Skip to main content
Log in

The logic of coherence

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

To remedy the lack of precision attached to the concept of coherence, a plethora of probabilistic measures has been developed. To broaden the perspective, we do not focus on the differences between these quantitative but the differences between qualitative approaches to coherence by comparing three probabilistic definitions for the relation denoted by ‘coheres with’. To reveal the different logics underlying these relations, we introduce a considerable number of formal properties and examine whether the given coherence relations possess them. Among these properties are not only the classics reflexivity, symmetry and transitivity, but also a variety of features that concern propositions containing negation, conjunction and disjunction, as well as features that concern inconsistency, entailment and equivalence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Such a relation must not be confused with the binary coherence relation that is in the focus of Bovens and Hartmann’s (2003, chs. 1.4 and 2.2) account. Bovens and Hartmann are interested in the relation ‘is no less coherent than’, while we are interested in ‘coheres with’. Even if the latter relation’s scope is extended to sets of propositions, these relations remain independent of each other. For a set that is no less coherent than another set need not cohere with it, and a set that coheres with another set need not be no less coherent than it.

  2. Cf. Achinstein’s (2001, chs. 3f.) discussion of these three approaches to confirmation.

  3. In the last resort, it is possible to add the constraint that coherence relations obtain between x and y only if xy. This would merely entail that reflexivity is no longer among the possible properties of these relations. Note also that, to model cases of identical contents in a set-theoretical manner, one may draw on multisets because they can contain the same proposition more than one time.

  4. As shown by Schippers (2014), there are nonetheless screening-off conditions that guarantee transitivity for each of the above relations.

  5. The former constraint is sometimes labelled “cautious monotonicity’ (cf. Huber 2007).

  6. It has also been argued that logically equivalent propositions are maximally coherent (cf. Fitelson 2003; Siebel and Wolff 2008; contrast Olsson and Schubert 2007). Since we are interested in coherence only from a qualitative perspective, we will not dwell on this and related issues.

References

  • Achinstein, P. (2001). The book of evidence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Akiba, K. (2000). Shogenji’s probabilistic measure of coherence is incoherent. Analysis, 60, 356–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovens, L., & Hartmann, S. (2003). Bayesian epistemology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1962). Logical foundations of probability (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crupi, V., & Tentori, K. (2015). Confirmation theory. In A. Hájek & C. Hitchcock (Eds.), Oxford handbook of philosophy and probability. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2011). Further results on the intransitivity of evidential support. Review of Symbolic Logic, 4, 487–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I., & Meijs, W. (2007). Measuring coherence. Synthese, 156, 405–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (1992). Bayes or bust? A critical examination of Bayesian confirmation theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson, B. (1999). Studies in Bayesian confirmation theory. Ph.D. thesis, University of Wisconsin-Madison.

  • Fitelson, B. (2003). A probabilistic theory of coherence. Analysis, 63, 194–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson, B. (2004). Two technical corrections to my coherence measure. http://www.fitelson.org/coherence2.pdf. Accessed 29 Jan 2020.

  • Glass, D. H. (2002). Coherence, explanation, and Bayesian networks. In M. O’Neill et al. (Eds.), 13th Irish international conference (Proceedings) on artificial intelligence and cognitive science (pp. 177–182). Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer.

  • Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (2006). Scientific reasoning. The Bayesian approach (3rd ed.). Chicago and La Salle, Illinois: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huber, F. (2007). The logic of theory assessment. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 36, 511–538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C. I. (1946). An analysis of knowledge and valuation. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meijs, W. (2006). Coherence as generalized logical equivalence. Erkenntnis, 64, 231–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E. J. (2002). What is the problem of coherence and truth? Journal of Philosophy, 94, 246–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E. J., & Schubert, S. (2007). Reliability conducive measures of coherence. Synthese, 157, 297–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roche, W. (2013). Coherence and probability. A probabilistic account of coherence. In M. Araszkiewicz & J. Savelka (Eds.), Coherence: Insights from philosophy, jurisprudence and artificial intelligence (pp. 59–91). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Roche, W., & Shogenji, T. (2014). Confirmation, transitivity, and Moore: the screening-off approach. Philosophical Studies, 168, 797–817.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schippers, M. (2014). Structural properties of qualitative and quantitative accounts to coherence. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 7, 579–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schippers, M., & Siebel, M. (2015). Inconsistency as a touchstone for coherence measures. Theoria, 30, 11–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schupbach, J. N. (2011). New hope for Shogenji’s coherence measure. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 125–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shogenji, T. (1999). Is coherence truth conducive? Analysis, 59, 338–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shogenji, T. (2003). A condition for transitivity in probabilistic support. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54, 613–616.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siebel, M. (2004). On Fitelson’s measure of coherence. Analysis, 64, 189–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siebel, M., & Wolff, W. (2008). Equivalent testimonies as a touchstone of coherence measures. Synthese, 161, 167–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

