Aristotle and Modern Science

The relevance of Darwin's comment (above) to his friend William Ogle lies in the achievements of Darwin's two "gods." Linnaeus developed modern methods of classifying animals and plants (taxonomy) (Herbaria 2019). Cuvier extended Linnaeus's ideas by classifying organisms into phyla that included fossils as well as living species (Faria, 2010), work that was admired by Darwin (Gotthelf 1999).Footnote 1 When he compares Aristotle with Cuvier and Linnaeus, Darwin clearly considers Aristotle to have made a greater contribution to modern science and biology in particular. To elucidate that contribution as it continues today, this paper attempts to (1) identify more recent scientific publications about Aristotle’s works on biological phenomena, (2) discuss the major foci of those papers, and (3) demonstrate how Aristotle continues to contribute to current scientific thinking on biology.Footnote 2 The decision to focus on these scientific works does not deny the value of other, more philosophical papers that discuss the metaphysics of Aristotle’s biology, but rather it augments those papers by examining what is being written about a historical event in biology (that is, Aristotle’s writings) from a scientific perspective and for modern students of biology.

Darwin's comment about Aristotle was made in 1882. More recently, there has been a renewal of interest in what might (from a contemporary perspective) be called Aristotle’s biological writings in the last 50 years or so by two sets of authors with distinct motivations (Tipton 2006, 2014). First, there are biologists (some eminent) who have been impressed by the rigor of Aristotle’s observations and want to bring these to the attention of modern scientists; second, there are philosophers and classicists who seek to find out how Aristotle’s writings on biology fit into his other works on metaphysics, ethics, and physics.

Although Tipton (2006) claims that there has been renewed interest in Aristotle’s biology, he does not itemize that interest by listing and describing the papers published, any trends in frequency over time, or the foci of those papers. Such an examination of the published works on Aristotle’s biology has the potential to provide a sense of perspective to the history of biology in terms of these aspects and also to generate some hypotheses regarding the possible reasons why interest in Aristotle’s biology has been revived.

This paper is concerned with only the first group of publications mentioned above (that is, those directed towards readers of zoological papers, albeit from a historical perspective) in order to ascertain how Aristotle’s biology is being made relevant to twenty-first-century biologists and to students of the history of biology.Footnote 3 Such a focus is not patronizing on the scientific side; on the contrary, it deliberately reflects on the trend in the other areas concerned with Aristotelian studies: philosophy and classics. These other areas, rather than seeing Aristotle as a philosopher only, increasingly stress the enormous impact Aristotle’s biology has on the other topics that Aristotle writes about (ethics, physics, philosophy, etc.). Thus, there is a correlation detectable between the renewed interest in how Aristotle’s biological ideas contribute to modern science and the opening up of the other areas for a more science-focused discourse, whether it be Aristotle’s social and political writings (Horowitz 1976; Kullmann 1980), philosophical works (Gotthelf 2012; Tipton 2014), or linguistic studies (Laspia 2018).

While the influence that his work on biology had on Aristotle’s overall research program (when acknowledged) has, in previous decades, often been interpreted in a dichotomous pattern (as in the case of Aristotle’s understanding of gender, usually in a misogynistically-assumed interpretation; see Horowitz 1976), recent scholarship is more cautious and follows a more-encompassing pattern of explanation rather than quickly ideologizing its findings (for example, on Aristotelian gender views, see Mayhew 2004). Therefore, while not arguing that the renewed interest in Aristotle’s biology is only a matter relevant for modern biologists, we concentrate here on scientific papers strictu sensu because the influence and intensity of discussion of this work on the side of the sciences is still greater than in classics and philosophy.

From a cross-disciplinary perspective, this momentum of the relevance that Aristotle is currently regaining in modern science should continuously alert humanities scholars to the significance of Aristotle’s biological works for the overall assessment of his intellectual personality and life achievement. Although this primary focus upon the relevance of Aristotle’s biology for modern sciences might be interpreted as 'politicizing' his work in favor of scientists, that focus also highlights one legitimate, if present-focused, history of biology that demonstrates how Aristotle’s work bridges a gap of some 2300 years and remains relevant to twenty-first-century science (Horowitz 1976).

