Skip to main content
Log in

First-Person Perspective in Experience: Perspectival De Se Representation as an Explanation of the Delimitation Problem

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In developing a theory of consciousness, one of the main problems has to do with determining what distinguishes conscious states from non-conscious ones—the delimitation problem. This paper explores the possibility of solving this problem in terms of self-awareness. That self-awareness is essential to understanding the nature of our conscious experience is perhaps the most widely discussed hypothesis in the study of consciousness throughout the history of philosophy. Its plausibility hinges on how the notion of self-awareness is unpacked. The idea that consciousness involves self-awareness has been understood in two different ways: either as awareness of oneself—the subject of experience—or as awareness of the conscious episode itself. In this paper I argue (i) that every experience concerns the subject in a very specific way, involving what I will call ‘perspectival de se representation’, and (ii) that there is no need to appeal to the experience itself in order to characterize the awareness within that experience. The view I articulate explains the subjective nature of experience without over-intellectualizing it, accommodates the phenomenology of experience, and dispels any doubt about the need to find the self in introspection.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See for example Byrne (2001), Carruthers (2000), Chalmers (2004), Dretske (1995), Kriegel (2002), Horgan and Tierson (2002), Siewert (1998)) or Tye (2002) for arguments in favor of the supervenience of phenomenal content in phenomenology. Cf. Block (1990) and Speaks (2009).

  2. Different versions thereof have been offered, for example in Dretske (1995), Kriegel (2009b), Rosenthal (2005) and Tye (1997).

  3. There is a disagreement in the literature about the kind of properties or objects that constitute the primary object of experience:

    For example, whether they are low-level ones, perhaps like shape or color (Tye, 1997; Dretske, 1995), or also higher-level ones such as being an apple (Block, 2014; Di Bona, 2017; Peacocke, 1995; Siegel, 2010), or whether we represent particulars or abstract entities in experience—see Schellenberg (2018) for a recent discussion. One might also think that rather than the apple and its properties, the primary objects of experience are mental properties, which are ‘copies’ (Hume, 2008), or that they “mirror somehow” (Rosenthal, 2015) the alleged perceptible properties. We can abstract away from this interesting debate for the purpose of this paper.

  4. Cf. Block (2016), Peters et al. (2016) and Phillips (2016).

  5. This presentation merely sketches the problem and the rebuttal of the functionalist strategy requires further development that cannot be carried out here. It suffices nonetheless for the main purpose of the paper, which is to explore the pure representationalist strategy.

  6. The idea that some form or another of self-awareness is constitutive of our conscious experience has been endorsed at some point for example by Dignaga, Dharmakirti, Shantarakshita, Mi Pham Gyatso and Sankara in Eastern Philosophy; by Aristotle, Chrysippus (the Stoic), and Carneades (the Skeptic) in Ancient Western Philosophy; by Descartes, Locke, Cudworth, Arnauld, Ried, and Kant in Early Modern Philosophy; by Fichte, Hegel, Novalis, Hölderlin, Schleiermacher and Kierkegaard in the 19th Century; by Meinong, Gurwitsch, Levinas, Cramer and Pothast in the 20th Century; by most, if not all phenomenologists such as Husserl, Heidegger, Sartre and Merleau-Ponty; and by Castañeda, Chisholm, Frank, Frankfurt, Goldman, Kapitan, Kriegel, Kripke, Rosenthal, Weisberg, Williford and Zahavi more recently.

  7. Altered states, such as those involving meditation or drugs, and pathological cases, like depersonalization or thought insertion, have been presented as a challenge to the strategy that I explore in this paper. It is not possible to deal with the details of these different cases within the reasonable length of a single paper. I have discussed the empirical evidence derived from altered states elsewhere (Sebastián, 2020).

  8. For example, Kriegel (2009b) and Williford (2006, 2015) endorse MSI; Sebastián (2012, 2018) endorses SI; and Zahavi (2005) SI + MSI. Different versions of Higher-Order Theories (Brown, 2015; Carruthers, 2003; Gennaro, 2012; Rosenthal, 2005; Weisberg, 2011b) can be read as endorsing one position or another depending on the details with regard to the content of the higher-order awareness and the relation between such awareness and phenomenology—see Sect. 4.