This study was supported by Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (Grant Number SI 1731/1-1).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

(REF):

\( P(x|x) \) = 1, and \( P(x|{\bar{x}}) \) = \( P({\bar{x}}|x) \) = 0. Hence, the definientia of (IC), (AC) and therefore also (SC) are satisfied.

(SYM):

(AC), (IC) and thus also (SC) require bidirectional confirmation in random order.

(TRA):

This is a straightforward consequence of the fact that the underlying accounts of confirmation are not transitive (cf. Douven 2011; Roche and Shogenji 2014; Shogenji 2003).

(INC):

\( P(x|x) \) = \( P({\bar{x}}|{\bar{x}}) \) = 1, and \( P(x|{\bar{x}}) \) = \( P({\bar{x}}|x) \) = 0. Hence, since x and \( {\bar{x}} \) are contingent and the probability function P is regular, \( P(x|{\bar{x}}) \) < P(x) < \( P(x|x) \) and \( P({\bar{x}}|x) \) < P(\( {\bar{x}} \)) < \( P({\bar{x}}|{\bar{x}}) \). The definientia of (IC) and (AC), and thus also (SC), are therefore violated.

(INC′):

If x ⊥ y, then \( P(x|y) \) = \( P(y|x) \) = 0. Hence, \( P(x|y) \) < P(x) and \( P(x|y) \) < \( P(x|\bar{y}) \), as well as \( P(y|x) \) < P(y) and \( P(y|x) \) < \( P(y|{\bar{x}}) \). That is, the definientia of (IC) and (AC), and thus also (SC), are again violated.

(NSC):

First, if x ~i y, then \( P(x|y) \) > P(x), which is for all contingent propositions equivalent to \( P(\bar{y}|{\bar{x}}) \) > \( P(\bar{y}) \). Analogously, \( P(y|x) \) > P(y) is equivalent to \( P({\bar{x}}|\bar{y}) \) > P(\( {\bar{x}} \)). Thus, if x ~i y, then also \( {\bar{x}} \) ~i \( \bar{y} \), in order that ~i satisfies (NSC). Secondly, probability distribution P1 in Table 6 shows that neither ~s nor ~a satisfies (NSC). According to this distribution, \( P_{1} (x|y) \) ≈ .731 > .637 ≈ P1(x) > .5, and \( P_{1} (y|x) \) ≈ .812 > .707 ≈ P1(y) > .5. Hence, x ~s y and therefore x ~a y. However, \( P_{1} (\bar{y}|{\bar{x}}) \) ≈ .477 < .5 and hence neither \( {\bar{x}} \) ~a \( \bar{y} \) nor \( {\bar{x}} \) ~s \( \bar{y} \).

Table 6 Probability distributions for pairs of propositions
(CON):

If x ~s y, then \( P(y|x) \) > P(y) and \( P(y|x) \) > \( P(\bar{y}|x) \). Hence, \( P(\bar{y}|x) \) < \( P(\bar{y}) \) and \( P(\bar{y}|x) \) < \( P(y|{\bar{x}}) \)}, and therefore xi \( \bar{y} \) and xa \( \bar{y} \) and thus also xs \( \bar{y} \).