Literature Search Strategy

Five strategies were followed to identify recent research papers that were (1) focused upon the scientific relevance of Aristotle’s biology, (2) not concerned with philosophical aspects of his model of scientific inquiry, and (3) truly aimed at bringing the value of Aristotle’s biology to the attention of the modern reader in science and in the history of biology itself. First (as recommended in the findings reported by Martín-Martín et al. [2018]), a search was conducted in Google Scholar on May 3, 2020 using the descriptors “Aristotle,” “biology,” “animals,” and “modern science,” chosen after a search of citations used in ten papers that we had already identified and whose descriptors we then adopted.Footnote 4 This method produced about 37,000 results for the fifty years from 1970 to 2019, sorted by relevance.Footnote 5 Of these results, the first 500 peer-reviewed journal articles were selected and their abstracts read for relevant content.Footnote 6 Second, the reference lists of each paper were manually searched for relevant articles. Third, a citation search in Google Scholar for each of those articles (that is, subsequent papers that had referenced them) was also undertaken.Footnote 7 Fourth, the bibliography from the specialized 2014 text by Leroi (2014) about Aristotle’s biological research on Lesbos was examined. The comprehensive Oxford Handbook of Aristotle (Shields 2012) also provided additional sources. Finally, the search descriptors were entered into PubMed and Science Direct to identify any papers that did not appear in Google Scholar.Footnote 8

These five processes produced a total of thirty-eight papers for inclusion in this review. As such, the selection of papers is appropriately narrow. To tie these papers to Aristotle’s writing, quotes and page references are given (where possible) for examples, using the Work title, Book number, and Bekkeri line notation, which denotes the columns as a or b (first or second columns), page numbers, and line numbers (Bekkeri 1831).

Search Findings

Cursory Comments

Several papers make only brief or cursory comments upon Aristotle’s biology. For example, Grene (2000) notes the state of current scientific debate regarding Aristotle’s supposed genetics; de Magalhaes and Costa (2009) cite Aristotle’s descriptions of the diversity of lifespans observed in nature; Brussow (2009, p. 2263) reports that Aristotle’s books offer “careful descriptions, sharp reasoning, the beginning of experimentation and entertaining errors;” Auer et al. (2007) refer to Aristotle’s development of comparative anatomy via dissection of animals; and Autumn et al. (2014) remind us that Aristotle observed that the gecko “could run up and down a tree in any way, even with its head downwards” (Aristotle, History of Animals, IX, 614b 2–3). Föllinger (2012) comments on the use by Aristotle of “dialogical elements,” and many papers used Aristotle’s biology in an introductory manner, briefly mentioning his work and then passing on to a non-related discussion of more modern findings (see Sodergren et al. 2006) or a review of historical processes (see Carlos et al. 2019).

Analytic Process Papers

Some authors focus on the analytic processes used by Aristotle to classify animals and generally conclude that there is “a fairly consistent underlying classification in the zoological works of Aristotle” (von Lieven and Humar 2008, p. 227). Similarly, it is strongly argued by Grene (1972, p. 423) that Aristotle’s biology reminds us of the “many-levelled structure of biological systems” and, hence, the “inadequacy of a one-levelled atomism” that sometimes overtakes modern biology in the form of reductionism to physics and chemistry (Grene 1972, p. 395). In dealing with what he refers to as the "genus-as-matter/species-as-differentia" account of the genus-species relation found in the Metaphysics, Lennox (1980, p. 324) argues that Aristotle introduces the constructs of “the more and the less” to differentiate between different species within the same genus in Parts of Animals.Footnote 9 Lennox admits that this distinction would not stand against modern definitions of genus and species, although this opinion is not shared by all. Pellegrin, for example, argues that “the two terms seem to have, at least approximately, the significance of ‘genus’ and ‘species’ in the modern sense” (Pellegrin 1986, p. 76). In his discussion of the Triune Brain as described by Plato, Aristotle, and Erasistratus, Smith (2010) sets out each account of the three types of “soul” and shows that Aristotle was the only one of these three ancient philosophers to argue that the soul was within the body.Footnote 10 Corsilius and Gregoric present a model for resolving the apparent contradiction between Aristotle’s claims that “the soul is the efficient cause of animal motion” as well as “being the internal supporting-point necessary for animal motion” (Corsilius and Gregoric 2013, p. 52).

