Skip to main content
Log in

Epistemic Stances, Arguments and Intuitions

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The debate between scientific realists and anti-realists is now a classic debate in the Philosophy of Science. Van Fraassen (2002) has suggested that the positions that take part in the debate involve not only different doxastic attitudes regarding some propositions, but different epistemic stances, that is, different sets of commitments, values and epistemic strategies. The formulation of this debate in terms of epistemic stances and the voluntarist epistemology it motivates make it plausible to think of it as a deep disagreement. This kind of disagreements cannot be settled by reason alone because they lack the conditions that are necessary for arguments to work. I argue, however, that the attempts to use arguments can have an epistemic value in these contexts, as they can help reveal intuitions. I adopt the view on intuitions put forward by Chudnoff (2014), according to which they are mental states capable of motivating epistemic action. I claim that, while the attempt to utter an argument cannot convince an opponent of changing her mind, it can make her perform some epistemic actions and, thus, bring out some of her intuitions. To show how arguments can work in this way, I take as a study case one of the main realist arguments: the No Miracles Argument.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a general account of the debate, see Kukla (1998) and Saatsi (2018).

  2. I want to thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this objection: one frequent trait of empiricist is their resisting to let themselves be carried away by intuitions. In the case of the NMA, empiricists may acknowledge they have certain intuition regarding the need for an explanation of the success of scientific theories but still refuse to trust that intuition because they have reasons to refrain from inferring in accordance to it. Even if this is so, eliciting intuitions in the opponent might be helpful in a case of disagreement. Finding out about the existence of certain intuition gives the agent the opportunity to judge how valuable that intuition is for her epistemic life. The result might be the realization that she does rely on that intuition in many of her epistemic practices and, as a consequence, she is not the empiricist she thought she was.

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. 1957. Intention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Bealer, G. 1998. Intuition and the autonomy of philosophy. In Rethinking intuition: the psychology of intuition and its Role in Philosophical Inquiry, eds. M. De Paul, and W. Ramsey, 201–240. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J. 2015. The intellectual given. Mind 124: 707–760.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. 2017. Scientific Ontology. Integrating Naturalized Metaphysics and Voluntarist Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. 2004. Stance relativism: empiricism versus metaphysics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 35: 173–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chudnoff, E. 2014. The rational roles of intuition. eds. Intuitions, eds. Booth, A., and D. Rowbottom, 9–35. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chudnoff, E. 2011. What intuitions are like. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82 (3): 625–654. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2010.00463

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. 1984. Elbow room. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. 1986. Unnatural attitudes: Realist and Instrumentalist attachment to Science. Mind CXV (378): 149–179.

  • Fogelin, R. 1985. The logic of deep disagreements. Informal Logic 7 (1): 3–1.

  • Kukla, Andre. 1998. Studies in scientific realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M. P. 2010. Epistemic circularity and epistemic incommensurability. In Social Epistemology, eds. A. Millar, and D. Pritchard, 261–276. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. 1995. Pushmi-Pullyu Representations. Philosophical Perspectives 9: 185–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. 2020. El giro realista en filosofía de la ciencia. In La ciencia y el mundo inobservable. Discusiones contemporáneas en torno al realismo científico, eds. Borge, B. and Nélida Gentile, 49–96. Buenos Aires: Eudeba.

  • Psillos, S. 1999. Scientific realism. How Science Tracks Truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1975. Mathematics, Matter and Method. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J., ed. 2018. The Routledge Handbook of Scientific Realism. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. 2007. A Virtue Epistemology. In Apt belief and reflective knowledge, vol. I. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. 1980. The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. 2002. The empirical stance. Yale: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worral, J. 2011. The No Miracles Intuition and the No Miracles Argument. In Explanation, Prediction, and Confirmation. The Philosophy of Science in a European Perspective, eds. D. Dieks, W. Gonzalez, S. Hartmann, et al. vol. 2, 11–21. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

This study has received no funding.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dalila Serebrinsky.

Ethics declarations

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Conflict of Interest

I, Dalila Serebrinsky, declare I have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Serebrinsky, D. Epistemic Stances, Arguments and Intuitions. J Gen Philos Sci 55, 79–94 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-023-09643-8

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-023-09643-8

Keywords

Navigation