  9. Two experiences have the same phenomenology just in case they are phenomenally indistinguishable in ideal conditions –abstracting away from the discriminatory limitations we might have. This raises interesting questions regarding interpersonal indistinghuishability (Shoemaker, 1996; Stalnaker, 2000). However, even Stalnaker (2000), who questions the coherence of interpersonal indistinguishability, acknowledges that the intuition that at least physical duplicates undergo experiences with the same phenomenology is very hard to resist. The vast majority of theories have more relaxed constraints on the requisites that two individuals must satisfy to have experiences with the same phenomenology.

  10. Schellenberg (2018) holds a representationalist position and rejects the entailment. She thinks that veridical perceptions and hallucinations differ in content, and she accounts for the common phenomenology in terms of their contents belonging to the same content-kind. However, Schellenberg’s content-kinds play the same theoretical roles that content plays on other theories [See Torre’s (2018 pp. 183–184) discussion of the relation between Perry’s belief states and content. Beliefs states are analogous to the capacities that individuate Schellenberg’s content-kinds]. If this is correct, her rejection of the entailment between phenomenology and content is merely due to a mere choice in terminology.

  11. Through the influence of Kant in Husserl, SI-self-awareness is brought into the phenomenological tradition (Husserl, 1998; Zahavi, 2005). However, some phenomenologists, like Sartre, have favored MSI views—see next section.

  12. Fichte suggests an immediate acquaintance with ourselves to explain such pre-reflective self-awareness. A similar idea is also suggested, for example, by Frege (1997), early writtings of Russell (1910), or Kripke (2011) more recently.

  13. The details of the relation will depend on what one takes the POE to be; see fn.3.

  14. See e.g. Cappelen and Dever (2013), García-Carpintero (2017), Ninan (2016), Magidor (2015) and Torre (2018).

  15. For a recent review see Morgan and Salje (2020).

  16. Perry (1979) distinguishes the content of the thought from the thought-state through which such a content is accessed. In such a case the thought-state also contributes to what is conveyed by the representation which is what I have called ‘content’. Torre (2018) argues that Perry’s thought-states are indeed a form of content.

  17. Lewis famously argues that de se subsumes de dicto; for any possible world proposition can be reduced to a centered world proposition such that the center is irrelevant to its truth value. First-person representations involve what Egan (2006b) calls ‘interesting centered worlds’; i.e., those that do not “include, for each world w, either all of the positions in w or none of them” (ibid. 112).

  18. Note that this is consistent with the possibility that individuals differ about the ways in which they can exploit that information, or about the knowledge that they can thereby acquire–if, for example, knowledge depends also on the concepts that one possesses and they possess different concepts. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for pressing me on this point.

  19. It is worth stressing that the argument shows that phenomenal content is perspectival de se, not that any de se representation is perspectival. See below.

  20. In perspectival de se representation the pole is a subject, but there can be perspectival representations with a different kind of pole. For example the contents of the sentences ’there is an apple here’ or ’it is raining now’, if they were to be read as being portable and not global, would be true or false depending not only of the world but also on a location and a time within the world. We can call this kind of contents perspectival ‘de hinc’ and ‘de nunc’.

  21. An anonymous referee has suggested to me the possibility of capturing this in terms of the attitude rather than in terms of the content. A possibility that might make jeopardize the idea that this is a pure representationalist approach to the delimitation problem. This seems to be a terminological dispute regarding how to use the technical term ‘content’. I am characterizing awareness in experience solely in terms of content, and hence my use includes as part of it what others might call ‘attitude’ or ‘manner of representation’—in so far as they make a difference in the information that the state conveys. For example, authors like Chalmers (2004) or Egan (2006a) consider the possibility that experiences in different modalities concern exclusively the same POE and that differences in phenomenology are captured in terms of the attitude—e.g. seeing rather than touching—, calling this form of representation “impure”. Leaving aside whether there is really any good reasons to appeal to something like an attitude in the case of awareness in experience (Montague, 2022), it should be clear that awareness in the experience of seeing and touching the POE are different. These experiences convey different information—e.g. that the subject is in different relations to the POE—; and in this sense, the content of such information is different. The pure representationalist approach that I am defending in this paper is one that solves the delimitation problem in informational terms: conscious experiences convey information which would be expressed with a sentence along the lines of ‘I am in such-and-such a state’, and which should be read as portable and not global. There is no reason to think that this kind of information is conveyed by unconscious states as we are about to see.