(CON′):

Consider probability distribution P6 in Table 7. Here \( P_{6}(x|y) \) = 1 > .5 = P6(x) and \( P_{6}(y|x) \) = .5 > .25 = P6(y); hence, x ~i y. Furthermore, \( P_{6}(z|x) \) = .5 > .25 = P6(z) and \( P_{6}(x|z) \) = 1 > .5 = P6(x), so that also x ~i z. Nonetheless, y ⊥ z because P6(y ∧ z) = 0, with the result that ~i violates (CON′). On the other hand, if x ~a y, then \( P(y|x) \) > .5 and hence \( P(\bar{y}|x) \) ≤ .5. Hence, since \( P(\bar{y}|x) \) = P(\( \bar{y} \) ∧ \( z|x \)) + P(\( \bar{y} \) ∧ \( \bar{z}|x \)), P(\( \bar{y} \) ∧ \( z|x \)) ≤ .5. Finally, since yz, z implies \( \bar{y} \), in order that P(\( \bar{y} \) ∧ \( z|x \)) = \( P(z|x) \) ≤ .5. That is, xa z and xs z, entailing that both relations satisfy (CON′).

Table 7 Probability distributions for triples of propositions, where ai = 1 − Pi(x ∨ y ∨ z)
(WAC):

As to incremental coherence, since P is regular and x is contingent, P(\( x|x \) ∧ y) = 1 > P(x). Due to the symmetry of incremental confirmation, it also holds that P(x ∧ \( y|x \)) > P(x ∧ y); hence, x ~i x ∧ y. As to absolute coherence, since P is regular and x is contingent, P(\( x|x \) ∧ y) = 1 > P(\( {\bar{x}}|x \) ∧ y). Moreover, P(x ∧ \( y|x \)) = \( P(y|x) \) and P(\( \overline{x \wedge y} |x \)) = P(\( {\bar{x}} \) ∨ \( \bar{y}|x \)) = \( P(\bar{y}|x) \). Since x ~a y, we also get \( P(y|x) \) > \( P(\bar{y}|x) \), so that P(x ∧ \( y|x \)) = \( P(y|x) \) > \( P(\bar{y}|x) \) = P(\( \overline{x \wedge y} |x \)). Hence, x ~a x ∧ y. Therefore, all three accounts satisfy (WAC).

(WOC):

As to incremental coherence, since P is regular and x is contingent, P(x ∨ \( y|x \)) = 1 > P(x). Due to the symmetry of incremental confirmation, we thus get x ~i x ∨ y. As to absolute coherence, P(x ∨ \( y|x \)) = 1 > 0 = P(\( \overline{x \vee y} |x \)). Furthermore, since x ~a y, \( P(x|y) \) > \( P({\bar{x}}|y) \), and therefore P(x ∧ y) > P(\( {\bar{x}} \) ∧ y). Hence, P(x) = P(x ∧ y) + P(x ∧ \( \bar{y} \)) > P(\( {\bar{x}} \) ∧ y) + P(x ∧ \( \bar{y} \)) > P(\( {\bar{x}} \) ∧ y). Consequently, P(\( x|x \) ∨ y) = P(x)/P(x ∨ y) > P(\( {\bar{x}} \) ∧ y)/P(x ∨ y) = P(\( {\bar{x}}|x \) ∨ y). This means that x ~a x ∨ y and x ~s x ∨ y, so that all three accounts satisfy (WOC).

(WCC):

According to probability distribution P2 in Table 6, P2(x ∧ \( y|x \)) ≈ .516 > .5 > .188 ≈ P2(x ∧ y), and P2(\( x|x \) ∧ y) = 1 > .5 > P2(x). Hence, x ~i x ∧ y and x ~a x ∧ y, so that also x ~s x ∧ y. However, P2(\( x|y \)) ≈ .353 < 0.363 ≈ P2(x) < .5. Therefore, neither x ~i y nor x ~a y, entailing that x ~s y does not hold, too.

(WCD):

Consider again distribution P2. P2(\( x|x \) ∨ y) ≈ .514 > .5 > .363 ≈ P2(x), and P2(x ∨ \( y|x \)) = 1 > .707 ≈ P2(x ∨ y) > .5. Thus, x ~i x ∨ y and x ~a x ∧ y, implying that also x ~s x ∨ y But since P2(\( x|y \)) < P2(x) < .5, x and y are assessed incoherent on all three accounts.

