Skip to main content
Log in

Discussion Note: Selim Berker’s Combinatorial Argument against Practical Reasons for Belief

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In a recent paper, Selim Berker (Analytic Philosophy, 59, 427-470, 2018) develops an abductive argument against practical reasons for belief that exploits an alleged difference between epistemic and practical reasons. According to Berker, epistemic reasons for belief balance to suspension. If I have equally strong epistemic reasons to believe and disbelieve some proposition, I lack sufficient reason either to believe or disbelieve it. Rather, I have decisive reason to suspend judgment. In contrast, practical reasons balance to permission. If I have equally strong practical reasons to φ or ψ (and there are no other reasons on the scene), I have sufficient reason to do either. Given this difference, Berker argues that defenders of practical reasons for belief cannot offer a plausible explanation of how practical and epistemic reasons interact in order to yield all-things-considered normative verdicts. In this essay, I defend a non-interactionist “pure” form of pragmatism against Berker’s objection. I outline a pure pragmatist theory, recapitulate why Berker thinks it also falls prey to his objection, and explain why the objection fails to undermine pure pragmatism. Finally, I consider an additional reason Berker’s argument might seem persuasive and show that it depends on conflating Berker’s objection and a separate challenge to pure pragmatism. Once these distinct challenges are disambiguated, it is easier to see why Berker’s objection is not a significant concern for pure pragmatists.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Throughout, I adopt Berker’s reasons-based framework according to which “X’s φ-ing has a normative status such as the following: X has decisive reason to φ (i.e., φ-ing is required by the overall balance of X’s reasons); X has sufficient reason to φ (i.e., φ-ing is permitted by the overall balance of X’s reasons); X lacks sufficient reason to φ (i.e., φ-ing is forbidden by the overall balance of X’s reasons)” (427).

  2. For discussions of how similar examples of self-fulfilling beliefs pose challenges to the view that epistemic reasons for belief necessarily balance to suspension, see Reisner (2007, 2013, 2018), Drake (2017), and Raleigh (2017). Thanks to an anonymous referee for clarifying this point.

  3. See, e.g., Feldman (2000).

  4. Pure pragmatism is endorsed by Stich (1990), and a similar view to Stich’s can be found in Rinard (2015, 2017). McCormick (2015), Papineau (2013), and Maguire and Woods (in press) all develop novel versions of pure pragmatism. See Reisner (2008 and 2009) for helpful discussion. Thanks to an anonymous referee for suggesting some of the relevant literature.

  5. For versions of this analogy, see Schroeder (2010), Howard (2016), Leary (2017), Côté-Bouchard (2016), and Maguire and Woods (in press).

  6. As McCormick aptly puts a similar point, “having true beliefs and knowledge help us achieve our goals, flourish, and be excellent human beings. In general, forming and maintaining beliefs in accordance with evidential norms that produce knowledge is the best way to achieve these goals.” (2015: 48).

  7. In his 2008 paper, Reisner notes that a similar proposal to the one I outline below is compatible both with pure and interactionist forms of pragmatism, though he doesn’t endorse either. See pg. 27. For the reasons I give below, I think this approach is more plausible given a commitment to pure pragmatism than it would be if one accepted the existence of epistemic reasons and an independent source of normativity for belief.

  8. See Dancy (2004). He calls these considerations “disablers.” See also Schroeder (2007 and 2011) for discussion. According to Schroeder, undercutting defeat is a limiting case of attenuation, which occurs when one consideration makes another a much weaker reason than it otherwise would be. Nothing in my argument here turns on whether the practical reason to avoid believing p completely undercuts the practical reason to respect the evidence concerning p, or merely attenuates it below some threshold beneath which it is no longer relevant.

  9. See pg. 444. Since Berker presents this objection in the context of discussing Reisner’s proposal, his imagined scenario involves equally balanced “epistemic reasons.” In applying the criticism to pure pragmatism, I describe the scenario as involving equally balanced “evidence.”

  10. Again, in order to make the criticism applicable to pure pragmatism, assume that “no other reasons that bear on the matter” means “no other reasons that bear on the matter other than a standing practical reason to respect the evidence.”