  22. For a detailed disucussion of the relation between perspectival representation and IEM see Recanati (2007, 2012), cf. Musholt (2013).

  23. Rosenthal (2002) also notes that there is no distinctive quality associated with the self-awareness and he argues that we would expect there to be one if the form of awareness were not a thought. I fail to appreciate the force of his argument and I see no reason to postulate a different quality associated to something common to all experiences—see Sebastián (forthcoming) for further discussion.

  24. Musholt (2013) argues that self-consciousness requires conceptual capacities. However, she defines self-consciousness as the ability to think ‘I’ thoughts, which she thinks requires self-reference and, in turn, the deployment of concepts. This is compatible with the claim that the experience entails non-conceptual perspectival de se representation—as she acknowledges in a discussion of what Recanati calls ‘implicit representation’.

  25. Just as perspectival de hinc representation is not a matter of representing a particular location—see below.

  26. If Musholt (2013) is right and the capacity to form ‘I ’ thoughts requires self-reference, then there are also good reasons to think that these thoughts are not pespectival representations in so far as reference contributes to content, because the reference of your ‘I’ thought and mine are not the same.

  27. Some authors (Peacocke, 2014; Recanati, 2007, 2012) have indeed argued that precisely non-conceptual forms of de se representation, as those present in experience, ground the possession of the first-person concept. This concept can then be deployed in thought, independently of the instantiation of a non-conceptual de se representation.

  28. Block (2011), Byrne (1997), Neander (1998); cf. Rosenthal (2011) and Weisberg (2011a).

  29. INITIAL has to be endorsed by any HOR theory that is intended to be a theory of phenomenal consciousness–what Block (2011) calls an ‘ambitious’ HOR theory.

  30. See also Gurwitsch (1985) and Williford (2011). A similar argument based on memory is offered in the Buddhist-Abhidharma tradition (Chadha, 2017) and in Gurwitsch (1985), based on vehicles of representation. Cf. Howell and Thompson (2017).

References

  • Aristotle. (1906). De Sensu and De Memoria. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T., & Montague, M. (2011). Cognitive phenomenology. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, G. (1713/1998). Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonus. Oxford University Press.

  • Block, N. (1990). Inverted earth. Philosophical Perspectives, 4(4), 53–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2011). The higher order approach to consciousness is defunct. Analysis, 71(3), 419–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2014). Seeing-as in the light of vision science. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89(3), 560–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2016). The Anna Karenina principle and skepticism about unconscious perception. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 2, 452–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1874/1973). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. International Library of Philosophy.

  • Brogaard, B. (2011). Conscious vision for action versus unconscious vision for action? Cognitive Science, 35, 1076–1104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brook, A. (2008). Kant’s view of the mind and consciousness of self. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-mind/

  • Brown, R. (2015). The HOROR theory of phenomenal consciousness. Philosophical Studies, 172, 1783–1794.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (1997). Some like it hot: Consciousness and higher-order thoughts. Philosophical Studies, 86, 103–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2001). Intentionalism defended. Philosophical Review, 110(2), 199–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Dever, J. (2013). The inessential indexical: On the philosophical insignificance of perspective and the first person. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2000). Phenomenal consciousness: A naturalistic theory. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2003). Phenomenal consciousness: A naturalistic theory. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N. (1966). ‘he’: A study in the logic of self-consciousness. Ratio, 8, 130–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caston, V. (2002). Aristotle on consciousness. Mind, 111(444), 751–815.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chadha, M. (2017). Inner awareness is essential to consciousness: A buddhist-abhidharma perspective. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 8, 83–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2002). Does conceivability entail possibility? In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility (pp. 145–200). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2004). The representational character of experience. In B. Leiter (Ed.), The future for philosophy (pp. 153–181). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. M. (1981). The first person: An essay on reference and intentionality. University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coliva, A. (2006). Error through misidentification: Some varieties. The Journal of Philosophy, 103(8), 403–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1998). Descartes: Selected philosophical writings. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Bona, E. (2017). Towards a rich view of auditory experience. Philosophical Studies, 174, 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, A. (2006a). Appearance properties? Noûs, 40(3), 495–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan, A. (2006b). Secondary qualities and self-location. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 72(1), 97–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fichte, J. G. (1794/1982). Science of knowledge (2 ed.). Cambridge University Press.