(EOC):

Since x is contingent and P is regular, P(\( x|x \) ∧ y) = 1 > P(x). Therefore, by the symmetry of incremental confirmation, P(x ∧ \( y|x \)) > P(x ∧ y), in order that ~i satisfies (EOC). On the other hand, as is shown by distribution P3 in Table 6, there are situations in which P3(x ∧ \( y|x \)) = P3(x ∧ \( y|y \)) ≈ .332 < P3(x ∧ y) ≈ 0.147 < .5. Hence, neither x ~ x ∧ y nor y ~ x ∧ y for either ~a or ~s.

(EOD):

Since x ∨ y is contingent and P is regular, P(x ∨ \( y|x \)) = 1 > P(x ∨ y). Hence, by symmetry also P(\( x|x \) ∨ y) > P(x), entailing that x ~i x ∨ y. But distribution P4 in Table 6 proves possible that P(\( x|x \) ∨ y) = P(\( y|x \) ∨ y) = .5, so that neither x ~ x ∨ y nor y ~ x ∨ y for either ~a or ~s.

(CSC):

Consider probability distribution P7 in Table 7. P7(\( x|y \)) ≈ .165 > .163 ≈ P7(x), in order that by symmetry x ~i y. However, P7(x ∧ \( z|y \) ∧ z) ≈ .003 < .006 ≈ P7(x ∧ z), implying that x ∧ z ~i y ∧ z does not hold. Furthermore, according to distribution P8 in the same table, P8(\( x|y \)) ≈ .613 > .5 > .419 ≈ P8(x) and P8(\( y|x \)) = 1 > .684 ≈ P8(y) > .5; therefore x ~s y. But P8(x ∧ \( z|y \) ∧ z) ≈ .333 < .5, with the result that both ~a and ~s violate (CSC).

(DWC):

To show that ~a satisfies (DWC), assume that x ∨ za y ∨ z because P(x ∨ \( z|y \) ∨ z) = P(x ∧ y ∧ \( z|y \) ∨ z) + P(x ∧ y ∧ \( \bar{z}|y \) ∨ z) + P(x ∧ \( \bar{y} \) ∧ \( z|y \) ∨ z) + P(\( {\bar{x}} \) ∧ y ∧ \( z|y \) ∨ z) + P(\( {\bar{x}} \) ∧ \( \bar{y} \) ∧ \( z|y \) ∨ z) ≤ .5. Since P(x ∧ \( \bar{y} \) ∧ \( \bar{z}|y \) ∨ z) = P(\( {\bar{x}} \) ∧ \( \bar{y} \) ∧ \( \bar{z}|y \) ∨ z) = 0, this implies that the remaining probability P(\( {\bar{x}} \) ∧ y ∧ \( \bar{z}|y \) ∨ z) > .5. Hence, P(\( {\bar{x}} \) ∧ y ∧ \( \bar{z}|y \)) ≥ P(\( {\bar{x}} \) ∧ y ∧ \( \bar{z}|y \) ∨ z) > .5. But this entails that P(x ∧ y ∧ \( z|y \)) + P(x ∧ y ∧ \( \bar{z}|y \)) = \( P(x|y) \) ≤ .5, so that xa y. Since an analogous argument applies if x ∨ za y ∨ z because P(y ∨ \( z|x \) ∨ z) ≤ .5, ~a satisfies (DWC). Furthermore, distribution P7 in Table 7 proves that ~i does not meet this constraint. Here, x ~i y but P7(x ∨ \( z|y \) ∨ z) ≈ .730 < .732 ≈ P7(x ∨ z), so that x ∨ zi y ∨ z. One can easily find similar distributions showing that ~s also violates (DWC).

(CMC):

We have seen that (CSC) is violated by all coherence relations, that is, it is possible that x ~ y but x ∧ zy ∧ z. Since reflexivity implies that z ~ z, it is also possible that x ~ y and z ~ z but x ∧ zy ∧ z. Hence, if z′ = z, then it is possible that x ~ y and z ~ z′ while x ∧ z ~ y ∧ z′. Hence, (CMC) is also violated by all coherence relations.