  11. The claim that practical considerations cannot be reasons for belief because we are incapable of reasoning from non-evidential considerations to belief is a prominent objection to pragmatism, but it is importantly different from Berker’s objection. Versions of this argument can be found in Shah (2006), Kelly (2002), Kolodny (2005), Raz (2011), and Persson (2007). Similar views may be inferred from Parfit (2011) and Gibbard (1990).

  12. For some attempts to respond to this sort of objection, see: Rinard (2015, 2017, 2018) McCormick (2015), Reisner (2009), Crawford (2019), Leary (2017), Howard (2016), and Maguire and Woods (in press).

References

  • Berker, S. (2018). A combinatorial argument against practical reasons for belief. Analytic Philosophy. 59: 427–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Côté-Bouchard, C. (2016). Can the aim of belief ground epistemic normativity? Philosophical Studies 173(12): 3181–3198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crawford, L. (2019). Believing the best: On doxastic partiality in friendship. Synthese 196(4): 1575–1593.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (2004). Ethics without principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Drake, J. (2017). Doxastic permissiveness and the promise of truth. Synthese, 194(12), 4897–4912.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (2000). The ethics of belief. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 60(3), 667–695.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings: a theory of normative judgment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Howard, C. (2016). Transparency and the ethics of belief. Philosophical Studies, 173(5), 1191–1201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2002). The rationality of belief and some other propositional attitudes. Philosophical Studies 110(2): 163–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny, N. (2005). Why be rational? Mind, 114, 509–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leary, S. (2017). In defense of practical reasons for belief. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 95(3), 529–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maguire, B. and Woods, J. (in press). “The Game of Belief.” Philosophical Review.

  • McCormick, M. (2015). Believing against the evidence: Agency and the ethics of belief. Routledge.

  • Papineau, D. (2013). There are no norms of belief. In Timothy Chan (ed.), The Aim of Belief. Oxford University Press: 64–79, There Are No Norms of Belief.

  • Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Persson, I. (2007). Primary and secondary reasons. Hommage à Wlodek: Philosophical Papers Dedicated to Wlodek Rabinowicz. eds. Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen, Bjorn Petersson, Jonas Joseffson, and Dan Egonsson. http://www.fil.lu.se/hommageawlodek. Accessed 2 June 2019.

  • Raleigh, T. (2017). Another Argument Against Uniqueness. The Philosophical Quarterly, 67(267), 327–346.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (2011). From normativity to responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reisner, A. (2007). Evidentialism and the numbers game. Theoria, 73(4), 304–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reisner, A. (2008). Weighing pragmatic and evidential reasons for belief. Philosophical Studies, 138(1), 17–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reisner, A. (2009). The possibility of pragmatic reasons for belief and the Wrong Kind of Reasons Problem. Philosophical Studies 145(2): 257–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reisner, A. (2013). Leaps of knowledge. In Timothy Chan (ed.), The aim of belief. Oxford University Press: 167–183.

  • Reisner, A. (2018). Pragmatic reasons for belief. In Daniel star (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity. Oxford University Press.

  • Rinard, S. (2015). Against the new Evidentialists. Philosophical Issues, 25(1), 208–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rinard, S. (2017). No exception for belief. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 94(1), 121–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rinard, S. (2018). Believing for practical reasons. Noûs. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2010). Value and the right kind of reason in Oxford studies in Metaethics 5: 25–55.

  • Schroeder, M. (2007). Slaves of the passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Schroeder, M. (2011). Holism, weight, and undercutting. Noûs, 45(2), 328–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shah, N. (2006). A new argument for Evidentialism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 56(225), 481–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1990). The fragmentation of reason: Preface to a pragmatic theory of cognitive evaluation. MIT Press.

Download references

Acknowledgements

Special thanks to Daniel Star and two anonymous referees at Philosophia for written comments that greatly improved the paper. I would also like to thank David DiDomenico, Becca Fink, Walter Hopp, Berislav Marušić, Miriam McCormick, Susanna Rinard, Sebastian Schmidt, Jack Woods, and especiallySelim Berker for helpful conversations.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adam Shmidt.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Shmidt, A. Discussion Note: Selim Berker’s Combinatorial Argument against Practical Reasons for Belief. Philosophia 48, 763–776 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-019-00103-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-019-00103-6

Keywords

Navigation