  • Frege, G. (1984). Collected papers on mathematics, logic, and philosophy. Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1997). Thought. In M. Beaney (Ed.), The Frege reader (pp. 325–345). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • García-Carpintero, M. (2017). The philosophical significance of the de se. Inquiry, 60, 253–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gennaro, R. (2012). The consciousness paradox: Consciousness, concepts, and higher-order thoughts. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gennaro, R. J. (1996). Consciousness and self-consciousness: A defense of the higher-order thought theory of consciousness. John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Guillot, M. (2016). I me mine: On a confusion concerning subjective character. Review of Philosophy and PSychology, 8(1), 23–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch, A. (1985). Marginal consciousness. Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1990). The intrinsic quality of experience. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 31–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heck, R. G. (2002). Nonconceptual content and the space of reasons. Philosophical Review, 109, 483–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Tierson, J. (2002). The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howell, R. J., & Thompson, B. (2017). Phenomenally mine: In search of the subjective character of consciousness. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 8, 103–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739). A treatise of human nature. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1777/2008). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Oxford University Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1913/1998). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, first book. Kluwer.

  • Kriegel, U. (2002). Phenomenal content. Erkenntnis, 57, 175–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2003). Consciousness, higher-order content, and the individuation of vehicles. Synthese, 134(3), 477–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2007). Self-consciousness. In Internet Encyclopedia of philosophy.

  • Kriegel, U. (2009a). Self-representationalism and phenomenology. Philosophical Studies, 143, 357–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2009b). Subjective consciousness: A self-representational theory. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (1980). Naming and necessity. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (2011). The first person. In Philosophical troubles collected papers (Vol. 1). Oxford University Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1966). An argument for the identity theory. Journal of Philosophy, 63, 17–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Attitudes de dicto and de se. Philosophical Review, 88(4), 513–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1690/1994). An essay concerning human understanding. Prometheus Books.

  • Magidor, O. (2015). The myth of the de se. Philosophical Perspectives, 29(1), 249–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McClelland, T. (2020). Self-representational theories of consciousness. In U. Kriegel (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of consciousness. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, D., & Goodale, M. (1995). The visual brain in action. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, M. (2022). Rethinking the attitudes. In U. Kriegel (Ed.), Oxford studies in philosophy of mind (Vol. 2). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, D., & Salje, L. (2020). First-person thought. Analysis, 80(1), 148–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Musholt, K. (2013). Self-consciousness and nonconceptual content. Philosophical Studies, 163(3), 649–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1998). The division of phenomenal labor: A problem for representationalist theories of consciousness. Philosophical Perspectives, 12(S12), 411–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nida-Ruemelin, M. (2017). Self-awareness. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 8, 55–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ninan, D. (2016). What is the problem of de se attitudes? In M. García-Carpintero & S. Torre (Eds.), About oneself. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oonaill, D. (2019). Subjectivity and mineness. Erkenntnis, 84(2), 325–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1995). A study of concepts. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (2014). The mirror of the world: Subjects, consciousness, and self-consciousness. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs, 13, 3–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (2001). Knowledge, possibility and consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peters, M., Kentridge, R., Phillips, I., & Block, N. (2016). Does unconscious perception really exist? Continuing the assc20 debate. http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/2017.unc.symp.pdf

  • Phillips, I. (2016). Consciousness and criterion: On blocks case for unconscious seeing. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 93(2), 419–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2007). Perspectival thought: A plea for (moderate) relativism. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2012). Immunity to error through misidentification: What it is and where it comes from. In S. Prosser & F. Recanati (Eds.), Immunity to error through misidentification: New essays. Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. (2002). How many kinds of consciousness? Consciousness and Cognition, 11, 654–657.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. (2005). Consciousness and mind. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. (2011). Awareness and identification of self. In J. Liu & J. Perry (Eds.), Consciousness and the self: New essays. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. (2015). Qualities spaces and sensory modalities. In P. Coates & S. Coleman (Eds.), Phenomenal qualities: Sense, perception and consciousness. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (2011). Exaggerated reports. Reply to block. Analysis, 71, 431–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1910). Knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, pp. 108–128.