(DMC):

By analogy with (CMC), the fact that ~s and ~i violate (DWC) entails that they also violate (DMC). To show that, although ~a satisfied (DWC), it does not satisfy (DMC), let y be \( \bar{y} \), z be y and z′ be \( {\bar{x}} \), and assume that x ~a \( \bar{y} \) and y ~a \( {\bar{x}} \). Probability distribution P9 in Table 7 provides an example because all relevant conditional probabilities for these pairs equal 1. However, it is clearly not the case that x ∨ y ~a \( \bar{y} \) ∨ \( {\bar{x}} \).

(LAC):

Probability distribution P10 in Table 7 shows that none of the coherence relations satisfies (LAC). P10(\( x|z \)) ≈ .586 > .555 ≈ P10(x) > .5, P10(\( z|x \)) ≈ .581 > .551 ≈ P10(z) > .5, P10(\( y|z \)) ≈ .619 > .587 ≈ P10(y) > .5 and P10(\( z|y \)) ≈ .580 > .551 ≈ P10(z) > .5. Hence, x ~s z and y ~s z. However, P10(x ∧ \( y|z \)) ≈ .450 < .480 ≈ P10(x ∧ \( y|z \)) < .5. Therefore, neither x ∧ y ~i z nor x ∧ y ~a z, and a fortiori not x ∧ y ~s z.

(LOC):

An example showing that none of the accounts satisfies (LOC) is given by probability distribution P11. P11(\( x|z \)) ≈ .535 > .532 ≈ P11(x) > .5, P11(\( z|x \)) ≈ .501 > .5 > .498 ≈ P11(z), P11(\( y|z \)) ≈ .531 > .527 ≈ P11(y) > .5 and P11(\( z|y \)) ≈ .502 > .5 > .498 ≈ P11(z). Accordingly, x ~s z and y ~s z. But P11(\( z|x \) ∨ y) ≈ .493 < .498 ≈ P11(z) < .5. Hence, it is not the case that x ∨ y ~ z for each of the three accounts.

(RAC):

Due to the symmetry of the coherence relations, (RAC) is equivalent to (LAC).

(ROC):

Due to the symmetry of the coherence relations, (ROC) is equivalent to (LOC).

(LLE):

This is a straightforward consequence of the fact that the laws governing probability are not affected when propositions are replaced by equivalent propositions.

(LRE):

Ditto.

(CEQ):

If x and y are equivalent, then \( P(x|y) \) and \( P(y|x) \) equal 1 and are thus smaller than .5. Moreover, since x and y are contingent and P is regular, it is also entailed that \( P(x|y) \) > \( P({\bar{x}}|y) \) and \( P(y|x) \) > \( P(\bar{y}|x) \). Hence, x ~ y for all three relations.

(CEN):

If x entails y, then \( P(y|x) \) = 1. Hence, since y is contingent and P is regular, it is also implied that \( P(y|x) \) > P(y). By symmetry we obtain \( P(x|y) \) > P(x), with the result that x ~i y. On the other hand, consider probability distribution P5 in Table 6. Here x entails y because P5(\( y|x \)) = 1 with x and y being contingent. However, P5(\( x|y \)) = 1/9, so that neither x ~a y nor x ~s y.

(LMO):

According to probability distribution P12 from Table 7, P12(\( x|y \)) ≈ .798 > .5 > .474 ≈ P12(x) and P12(\( y|x \)) ≈ .604 > .5 > .359 ≈ P12(y). Therefore, x ~ y for all three coherence relations. Furthermore, y ⊢ z because P12(\( z|y \)) = 1 with z and y being contingent. However, x ~ z holds for no relation because P12(\( x|z \)) ≈ .352 < .474 ≈ P12(x) < .5.

(RMO):

Consider probability distribution P13. P13(\( x|y \)) = 1 > .751 > .5 ≈ P13(x) and P13(\( y|x \)) ≈ .670 > .503 ≈ P13(y) > .5. Hence, x ~ y on all three accounts. Moreover, z ⊢ x because P12(\( x|z \)) = 1 with x and z being contingent. Nonetheless, we have P13(\( y|z \)) = 0 < .5 < .503 ≈ P13(y), implying that y ~ z obtains for none of the accounts.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schippers, M., Siebel, M. The logic of coherence. Synthese 198, 7697–7714 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02542-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02542-1

Keywords

Navigation