Although these papers focus upon more general aspects of Aristotle’s writing on biology, they are relevant to the papers on specific topics (described below) because they cover what might loosely be termed the scientific method as Aristotle was developing it. As such, they reflect his overall approach to (for example) general problems like speciation and classification. They also link Aristotle’s biological works to the rest of his writing.Footnote 11 However, the question addressed by this paper may be answered in more detail by reference to peer-reviewed publications about specific topics in Aristotle’s biology. Several key areas in which such papers have been written are summarized below to provide a flavor of the kind of writing about Aristotle’s biology that has occurred during the last fifty years of relevant scientific literature.

Specific Topics

Genetics

Although it has been suggested that Aristotle all but set down a model of gene-based inheritance (Delbrück 1971), that view is strongly challenged as overly simplistic and mechanistic and attributing to DNA a much more controlling role by “posit[ing] a decidedly un-Aristotelian genetic vitalism” (Vinci and Robert 2005, p. 221). One of the most influential ideas in modern biology is epigenetics, first coined by Waddington and defined as “derived from the Greek word epigenesis, which Aristotle used for the theory that development is brought about through a series of causal interactions between the various parts” (Waddington 1956, p. 10). While no argument is being made here that Aristotle was responsible for the entire modern concept of epigenetics, Waddington considered that the Parts of Animals contributed to the development of that concept.

Further comment on Aristotle’s contributions to genetics comes from Kullmann, who sets himself “to point out some striking examples which show that Aristotle's thoughts may yet play a remarkable role in contemporary scientific discussion” (Kullman 1991, p. 137). Although most of his paper concentrates on Aristotle’s overall contributions,Footnote 12 such as his (unintended) taxonomy,Footnote 13 Kullmann makes a case for Aristotle as a proto-geneticist, even arguing that Aristotle took this role in ways that were superior to Darwin’s modelFootnote 14 because Aristotle argued that (in Kullmann’s words) “the purposeful structure of a living being depends on the programme pre-existing in the blood of the parents” (Kullman 1991, p. 146).Footnote 15

Henry discusses the question, What are the causal mechanisms behind the transmission of biological form? (Henry 2006, p. 426). He argues that the answer lies in the Generation of Animals, Book 4, where Aristotle describes the phenomenon of inheritance.Footnote 16 Aristotle maintains that there are a set of “movements”Footnote 17 that transmit the parents’ form to their offspring and that these movements “exist in the semen; potentially from remoter ancestors but in a higher degree from whatever individual is nearer.”Footnote 18

Population Biology

The purview of population biology includes “age structure,” and Egerton (1975, p. 307) considers that “almost all” of Aristotle’s biology was relevant to this construct. Egerton also argues that Aristotle’s History of Animals encompasses age structure in great detail, and uses the examples of mammals and birds to illustrate how Aristotle does this.Footnote 19

On Animals and Humans

Perhaps due to his experiences as a child (Shields 2012),Footnote 20 Aristotle developed a good understanding of native wildlife, exotic species, and farmed animals (Grumett 2019), and he devoted quite a lot of time to describing the care of farm animals.Footnote 21 Because he considered that animals have a soul similar to humans, and that animals’ telos is to confer their attributes and products onto their owners (for example, a cow’s milk, a sheep’s wool, a chicken’s eggs), then “a stockperson’s primary role is to promote the good of the animals in their care, ensuring that their needs, wants and desires are satisfied.”Footnote 22Footnote 23 Aristotle gave many examples of how this may be accomplished.Footnote 24