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1956). Being and nothingness. trans. Hazel E. Barnes. Philosophical Library.

  • Schear, J. K. (2009). Experience and self-consciousness. Philosophical Studies, 144, 95–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, S. (2018). The unity of perception: Content, consciousness, evidence. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sebastián, M. Á. (forthcoming). Being self-involved without thinking about it: Confusions, virtues and challenges of higher-order theories. In Weisberg J. (eds.) Qualitative Consciousness: Themes from the Philosophy of David Rosenthal. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Sebastián, M. Á. (2012). Experiential awareness: Do you prefer "it" to "me"? Philosophical Topics, 40(2), 155–177.

  • Sebastián, M. Á. (2018). Embodied appearance properties and subjectivity. Adaptive Behaviour, 26(5), 199–210.

  • Sebastián, M. Á. (2020). Perspectival self-consciousness and ego-dissolution: A theoretical analysis of (some) altered states of consciousness. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 1(I), 9.

  • Shea, N. (2018). Representation in cognitive science. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1996). Intersubjective/ intersubjective. In The first-person perspective and other essays (pp. 141–154). Cambridge University Press.

  • Shoemaker, S. S. (1968). Self-reference and self-awareness. The Journal of Philosophy, 65, 555–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2010). The contents of visual experience. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siewert, C. (1998). The significance of consciousness. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. (2020). Self-consciousness. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2020 ed.).

  • Sorabji, R. (2006). Self: Ancient and modern insights about individuality, life, and death. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1981). Propositions and indexical attitudes. In H. Parret (Ed.), On believing (pp. 316–332). Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Speaks, J. (2009). Transparency, intentionalism, and the nature of perceptual content. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79(3), 539–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. C. (2000). Comparing qualia across persons. Philosophical Topics, 26, 385–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. L. (2006). Self-awareness and self-knowledge. Psyche, 12(2), 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Torre, S. (2018). In defense of de se content. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 97(1), 172–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1997). Ten problems of consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2002). Consciousness, color, and content. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, J. (2011). Abusing the notion of what-it-is-like-ness: A response to block. Analysis, 71, 438–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, J. (2011). Misrepresenting consciousness. Philosophical studies, 154(3), 409–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williford, K. (2006). The self-representational structure of consciousness. In U. Kriegel & K. Williford (Eds.), Self-representational approaches to consciousness. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williford, K. (2011). Pre-reflective self-consciousness and the autobiographical ego. In J. Webber (Ed.), Reading Sartre: On phenomenology and existentialism. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williford, K. (2015). Representationalisms, subjective character and self-acquaintance. In T. Metzinger & J. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND. Mind Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). The Blue and Brown books. Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D., & Kriegel, U. (2016). For-me-ness: What it is and what it is not. In D. Dahlstrom, A. Elpidorou, & W. Hopp (Eds.), Philosophy of mind and phenomenology: Conceptual and empirical approaches. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For discussion and comments I am very grateful to Paloma Atencia-Linares, Enrique Aramendia, Marc Artiga, David Chalmers, Daniel Druecker, Santiago Echeverri, Manuel García- Carpintero, Anna Giustina, Ekain Garmendia, Marta Jorba, Uriah Kriegel, Andrew Lee, Martin Lin, Azenet Lopez, Ricardo Mena, Azul Santibañez, Elizabeth Schechter, Pepa Toribio, Josh Weisberg, Ken Williford, my students at the SCC-PhiLab and two anonymous referees. Ancestors of this paper were presented at the meeting of the ASSC22 in Krakow, the V ALFAn meeting in Villa de Leyva, the SSPP18 in San Antonio, and the workshop ``The subjectivity of experience: its nature and its role in cognition'' at UNAM. I am very grateful to the audience of these events for their helpful contribution and feedback. Financial support for this research was provided by DGAPA projects IN400520, IN400221 and IG400219.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Miguel Ángel Sebastián.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sebastián, M.Á. First-Person Perspective in Experience: Perspectival De Se Representation as an Explanation of the Delimitation Problem. Erkenn 89, 947–969 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-022-00564-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-022-00564-4

Navigation