas Hüttemann, Bernhard Nickel, Jeff Pelletier, Alexander Reutlinger, Jonah Schupbach, Wolfgang Spohn, Michael Strevens, Paul Thorn and Matthias Unterhuber.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gerhard Schurz.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of the equivalence of “DEP” and “Cr” stated in (17)

DEP  Cr: If (for some given x, y, z) P(y|x, z) ≠ P(y|z), then by probability theory there must also exist a y*∈Val(Y) such that P(y*|x,z) > P(y*|z). By letting Δx = {x} and Δz = {z} this implies an cr assertion of the form (13)(i) (with empty C).

Cr  DEP: Assume “Cr”, i.e. for some Δy, Δx and Δz, P(Y ∈ Δy | X ∈ Δx, Z ∈ Δz) > P(Y ∈ Δy|Z ∈ Δz). Y ∈ Δy is equivalent with an exclusive disjunction Y ∈ y1 \( \dot{ \vee } \) ··· \( \dot{ \vee } \)Y ∈ yn; and likewise for X ∈ Δx and Z ∈ Δz. By probability theory, P(A1 \( \dot{ \vee } \)A2|B1 \( \dot{ \vee } \)B2) > P(A1 \( \dot{ \vee } \)A2) implies that P(A1|B1) > P(A1) or P(A2|B2) > P(A2) or P(A1|B2) > P(A1) or P(A2|B1) > P(A2). By generalizing this result to n-fold disjunctions one derives from “Cr”: ∃x,y,z: P(Y = y|X = x, Z = z) > P(Y = y|Z = z); i.e. DEP(X,Y|Z).□

Proof of theorem (18)

By (17), the cr-claim in (18) is equivalent with “DEP(X,Y|Z)”. If (V,E,P) satisfies the causal Markov condition (cMC), then (V,E,P) satisfies the following principle (D) of “d-connection”:

(D) For all X,Y∈V and Z ⊆ V − {X,Y}: If DEP(X,Y|Z), then X and Y are connected by some path π such that no intermediate cause Z (Z’ → Z→ Z’’) or common cause Z (Z’ ← Z→ Z’’) on π is in Z, and every common effect Z on π (Z’ → Z ← Z’’) is in Z or has an effect in Z.

This is a consequence of the first part of theorem 1.2.4 in Pearl (2009, 18).

For (18.1): By (D), DEP(X,Y|Z) entails that

(*) there exists a path π = X − C1 − ··· − Cn − Y (with n ≥ 0) such that no common or intermediate cause Ci on this path π is in Z, and every common effect on π is in Z.

By our assumption,

(**) Z contains all and only the non-effects of X in V − {X,Y}.

We have two cases:

Case (1): If X − Y holds, then X → Y and Y → X are compatible with (*) and (**).

Case (2): X − C1 − ··· −Cn − Y holds for n ≥ 1.

Step (a): Then for no Ci (1 ≤ i ≤ n), X − ···←Ci −− Y can hold in E, for then Ci would be a non-effect of X and a common or intermediate cause on path π, which by (*) must not be in Z. But this contradicts (**).

Step (b): By step (a), X → C1 →→ Cn − Y must hold.

Step (c): X →→ Cn ← Y cannot hold, since then Cn would be an effect of X and a common effect on π, which by (*) must be in Z, in contradiction of (**). Therefore in case (2), X →→ Y must hold.

For (18.2): This is an obvious consequence of (18.1), since t(X) < t(Y) and the assumption that causal arrows are forward-directed in time precludes the second possibility X ← Y.

For (18.3): Spirtes et al. (2000, 50) define an intervention variable (“policy variable”) IX for X as a direct cause of X which not connected with any other variable in V. So if the second possibility of (18.1), X ← Y, would hold, the causal structure would be IX → X ← Y; but then by (D) and since IX is not connected with any other variable in V, DEP(IX,Y) could not hold.□

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schurz, G. Ceteris Paribus and Ceteris Rectis Laws: Content and Causal Role. Erkenn 79 (Suppl 10), 1801–1817 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9643-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9643-8

Keywords

Navigation