Aristotle asserted that, if a hen bird has mated with a cock and is pregnant, then if “she be trodden by another cock, the whole brood of chicks turn out like the second cock.”Footnote 25 Although this claim was said to be “very astonishing,” it has been verified (Birkhead and Møller 1998), and Brock notes that this is “another case where Aristotle’s empirical observations of biology, though apparently bizarre, have been vindicated by modern science” (Brock 2004, p. 278).Footnote 26

The Brain

Gross (1995) describes how Aristotle broke from some of his predecessors such as Alcmaeon of Croton, Democritus, Anaxagoras, and Diogenes, to state that “the brain cannot be the cause of any sensations, seeing that it is itself as utterly without feeling as any of the excretions”Footnote 27 and that “it is the region of the heart that constitutes the sensory center.”Footnote 28 It has been argued that this error by Aristotle arose because of his lack of clinically-focused study and that “he never dissected a human” (Gross 1995, p. 249). Aristotle lived in an era when the budding scientific methodology did not include experimentation, which forbade him from engaging in the kind of clinically-focused research that Galen undertook six centuries later that described the function of the brain and the spinal cord (Galen 1962). However, Aristotle was active in establishing the Museum at Alexandria, where dissection was undertaken, leading to the accurate description of the human brain (Longrigg 1988).Footnote 29

Although it was published just before the search period (1970–2020), an earlier paper by Clarke and Stannard deserves mention because its authors present several arguments explaining why Aristotle reported that the brain occupied only the front of the head,Footnote 30, Footnote 31 such as Aristotle’s desire to “create a synthesis of Pre-socratic and Platonic knowledge” (Clarke and Stannard 1963, p. 132).Footnote 32, Footnote 33 Aristotle inaccurately described several human structures, including the cranial sutures, uterus, kidney, spleen, ribs, and heart, and “viewed biological phenomena from a philosophical standpoint,” with less attention to accuracy than is expected by biologists today (Clarke and Stannard 1963, p. 148).

Anatomy

Aristotle is considered by many as “the founder of comparative anatomy,” although much of his work was based upon animals (from which he generalized to humans) because he did not perform dissections of humans (Blits 1999, p. 59).Footnote 34 However, Malomo et al. describe Aristotle as having “laid the foundation of comparative anatomy and established embryology on a scientific foundation by his direct studies of the chick embryo” (Malomo et al. 2006, p. 100). These studies were detailed and undertaken by an ingenious methodFootnote 35 and influenced thinking in that field until well after the Renaissance.

Perhaps the strongest basis for the high opinion in which anatomists hold Aristotle is his focus upon function.Footnote 36 Thus Blits writes: “Form and function go together for Aristotle. Anatomy and physiology are integral components of the same science” (Blits 1999, p. 62). This position is amplified by Blits when she explains that Aristotle’s task “is to discover the principles of organization and function responsible for the various animal kinds and their relations,” which entailed Aristotle in defining the differences in form between animals and the underlying "causes" why those differences occur. Aristotle identified four causes: material, form, origin of motion (or efficient), and end (or final), and in doing so, provided a model of anatomy that went well beyond a simple description of parts, but also included the reasons for why those parts are as they are and how they might differ across species. This individual variety of animals’ form and function led Aristotle to state that “each and all will reveal to us something natural and something beautiful.”Footnote 37

In their historical article in Clinical Anatomy in 2007, Crivellato and Ribatti divert their discussion away from “many of his physiological concepts (that) turned out to be wrong” and instead focus on Aristotle’s development of a “precise topographical terminology” that cast the body into “a bipartite, symmetrical architecture,” including the front and back of the body, its top and what lay below, and its right and left sides (Crivellato and Ribatti 2007, pp. 477–479).Footnote 38 Crivellato and Ribatti’s message is clear: Aristotle set down the nomenclature for most body parts and then went on to provide detailed accounts of the anatomy of the heart, blood vessels, brain, respiratory system, digestive system, kidney and urinary tract, genitals, bones and joints, muscles, and sense organs. In doing so, “Aristotle’s contribution to the development of anatomy was enormous” (Crivellato and Ribatti 2007, p. 484), and he foreshadowed the basic principle of experimentation in modern science and developed an early the concept of an organ (organon) as an instrumental and functional part of the body (Crivellato and Ribatti 2007).Footnote 39 These ideas exerted “a sort of intellectual dictatorship on further generations of anatomists,” even to Renaissance thinkers (Crivellato and Ribatti 2007, p. 485) and William Harvey in the seventeenth century.Footnote 40 Aristotle’s ideas about ways of understanding nature, plus twelfth-century translations of the wider Greco-Arabic ancient science, have been recognized as one of the three major bases of the development of the scientific revolution during the last few centuries, along with universities and the emergence of theologian-natural philosophers (Grant 1997).

In terms of the heart, Shoja et al. (2008) remind us that Aristotle reported that it consists of three chambers.Footnote 41 In doing so, he omitted the right atrium, which he instead called a venous dilation (Shoja et al. 2008).Footnote 42 This error has been discussed at length and is attributed to the mystical tradition attached to the number three, which is probably in accordance with Plato's notion of the three corporeal faculties (mind, emotion, desire) (Lennox 2001; Van Praagh and Van Praagh 1983). Other modern scientific papers on Aristotle’s model of the heart include Shaw’s, who notes that Aristotle made “over one hundred references to cardiac anatomy and physiology” in the History of Animals and Parts of Animals and that his “main model for the heart is simple and entirely structural: the heart is a container.” (Shaw 1972, pp. 355, 385). Shaw argues that Aristotle’s model drifted away from a more modern understanding of the heart when he attempted to describe its physiology, perhaps because of the lack of adequate laboratory settings necessary to investigate the actual way the heart worked (Shaw 1972, p. 386).

In his defense against Francis Bacon’s sixteenth-century criticisms of Aristotle’s anatomical writing,Footnote 43 Cosans replicates Aristotle’s anatomical experiments by obtaining “anatomical material” from a Chicago meatpacking company (Cosans 1998, p. 311). This experience allowed him to understand the process used by Aristotle that “shows animals to consist of parts that are organized into wholes in virtue of dynamic forms” (Cosans 1998, p. 336). Cosans argues that, far from Bacon’s criticism, this kind of animal dissection “not only reveals the order within organisms but naturally led to Aristotle’s quest to understand the order amongst organisms” and thus contributed to the development of his more comprehensive philosophy (Cosans 1998, p. 336).

Movement

Frampton’s paper on the role of the heart in animal movement summarizes Aristotle’s explanation of movement as follows: “The general rule of locomotion is that there must be an unmoved mover, something that is moved, and an intermediate moved mover” (Frampton 1991, p. 310). Aristotle expanded upon this simplified model by identifying that movement is initiated by “thought and desire,”Footnote 44 and that there is “some one thing which moves” limbs, and that this is “the soul.”Footnote 45 Although apparently despite having observed that taste and touch, sight, hearing, and smell are “lodged as a rule in the head,” for Aristotle, the soul resided in the heart.Footnote 46

Particular Creatures

Fish and Marine Creatures

Tipton describes Aristotle as a philosophical biologist for whom the two disciplines were intermingled (Tipton 2006, p. 370). By focusing on two particular fish that Aristotle described (the kobios, which is the giant goby in modern terms; and the phucis, or modern intertidal benny), Tipton evaluates the accuracy of Aristotle’s descriptions of the habitat, diet, spawning, sexual dimorphism, and eggs of these fishes,Footnote 47 which are found near Lesbos, and does so by adopting the same methods as Aristotle did (by catching these fish with hook and line).Footnote 48 Tipton notes that his findings were mostly consistent with Aristotle’s descriptions of these two fish. However, he also notes that neither of these two fish was often eaten by Lesbos’ citizens or found in the fish markets there during Tipton’s visits to this place, suggesting that Aristotle did not completely rely on the services of information provided by fishermen but made his own observations (Tipton 2006, p. 379).

In a second paper, Tipton discusses Aristotle’s description of the feeding behavior of the red mullet (Mullus surmuletus), a much-fancied eating fish in Ancient Greece and still today (“in antiquity a great delicacy … and continues to be a highly-prized fish today”) (Tipton 2008, p. 166). Aristotle noted that this fish “burrows in the mud”Footnote 49 to stir up small animals, which it then eats, which Tipton observes to be correct. Tipton also confirms that, as Aristotle noted, after the red mullet “quits its haunt, the sargue (sea bream) settles down into the place and feeds on what is left behind.”Footnote 50

Aristotle also described the reproduction of the "dog fish," or shark,Footnote 51 and Bodson (1983a, b) examines the statement that Aristotle is claimed to have made about these creatures’ “ovoviviparity.” Aristotle is translated as saying that “dog-fish in general can extrude and take in again their young.” Still, Bodson argues that this is not Aristotle’s intended meaning and that the “again” is misplaced. That is, while the shark is ovoviviparous, the eggs are not expelled and then taken in again by the mother. Instead, Bodson suggests that the correct translation is: “The majority of dogfish females release the young [the embryos] and keep them inside [in the uterus]” (Bodson 1983a; b, p. 403). This translation allows Aristotle’s comment about these fish to be accurate. Bodson assigns this apparent, but not actual, error by Aristotle to misinterpretation by later readers who did not attempt to assess the scientific correctness of the data.

Buddington and Diamond (1986) focus upon Aristotle’s description of “the pyloric caeca in fish,” which are blind diverticula opening “high up about the stomach.”Footnote 52 Aristotle hypothesized these as “a sort of antechamber in which food may be stored up and undergo putrefaction and concoction.”Footnote 53 Buddington and Diamond (1986) test this hypothesis and find that, while these caeca do not store or putrefy food, they aid in concoction (that is, digestion).

Eleni Voultsiadou and her colleagues wrote several papers about Aristotle’s descriptions of marine creatures, not all of which are relevant to this discussion, but three are of particular interest here. First, Voultsiadou et al. (2007, p. 1763) focus on the sponges of the Mediterranean, confirming Aristotle’s comments about the diversity, nature, external morphology, symbiotic relationships, habitat, and value to humankind,Footnote 54 concluding that Aristotle’s descriptions are “more or less consistent with present scientific knowledge.” Second, her paper with Vafidis on marine invertebrate diversity in Aristotle’s biology reports on the 866 mentions he makes of marine invertebrates, including “85 current marine invertebrate taxa” (Voulsiadoun and Vafidis 2007, p. 103).Footnote 55 By constructing an annotated catalogue of all marine anhaima (invertebrates) appearing in Aristotle, Voutsiadou et al.’s work is comprehensive in its tabulation and description. They conclude that “All marine animal anhaima encountered in Aristotle’s zoological works are correlated with current marine invertebrate taxa” (Voutsiadou et al. 2007, p. 114). However, there are some differences in how Aristotle classifies some animals compared to current schemes.

The third relevant paper by Ganias et al. (2017) replicates Voultsiadou and Vafidis’ (2007) paper on marine invertebrates by focusing on 109 individual fish taxa, which the authors tabulate and relate to modern classifications. Ganias et al. (2017) make the point that Linneaus used Aristotle’s fish names to construct Latinized international scientific names, although several errors in translation from ancient Greek to Latin produced confusion. In addition to this correlation between Aristotle’s and modern classification of taxa, Ganias et al. (2017) also provide examples of Aristotle’s text on fish body structure and function,Footnote 56 reproduction and development,Footnote 57 behavior, ecology, migration, feeding, diseases, and how they were exploited.Footnote 58 Finally, Voultsiadou et al. (2017) reiterate their sentiments regarding the value of Aristotle’s classification schemes for the range of marine animals. They note that Aristotle also provided an account of their dispersion around the Mediterranean, including notes about water circulation patterns, bathymetry, and river sources. Aristotle also noted that fish migrated across the Mediterranean,Footnote 59 and suggests where they could most easily be caught.Footnote 60 Voultsiadou et al. (2017) conclude that Aristotle’s biological classification is familiar to modern marine biologists and that there are traces of his descriptions in current taxonomies.

Scorpions

Aristotle commented that “in Pharos and other places, the bite of the scorpion is not dangerous; elsewhere—in Scythia, for instance … the sting is fatal to man or beast.”Footnote 61 Fet et al. (2009) note that Aristotle’s comments of scorpion dispersion have hitherto been unnoticed, and they correct Aristotle’s geography, pointing out that there are indeed two Pharos, one that is a small island off the coast of Alexandria (where the scorpions were, and still are, toxic), and the other that is also an island (Hvar, in the Adriatic Sea) that is inhabited by non-toxic scorpions.

Elephants

Aristotle wrote about the elephant in several parts of the History of Animals, including its appetite,Footnote 62 diseases,Footnote 63 and use in war.Footnote 64 However, there is some discussion about where these elephants came from and how Aristotle knew about them. For example, Romm (1989) argues strenuously against the common ancient belief that Aristotle’s knowledge of elephants was based on information he received from Alexander’s eastern conquests and that the only elephant that Aristotle knew was from India. Further, Romm argues that, perhaps due to Aristotle's detailed knowledge about elephants, he most probably received that information from an elephant handler rather than first-hand. However, Bigwood (1993) responds to Romm’s (1989) assertions by arguing that Aristotle was indeed talking about the Indian elephant and seemed to have no knowledge of the African species. Further, Bigwood (1993) claims that Aristotle’s knowledge of India was sparse and that he probably gained his information about Indian elephants from other sources, such as Ctesias, Eudoxus of Cnidus, and Callisthenes (who accompanied Alexander's Asian expedition). Nevertheless, Bigwood (1993) and Romm (1989) agree that “Aristotle's information about the elephant, scattered throughout the Historia Animalium and other biological works, is not only extraordinarily detailed but in most cases accurate as well” (Romm 1989, p. 537).

Insects

Bodson (1983a, b) opens her discussion of Aristotle’s descriptions of insects by lamenting the relative lack of attention that most modern entomologists pay to Aristotle. Instead, she argues that modern entomology originated in ancient Greece and provides examples from Aristotle that include the sounds made by insects,Footnote 65 how they sleep,Footnote 66 hibernate,Footnote 67 mate,Footnote 68 and their reaction to being dissected.Footnote 69

Birds

In her paper addressed to comparative psychologists, Bodson (1996) provides a tabulated summary of sixteen aspects of bird breeding behavior, including forming pairs, nesting sites, courtship, egg laying, sitting period, hatching, and others. Bodson cross-references these aspects of bird breeding behavior across thirteen different species of birds, supported by twenty-two citations from Aristotle’s History of Animals.Footnote 70

Comment on the Selection of Topics by Modern Writers

Four aspects of the thirty-eight papers reviewed here are discussed below: their content, their publication outlet, the distribution of publications over the fifty-year period surveyed, and any trends in the topics studied in these publications. Table 1 presents a summary of those papers, grouped according to topic, and shows author(s), year published, and the source of material from Aristotle used in each paper.

It is apparent from Table 1 that papers were published on a range of topics, and that the most attention was shown to Aristotle’s descriptions of various creatures (13 papers), followed by those on his writing about anatomy (6 papers, or 7 papers if the writing on the brain is included). The paper by Clarke et al. (1963) was included because it gave a strong introduction to this work by Aristotle, even though it did not fall within the fifty-year period. Of the papers on creatures, by far the major focus is on Aristotle’s descriptions of fish and other sea creatures, although the contributions of Voultsiadou and her colleagues comprise the major portion of those papers. For instance, Voultsiadou and Vafidis (2007) list the 85 current marine invertebrate taxa that Aristotle accurately described, and Ganias et al. (2017) name 109 individual fish taxa mentioned by Aristotle. Not surprisingly, as well as the specific content (that is, animals, anatomy, etc.) of Aristotle’s work that these papers focus upon, the authors also share an admiration for Aristotle’s detailed and accurate observations. In dealing with the pointed criticisms made by Francis Bacon about Aristotle, Cosans (1998) does not hesitate to challenge Bacon’s comments by undertaking the same dissections with animals that Aristotle described.

Second, the selection of publication outlets also provides an insight into the goals of these authors who comment on Aristotle’s relevance to modern science. As shown in Table 1, the journals in which these papers appear cover a wide range of scientific fields. While there are four papers from the Journal of the History of Biology, there are also six papers from journals that include papers on the history of science (such as History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, Journal of the History of Ideas, Journal of the History of Medicine and Allied Sciences, Archives of Natural History, and American Journal of Philology). Similarly, classics journals have also published some of these papers on Aristotle’s observations of animals (Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, Acta Classica, Arethusa, The Classical Outlook, and Phronesis). However, there are twenty publications in scientific journals that do not purport to discuss historical issues (Journal of Evolutionary Biology, Perspectives on Science, Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, The Neuroscientist, Clinical Anatomy, Fish and Fisheries, Mediterranean Marine Science, and others of the same genre). From a slightly different perspective, twenty-eight (or 73.7%) of the papers appear in science journals or journals devoted to the history of science, but only ten (or 26.3%) are published in history or classics journals. These data suggest that almost three-quarters of this selection of modern literature about Aristotle’s observation of animals was written for the specific consumption of scientists, while the remaining one-quarter could be intended to interest historians or classicists. On the basis that all these papers were peer-reviewed, it may be claimed that there is a reasonably active interest shown by scientists, historians, and classicists in Aristotle’s observations of animals.

Table 1 Summary details for peer-reviewed papers on Aristotle’s biology, 1970–2019, that report on mainstream biological topics

Third, it is also of interest to note the distribution over time of the papers identified for review. Figure 1 depicts that distribution on a decade-by-decade basis (excluding Clarke et al. 1963) and shows a fairly even appearance rate per decade except for the period from 2000 to 2009. No obvious explanation is forthcoming for this finding, and perusal of Table 1 indicates that none of the various topic areas is particularly present in this ten-year period; those seventeen papers that were published between 2000 and 2009 included comments on Aristotle’s worth as a scientist, his animal classification systems, genetics, animal care, anatomy, fish, and scorpions.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Publications per decade, 1970 to 2019

Finally, when the content and year are combined to detect any observable trends over time, as shown in Table 2, there is no obvious pattern according to the subjects of papers published over the five decades. Researchers appear to be consistently interested in Aristotle’s method of classifying species over this period, with papers describing this in the 1970s, 1980s, and 2000s. Similarly, anatomy retains its place in papers published in the 1970s, 1990s, and 2000s; and specific animals receive attention in each decade from the 1970s to the present. There are proportionally more papers on these topics according to the total number of publications in specific decades (the 2000s has many more of everything than the other decades), but no clear change in focus.

Table 2 Publication focus by decade published

Conclusion

While the relative status of Aristotle as a natural scientist vis-a-vis his traditional image as a philosopher has only relatively recently started to be debated in classical studies, his reception in modern science has steadily grown over the last five decades. Based on the papers reviewed here, plus the brief summary of their content, outlets, and timing of publication over a fifty-year period, it is argued that Aristotle’s observations of animals not only continue to excite interest in modern scientists but remain of relevance to modern biology and contribute to the general history of biology itself. Evidence of this claim is the extent to which highly-competitive publication space in mainstream historical, classics, and scientific journals is being given to papers that highlight Aristotle’s exact and voluminous output in what is now termed “biology,” his ability to demonstrate the principles of precise observation and hypothesis-formulation, and his fluid and informative communication with his audience. The fact that each of the 38 papers described herein was peer-reviewed by other researchers in the general fields of history, classics, and biology, and judged by them to be not only of relevance but also of sufficient scientific standing as indicators of an ancient but enormously comprehensive and still informative piece of work, further affirms the relevance of Aristotle’s work to modern science. As a statement about the ongoing history of biology itself, these papers also argue for the worth of an accumulative set of observations and deductions in the general field of biology, even from very long ago.